首页 > 最新文献

The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism最新文献

英文 中文
Index 指数
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.034
{"title":"Index","authors":"","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.034","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.034","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"35 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131458671","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Legal Positivism of H. L. A. Hart 哈特的法律实证主义
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.013
Matthew H Kramer
{"title":"The Legal Positivism of H. L. A. Hart","authors":"Matthew H Kramer","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.013","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.013","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"34 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131211187","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Positivism, Realism and Sources of Law 实证主义、现实主义与法律渊源
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.002
L. Green
{"title":"Positivism, Realism and Sources of Law","authors":"L. Green","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.002","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"19 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132583846","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Semantic Thesis in Legal Positivism 法律实证主义的语义命题
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3878279
Michael S. Green
For positivists, law ultimately depends solely on social facts about a community’s legal practices. This is a metaphysical thesis about the nature of law. But most positivists — including Scott Shapiro, Joseph Raz, and H.L.A. Hart — reject a semantic thesis, according to which statements about the law are solely descriptions of those social facts. The semantic thesis, they argue, is unable to account for those legal statements, commonly using normative language, that Hart calls “internal.” Some argue that internal legal statements are not (or not solely) descriptions of social facts because they express one’s acceptance of conformity with legal practices. In response to difficulties with this expressivist approach (including the so-called Frege-Geach problem), Raz offers a detailed alternative, according to which they describe moral facts that would exist from the legal point of view, that is, on the assumption that there are always moral reasons for conformity to legal practices. Raz’s approach, although avoiding the Frege-Geach problem, has its own difficulties. I argue for a much simpler reason for positivists to reject the semantic thesis. Most positivists are assignment positivists, not reduction positivists. Reduction positivists believe that a legal system and its laws are reducible to social facts about a community’s legal practices, the way a traffic jam is reducible to facts about its constituent cars. For assignment positivists, by contrast, a legal system and its laws are abstract objects, not social entities. But these philosophers remain positivist, for they think that the grounds for assigning certain of these objects to a community — such that they are the legal system and laws of that community — are ultimately solely social facts about the community’s legal practices. Consider the following analogy. Many philosophers consider a language to be an abstract object. The fact that “Le chat est sur le tapis” means that the cat is on the mat in French is not a social fact concerning French linguistic practices but is instead a necessary truth concerning the abstract object that is French. Nevertheless, these philosophers believe that the grounds for assigning that abstract object to the French community are solely social facts about that community. It is a contingent fact that the French speak French rather than, say, Esperanto. That they speak French depends solely upon social facts concerning French linguistic practices. By analogy, assignment positivists should reject the semantic thesis for the simple reason that internal legal statements describe necessary truths about the abstract objects that are a legal system and its laws. This approach, which was probably the one adopted by Hart himself, overcomes the problems with expressivism — in particular, the Frege-Geach problem — while avoiding the difficulties with Raz’s approach.
对于实证主义者来说,法律最终完全取决于一个社区法律实践的社会事实。这是一篇关于法律本质的形而上学论文。但大多数实证主义者——包括斯科特·夏皮罗、约瑟夫·拉兹和H.L.A.哈特——都反对语义命题,即关于法律的陈述仅仅是对那些社会事实的描述。他们认为,语义命题无法解释那些通常使用规范语言的法律陈述,哈特称之为“内部”。一些人认为,内部法律陈述不是(或不仅仅是)对社会事实的描述,因为它们表达了一个人对符合法律惯例的接受。为了回应这种表现主义方法的困难(包括所谓的Frege-Geach问题),Raz提供了一个详细的替代方案,根据该方案,他们描述了从法律角度存在的道德事实,也就是说,假设总是存在符合法律实践的道德原因。拉兹的方法虽然避免了Frege-Geach问题,但也有其自身的困难。我认为实证主义者拒绝语义命题的理由要简单得多。大多数实证主义者是分配实证主义者,而不是还原实证主义者。还原实证主义者认为,一个法律体系及其法律可以还原为一个社区法律实践的社会事实,就像交通堵塞可以还原为其组成车辆的事实一样。相反,对于分配实证主义者来说,法律体系及其法律是抽象的对象,而不是社会实体。但这些哲学家仍然是实证主义者,因为他们认为,将某些对象分配给一个社区的依据——比如它们是该社区的法律体系和法律——最终仅仅是关于该社区法律实践的社会事实。考虑下面的类比。许多哲学家认为语言是一种抽象的东西。" Le chat est sur Le tapis "在法语中意思是猫在垫子上,这一事实不是关于法语语言实践的社会事实,而是关于法语这个抽象对象的必然真理。然而,这些哲学家认为,将这个抽象的对象分配给法国社会的理由仅仅是关于这个社会的社会事实。法国人说法语而不说世界语,这是一个偶然的事实。他们说法语完全取决于与法语语言实践有关的社会事实。通过类比,赋值实证主义者应该拒绝语义命题,理由很简单,即内部法律陈述描述了作为法律体系及其法律的抽象对象的必要真理。这种方法,很可能是哈特自己采用的方法,克服了表现主义的问题——特别是弗雷格-吉奇问题——同时避免了拉兹方法的困难。
{"title":"The Semantic Thesis in Legal Positivism","authors":"Michael S. Green","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3878279","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3878279","url":null,"abstract":"For positivists, law ultimately depends solely on social facts about a community’s legal practices. This is a metaphysical thesis about the nature of law. But most positivists — including Scott Shapiro, Joseph Raz, and H.L.A. Hart — reject a semantic thesis, according to which statements about the law are solely descriptions of those social facts. The semantic thesis, they argue, is unable to account for those legal statements, commonly using normative language, that Hart calls “internal.” \u0000 \u0000Some argue that internal legal statements are not (or not solely) descriptions of social facts because they express one’s acceptance of conformity with legal practices. In response to difficulties with this expressivist approach (including the so-called Frege-Geach problem), Raz offers a detailed alternative, according to which they describe moral facts that would exist from the legal point of view, that is, on the assumption that there are always moral reasons for conformity to legal practices. Raz’s approach, although avoiding the Frege-Geach problem, has its own difficulties. \u0000 \u0000I argue for a much simpler reason for positivists to reject the semantic thesis. Most positivists are assignment positivists, not reduction positivists. Reduction positivists believe that a legal system and its laws are reducible to social facts about a community’s legal practices, the way a traffic jam is reducible to facts about its constituent cars. For assignment positivists, by contrast, a legal system and its laws are abstract objects, not social entities. But these philosophers remain positivist, for they think that the grounds for assigning certain of these objects to a community — such that they are the legal system and laws of that community — are ultimately solely social facts about the community’s legal practices. \u0000 \u0000Consider the following analogy. Many philosophers consider a language to be an abstract object. The fact that “Le chat est sur le tapis” means that the cat is on the mat in French is not a social fact concerning French linguistic practices but is instead a necessary truth concerning the abstract object that is French. Nevertheless, these philosophers believe that the grounds for assigning that abstract object to the French community are solely social facts about that community. It is a contingent fact that the French speak French rather than, say, Esperanto. That they speak French depends solely upon social facts concerning French linguistic practices. \u0000 \u0000By analogy, assignment positivists should reject the semantic thesis for the simple reason that internal legal statements describe necessary truths about the abstract objects that are a legal system and its laws. This approach, which was probably the one adopted by Hart himself, overcomes the problems with expressivism — in particular, the Frege-Geach problem — while avoiding the difficulties with Raz’s approach.","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"55 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130129945","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Disruptive Implications of Legal Positivism’s Social Efficacy Thesis 法律实证主义社会效能论的颠覆意义
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.022
B. Tamanaha
{"title":"Disruptive Implications of Legal Positivism’s Social Efficacy Thesis","authors":"B. Tamanaha","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.022","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.022","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"32 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128389942","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Social-Practice Legal Positivism and the Normativity Thesis 社会实践法律实证主义与规范性命题
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.017
Stefano Bertea
{"title":"Social-Practice Legal Positivism and the Normativity Thesis","authors":"Stefano Bertea","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.017","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.017","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"124592649","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
John Austin 约翰·奥斯丁
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.010
M. Lobban
{"title":"John Austin","authors":"M. Lobban","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.010","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"73 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133761045","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
The Normativity of Law 法律的规范性
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.025
B. Bix
{"title":"The Normativity of Law","authors":"B. Bix","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.025","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.025","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"9 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131603352","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Jeremy Bentham and the Origins of Legal Positivism 边沁与法律实证主义的起源
Pub Date : 2021-01-31 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.009
P. Schofield
H. L. A. Hart is generally recognised as the most influential twentiethcentury exponent of the doctrine of legal positivism. According to Hart, Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), the philosopher and reformer, ‘opened the long positivist tradition in English jurisprudence’. Stephen Perry points out that Hart’s legal positivism contains two doctrines, namely substantive and methodological legal positivism, though Hart himself did not explicitly distinguish them. The former consists in the claim that there is no necessary connection between morality and the content of law and the latter in the claim that there is no necessary connection between morality and legal theory. Hart in effect attributed both doctrines to Benthamwhen referring to ‘Bentham’s sharp severance . . . between law as it is and law as it ought to be and his insistence that the foundations of a legal system are properly described in the morally neutral terms of a general habit of obedience’. Bentham’s view that there was no necessary connection between law and morality (his ‘sharp severance . . . between law as it is and law as it ought to be’) and his description of a legal system in ‘morally neutral terms’ were equivalent to Hart’s substantive and methodological doctrines respectively. Hart, moreover, indicated that Bentham’s methodological legal positivism had been subservient to his substantive legal positivism: ‘[Bentham] insisted on a precise, morally neutral vocabulary for use in the discussion of law and politics as part of a larger concern to sharpen men’s awareness . . . of the distinction between what is and what ought to be.’
哈特通常被认为是二十世纪最有影响力的法律实证主义学说的倡导者。根据哈特的说法,哲学家和改革家杰里米·边沁(1748-1832)“在英国法理学中开启了长期的实证主义传统”。斯蒂芬·佩里指出,哈特的法律实证主义包含两种学说,即实体法实证主义和方法论法实证主义,但哈特本人并没有明确区分这两种学说。前者主张道德与法律内容之间没有必然的联系,后者主张道德与法律理论之间没有必然的联系。当提到“边沁的尖锐分离”时,哈特实际上把这两种学说都归因于边沁。在现实的法律和应该的法律之间以及他坚持认为法律体系的基础应该被恰当地描述为道德中立的一般服从习惯。边沁认为法律和道德之间没有必然的联系(他的“尖锐的分离”)。在法律的现状和法律的应有状态之间”),以及他对法律体系的“道德中立”的描述,分别相当于哈特的实体论和方法论学说。此外,哈特指出,边沁的方法论法律实证主义一直屈从于他的实体法实证主义:“(边沁)坚持使用一种精确的、道德中立的词汇来讨论法律和政治,作为提高人们意识的更大关注的一部分……”是什么和应该是什么之间的区别
{"title":"Jeremy Bentham and the Origins of Legal Positivism","authors":"P. Schofield","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.009","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.009","url":null,"abstract":"H. L. A. Hart is generally recognised as the most influential twentiethcentury exponent of the doctrine of legal positivism. According to Hart, Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), the philosopher and reformer, ‘opened the long positivist tradition in English jurisprudence’. Stephen Perry points out that Hart’s legal positivism contains two doctrines, namely substantive and methodological legal positivism, though Hart himself did not explicitly distinguish them. The former consists in the claim that there is no necessary connection between morality and the content of law and the latter in the claim that there is no necessary connection between morality and legal theory. Hart in effect attributed both doctrines to Benthamwhen referring to ‘Bentham’s sharp severance . . . between law as it is and law as it ought to be and his insistence that the foundations of a legal system are properly described in the morally neutral terms of a general habit of obedience’. Bentham’s view that there was no necessary connection between law and morality (his ‘sharp severance . . . between law as it is and law as it ought to be’) and his description of a legal system in ‘morally neutral terms’ were equivalent to Hart’s substantive and methodological doctrines respectively. Hart, moreover, indicated that Bentham’s methodological legal positivism had been subservient to his substantive legal positivism: ‘[Bentham] insisted on a precise, morally neutral vocabulary for use in the discussion of law and politics as part of a larger concern to sharpen men’s awareness . . . of the distinction between what is and what ought to be.’","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125868389","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Tracing Finnis’s Criticism of Hart’s Internal Point of View: Instability and the ‘Point’ of Human Action in Law 追溯芬尼斯对哈特“内在观点”的批判:不稳定性与法律中人行为的“观点”
Pub Date : 2020-01-20 DOI: 10.1017/9781108636377.030
Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco
Finnis, tells us, that the participant of the legal practice, e.g. the citizen, the judge, the lawyer, are engaged with the law and are interested in distinguishing between a good and a not so good norm, between a just directive and unjust directive, between a rational court-decision and a non-rational court decision. Hart’s internal point of view refuses to make further distinctions between the peripheral and central cases of law and this brings instability to the concept. Hart’s internal point of view as unstable can be traced to a more fundamental criticism, i.e. Hart’s internal point of view cannot be used to understand the point of human actions and therefore we cannot rely on Hart’s internal point of view to identify significance differences that any actor in the field can make. In the ‘methodology’ literature, this argument on instability is overlooked and its premises has not been carefully examined. In this chapter, I will try to show that the idea that the internal point of view is unstable is both key to understand the limits of Hart’s legal theory and shed further light on the view that law should be conceived in terms of a central or focal case.
芬尼斯告诉我们,法律实践的参与者,例如公民、法官、律师,都与法律有关,并且对区分好的和不好的规范、公正的指令和不公正的指令、合理的法院判决和非理性的法院判决感兴趣。哈特的内部观点拒绝进一步区分法律的外围和中心案例,这给这个概念带来了不稳定性。哈特的内部观点是不稳定的,这可以追溯到一个更根本的批评,即哈特的内部观点不能用来理解人类行为的观点,因此我们不能依靠哈特的内部观点来识别领域中任何行动者都可以做出的重大差异。在“方法论”文献中,这种关于不稳定性的论点被忽视了,其前提也没有得到仔细研究。在本章中,我将试图表明,内部观点是不稳定的这一观点,既是理解哈特法律理论局限性的关键,也是进一步阐明法律应该根据一个中心或焦点案例来构想的观点。
{"title":"Tracing Finnis’s Criticism of Hart’s Internal Point of View: Instability and the ‘Point’ of Human Action in Law","authors":"Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco","doi":"10.1017/9781108636377.030","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108636377.030","url":null,"abstract":"Finnis, tells us, that the participant of the legal practice, e.g. the citizen, the judge, the lawyer, are engaged with the law and are interested in distinguishing between a good and a not so good norm, between a just directive and unjust directive, between a rational court-decision and a non-rational court decision. Hart’s internal point of view refuses to make further distinctions between the peripheral and central cases of law and this brings instability to the concept. Hart’s internal point of view as unstable can be traced to a more fundamental criticism, i.e. Hart’s internal point of view cannot be used to understand the point of human actions and therefore we cannot rely on Hart’s internal point of view to identify significance differences that any actor in the field can make. In the ‘methodology’ literature, this argument on instability is overlooked and its premises has not been carefully examined. In this chapter, I will try to show that the idea that the internal point of view is unstable is both key to understand the limits of Hart’s legal theory and shed further light on the view that law should be conceived in terms of a central or focal case.","PeriodicalId":131205,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism","volume":"199 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-01-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115014704","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1