首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Clinical Ethics最新文献

英文 中文
Should Providers Ask Family Members What They Want When Establishing Surrogate Decision-Making? 在确立代理决策时,医疗服务提供者是否应该询问家庭成员他们想要什么?
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/730874
Edmund G Howe

AbstractIn this piece I discuss optimal approaches that providers may take when pursuing surrogate decision-making. A potential critical problem here is some providers' approach differing from that of others. To the extent that this occurs, the results may be arbitrary, and the harm from this may be profound since this may affect, of course, even whether some of these patients will live or die. One factor possibly resulting in these differences is the moral weight providers place on what family members want when these outcomes differ from what they think patients would want. Providers now most commonly place greatest moral weight on following what patients would want to maximally respect their autonomy, but this view may clash with the view of others who see autonomy as more relational and thus based on prior and present social relations with others. Giving family members' wants more moral weight is a radical departure from what providers do now and may increase these differences. I discuss here the rationales for and against these competing choices.

摘要 在这篇文章中,我讨论了医疗服务提供者在进行代理决策时可能采取的最佳方法。其中一个潜在的关键问题是,一些服务提供者的方法与其他服务提供者的方法不同。如果出现这种情况,其结果可能是武断的,而由此造成的伤害可能是深远的,因为这甚至会影响到其中一些病人的生死。可能导致这些差异的一个因素是,当家属所希望的结果与医护人员认为病人所希望的结果不同时,医护人员对家属所希望的结果所赋予的道德权重。目前,医疗服务提供者最普遍的看法是,为了最大限度地尊重病人的自主权,他们最看重的是病人的意愿,但这种观点可能与其他人的观点相冲突,后者认为自主权更多的是关系性的,因此是建立在与他人之前和现在的社会关系基础之上的。给予家属的要求更多的道德权重与医疗服务提供者目前的做法截然不同,可能会加剧这些分歧。我在此讨论支持和反对这些相互竞争的选择的理由。
{"title":"Should Providers Ask Family Members What They Want When Establishing Surrogate Decision-Making?","authors":"Edmund G Howe","doi":"10.1086/730874","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/730874","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractIn this piece I discuss optimal approaches that providers may take when pursuing surrogate decision-making. A potential critical problem here is some providers' approach differing from that of others. To the extent that this occurs, the results may be arbitrary, and the harm from this may be profound since this may affect, of course, even whether some of these patients will live or die. One factor possibly resulting in these differences is the moral weight providers place on what family members want when these outcomes differ from what they think patients would want. Providers now most commonly place greatest moral weight on following what patients would want to maximally respect their autonomy, but this view may clash with the view of others who see autonomy as more relational and thus based on prior and present social relations with others. Giving family members' wants more moral weight is a radical departure from what providers do now and may increase these differences. I discuss here the rationales for and against these competing choices.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 3","pages":"147-154"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141983570","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dual Advocates in Deceased Organ Donation: The Potential for Moral Distress in Organ Procurement Organization Staff. 死者器官捐献中的双重代言人:器官采购组织工作人员道德困扰的可能性》。
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/728145
Hannah C Boylan, Anna D Goff

AbstractOrgan procurement organization (OPO) staff play an essential role in the facilitation of organ donation as they guide family members and loved ones of dying patients through the donation process. Throughout the donation process, OPO staff must assume the role of a dual advocate, considering both the interests of the donor (which often include the wishes of the donor's family) and the interests of potential recipient(s). The benefits of this role are well established; however, minimal literature exists on the ways this role can cause moral distress in OPO staff, who frequently face scenarios in which adhering to the wishes of a donor family may compromise donation potential but failing to honor donor family requests may result in further emotional burden for the family. Given the frequency with which these ethically complex situations exist during donation, OPO staff are at heightened risk for experiencing moral distress and burnout, yet they are seldom acknowledged in the existing moral distress literature. As a result, it is unclear whether the current practices available to mitigate moral distress are beneficial for this population.

摘要器官获取组织(OPO)的工作人员在促进器官捐献方面发挥着重要作用,他们指导垂死病人的家属和亲人完成捐献过程。在整个捐献过程中,器官获取组织的工作人员必须扮演双重代言人的角色,既要考虑捐献者的利益(通常包括捐献者家属的意愿),又要考虑潜在受捐者的利益。这种角色的益处已得到公认;然而,关于这种角色如何给手术组织工作人员造成道德困扰的文献却少之又少,因为他们经常面临这样的情况:坚持捐献者家属的意愿可能会损害捐献的可能性,但不满足捐献者家属的要求又可能会给家属带来更多的精神负担。鉴于在捐献过程中经常出现这些复杂的伦理状况,器官捐献组织的工作人员面临着更高的道德困扰和职业倦怠风险,但在现有的道德困扰文献中却很少得到承认。因此,目前尚不清楚目前可用于减轻道德困扰的方法是否对这一人群有益。
{"title":"Dual Advocates in Deceased Organ Donation: The Potential for Moral Distress in Organ Procurement Organization Staff.","authors":"Hannah C Boylan, Anna D Goff","doi":"10.1086/728145","DOIUrl":"10.1086/728145","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractOrgan procurement organization (OPO) staff play an essential role in the facilitation of organ donation as they guide family members and loved ones of dying patients through the donation process. Throughout the donation process, OPO staff must assume the role of a dual advocate, considering both the interests of the donor (which often include the wishes of the donor's family) and the interests of potential recipient(s). The benefits of this role are well established; however, minimal literature exists on the ways this role can cause moral distress in OPO staff, who frequently face scenarios in which adhering to the wishes of a donor family may compromise donation potential but failing to honor donor family requests may result in further emotional burden for the family. Given the frequency with which these ethically complex situations exist during donation, OPO staff are at heightened risk for experiencing moral distress and burnout, yet they are seldom acknowledged in the existing moral distress literature. As a result, it is unclear whether the current practices available to mitigate moral distress are beneficial for this population.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 1","pages":"70-75"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139906572","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An Innovation Ethics Framework for Safe and Equitable Contingency Planning. 安全公平应急规划的创新伦理框架。
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/732208
Alexander Quan, David Alfandre

AbstractThe contingency phase is a transition period between usual healthcare delivery and the activation of formalized rationing protocols under crisis standards of care. The contingency phase is defined by two simultaneous goals: avert or forestall critical scarcity of healthcare resources, and provide patient-centered care that is functionally equivalent to usual care when dynamic changes to healthcare operations are necessary to prevent hospital surge overload. Contingency measures modify the allocation of hospital space, staff, and supplies in service of these two goals. Although functionally equivalent care is theoretically possible, hospitals often cannot know a priori which alterations to space, staff, or supplies will lead to downstream effects on patient outcomes, raising ethical questions about how hospitals should institute equitable contingency measures when safety and efficacy data is limited. The current ethics literature has not sufficiently addressed these questions.

摘要 应急阶段是指从通常的医疗保健服务到根据危机护理标准启动正式配给协议之间的过渡时期。应急阶段有两个同时存在的目标:避免或防止医疗资源的严重匮乏;在为防止医院激增超负荷而必须对医疗运营进行动态调整时,提供以患者为中心的医疗服务,其功能等同于常规医疗服务。为实现这两个目标,应急措施改变了医院空间、人员和物资的分配。虽然从理论上讲,功能等同的医疗服务是可能的,但医院往往无法事先知道对空间、人员或供应品的改变会对患者的治疗效果产生下游影响,这就提出了一个伦理问题,即在安全和疗效数据有限的情况下,医院应如何实施公平的应急措施。目前的伦理文献尚未充分解决这些问题。
{"title":"An Innovation Ethics Framework for Safe and Equitable Contingency Planning.","authors":"Alexander Quan, David Alfandre","doi":"10.1086/732208","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/732208","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractThe contingency phase is a transition period between usual healthcare delivery and the activation of formalized rationing protocols under crisis standards of care. The contingency phase is defined by two simultaneous goals: avert or forestall critical scarcity of healthcare resources, and provide patient-centered care that is functionally equivalent to usual care when dynamic changes to healthcare operations are necessary to prevent hospital surge overload. Contingency measures modify the allocation of hospital space, staff, and supplies in service of these two goals. Although functionally equivalent care is theoretically possible, hospitals often cannot know a priori which alterations to space, staff, or supplies will lead to downstream effects on patient outcomes, raising ethical questions about how hospitals should institute equitable contingency measures when safety and efficacy data is limited. The current ethics literature has not sufficiently addressed these questions.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 4","pages":"237-248"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142630191","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Should Providers Advocate for Their Patients? 医疗服务提供者是否应该为患者代言?
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/729224
Edmund G Howe

AbstractThis piece discusses several ways in which providers may advocate for patients and their families that go beyond what providers usually do to help their patients. A much more expanded view of advocacy is suggested. Real cases illustrating all interventions suggested are presented, and each is paradigmatic of numerous others. Categories of possible options suggested for expanded advocacy include (1) providers enhancing patients' outcomes when standard treatments have failed, (2) providers taking measures outside those they usually take to benefit patients to a greater extent, and (3) providers sacrificing their own needs more than they customarily do to help their patients still further. The suggested interventions are practical and can be implemented immediately. Taken together, the interventions proposed are also aspirational.

摘要 本文讨论了医疗服务提供者为病人及其家属进行宣传的几种方式,这些方式超出了医疗服务提供者通常为帮助病人所做的工作。文章提出了一种更为广泛的宣传观点。文章介绍了所有建议干预措施的真实案例,每个案例都是众多其他干预措施的范例。为扩大宣传而建议的可能方案包括:(1)当标准治疗失败时,医疗服务提供者提高病人的治疗效果;(2)医疗服务提供者采取超出其通常所采取的措施,使病人在更大程度上受益;以及(3)医疗服务提供者牺牲自己的需要,比他们通常所做的更多,以进一步帮助病人。所建议的干预措施非常实用,可以立即实施。总之,所建议的干预措施也是令人向往的。
{"title":"Should Providers Advocate for Their Patients?","authors":"Edmund G Howe","doi":"10.1086/729224","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/729224","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractThis piece discusses several ways in which providers may advocate for patients and their families that go beyond what providers usually do to help their patients. A much more expanded view of advocacy is suggested. Real cases illustrating all interventions suggested are presented, and each is paradigmatic of numerous others. Categories of possible options suggested for expanded advocacy include (1) providers enhancing patients' outcomes when standard treatments have failed, (2) providers taking measures outside those they usually take to benefit patients to a greater extent, and (3) providers sacrificing their own needs more than they customarily do to help their patients still further. The suggested interventions are practical and can be implemented immediately. Taken together, the interventions proposed are also aspirational.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 2","pages":"77-84"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140904898","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ethics of Pediatric Surgical Innovation: Considerations, Controversies, and Pitfalls. 小儿外科创新的伦理:考虑因素、争议和陷阱。
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/730873
Katherine Brooke Snyder, Ryan Austin Stewart, Catherine J Hunter

AbstractThe field of surgery has relied on innovation and creativity to improve patient care and propel the field forward. Historically, regulatory oversight of innovative approaches to surgery has been largely inconsistent, rendering surgeons relatively unrestricted creative latitude in the operating room; whether this has proven to be more beneficial or harmful is subject to debate. While innovation plays a crucial role in the advancement of surgical techniques, the potential drawbacks of unregulated innovation must be seriously considered, especially when treating vulnerable populations such as infants and children. This article provides an overview of the ethical aspects surrounding innovation in pediatric surgery, including discussion of relevant considerations, controversies, and pitfalls. The following includes a review of the current and past literature surrounding the topic. The purpose of this review is to heighten awareness of the ethical challenges that surgeons face when considering novel operative techniques on pediatric patients.

摘要 外科领域一直依赖创新和创造力来改善病人护理并推动该领域向前发展。从历史上看,对外科创新方法的监管基本上是不一致的,这使得外科医生在手术室中的创新空间相对不受限制。虽然创新对外科技术的发展起着至关重要的作用,但我们也必须认真考虑不受监管的创新可能带来的弊端,尤其是在治疗婴儿和儿童等弱势群体时。本文概述了围绕儿科手术创新的伦理问题,包括相关考虑因素、争议和陷阱的讨论。下文回顾了当前和过去围绕该主题的文献。本综述旨在提高外科医生对儿科患者在考虑新手术技术时所面临的伦理挑战的认识。
{"title":"Ethics of Pediatric Surgical Innovation: Considerations, Controversies, and Pitfalls.","authors":"Katherine Brooke Snyder, Ryan Austin Stewart, Catherine J Hunter","doi":"10.1086/730873","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/730873","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractThe field of surgery has relied on innovation and creativity to improve patient care and propel the field forward. Historically, regulatory oversight of innovative approaches to surgery has been largely inconsistent, rendering surgeons relatively unrestricted creative latitude in the operating room; whether this has proven to be more beneficial or harmful is subject to debate. While innovation plays a crucial role in the advancement of surgical techniques, the potential drawbacks of unregulated innovation must be seriously considered, especially when treating vulnerable populations such as infants and children. This article provides an overview of the ethical aspects surrounding innovation in pediatric surgery, including discussion of relevant considerations, controversies, and pitfalls. The following includes a review of the current and past literature surrounding the topic. The purpose of this review is to heighten awareness of the ethical challenges that surgeons face when considering novel operative techniques on pediatric patients.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 3","pages":"180-189"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141983566","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Palliative Care for Refractory Depressive Symptoms in a Female Veteran Geriatric Patient. 姑息治疗女性退伍老年患者的难治性抑郁症状
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/730872
Yasser Sammour, Alyssa C Smith, Sydney Waller, Michael Riddle, Yena Choi

AbstractPsychiatric treatment options, such as electroconvulsive therapy (ECT), can be lifesaving for individuals suffering from severe mental illness. For individuals who are unable to make or communicate their own medical decisions, this decision may fall on a legal guardian, who will make decisions on the patient's behalf. Here we discuss the considerations of end-of-life planning in a patient with severe mental illness under guardianship when treatment modalities, in this case ECT, are no longer effective.

摘要 对于患有严重精神疾病的人来说,电休克疗法(ECT)等精神病治疗方案可以挽救他们的生命。对于无法做出或传达自己的医疗决定的患者,这一决定可能会由法定监护人代为做出。在此,我们将讨论在监护人的监护下,当治疗方式(本案例中为电痉挛疗法)不再有效时,重症精神病患者生命末期规划的注意事项。
{"title":"Palliative Care for Refractory Depressive Symptoms in a Female Veteran Geriatric Patient.","authors":"Yasser Sammour, Alyssa C Smith, Sydney Waller, Michael Riddle, Yena Choi","doi":"10.1086/730872","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/730872","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractPsychiatric treatment options, such as electroconvulsive therapy (ECT), can be lifesaving for individuals suffering from severe mental illness. For individuals who are unable to make or communicate their own medical decisions, this decision may fall on a legal guardian, who will make decisions on the patient's behalf. Here we discuss the considerations of end-of-life planning in a patient with severe mental illness under guardianship when treatment modalities, in this case ECT, are no longer effective.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 3","pages":"199-201"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141983569","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Should Providers Engage in Religious Discussions, and If They Should, Then with Whom? 医疗服务提供者是否应该参与宗教讨论?
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/732143
Edmund G Howe

AbstractPatients' spiritual views and, more generally, the meaning they feel in their lives is often, if not always, most important to them, especially when they have serious illness. Yet there are no standard requirements for providers to explore with patients their spiritual needs. Providers' views regarding their both taking initiatives to explore with patients needs and then to discuss with them their religious concerns if they want this vary widely. This piece explores, then, the extent to which providers should take these initiatives and, if they have this interest, whether as providers they should carry on these discussions or refer these patients, always, to clergy persons, as some providers adamantly advocate because they have expertise in this area that providers lack. This piece goes on to discuss whether providers believe they should have these discussions even when their patients' beliefs differ greatly from their own. In exploring this question, examples involving patients with Muslim, Hindu, and Christian beliefs are considered. Beliefs reported by some people from Germany and Israel regarding physician-assisted dying also are reported and compared, illustrating that patients' and people's beliefs cannot be reliably just inferred. Practical approaches, finally, are suggested.

摘要病人的精神观点,更广义地说,他们所感受到的生命意义,对他们来说即使不总是,也往往是最重要的,尤其是在他们身患重病的时候。然而,目前并没有对医疗服务提供者提出与患者探讨其精神需求的标准要求。对于医疗服务提供者是否主动与病人探讨他们的需求,并在病人愿意的情况下与他们讨论他们的宗教问题,他们的看法大相径庭。因此,本文探讨了服务提供者应在多大程度上采取这些主动行动,以及如果他们有这种兴趣,作为服务提供者,他们是否应该进行这些讨论,或者像一些服务提供者坚决主张的那样,总是将这些病人转介给神职人员,因为他们在这方面拥有服务提供者所缺乏的专业知识。这篇文章接着讨论了医疗服务提供者是否认为,即使病人的信仰与自己有很大的不同,他们也应该进行这些讨论。在探讨这个问题时,我们考虑了穆斯林、印度教和基督教信仰病人的例子。此外,还对德国和以色列的一些人报告的关于医生协助死亡的信仰进行了报告和比较,说明病人和人们的信仰不能仅靠可靠的推断。最后还提出了一些实用的方法。
{"title":"Should Providers Engage in Religious Discussions, and If They Should, Then with Whom?","authors":"Edmund G Howe","doi":"10.1086/732143","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/732143","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractPatients' spiritual views and, more generally, the meaning they feel in their lives is often, if not always, most important to them, especially when they have serious illness. Yet there are no standard requirements for providers to explore with patients their spiritual needs. Providers' views regarding their both taking initiatives to explore with patients needs and then to discuss with them their religious concerns if they want this vary widely. This piece explores, then, the extent to which providers should take these initiatives and, if they have this interest, whether as providers they should carry on these discussions or refer these patients, always, to clergy persons, as some providers adamantly advocate because they have expertise in this area that providers lack. This piece goes on to discuss whether providers believe they should have these discussions even when their patients' beliefs differ greatly from their own. In exploring this question, examples involving patients with Muslim, Hindu, and Christian beliefs are considered. Beliefs reported by some people from Germany and Israel regarding physician-assisted dying also are reported and compared, illustrating that patients' and people's beliefs cannot be reliably just inferred. Practical approaches, finally, are suggested.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 4","pages":"217-223"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142630259","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How Should We Allocate Divisible Resources? An Overlooked Question. 我们应该如何分配可分割的资源?一个被忽视的问题
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/728143
Noah Berens, Mara Buchbinder

AbstractThe ethical allocation of scarce medical resources has received significant attention, yet a key question remains unaddressed: how should scarce, divisible resources be allocated? We present a case from the COVID-19 pandemic in which scarce resources were divided among patients rather than allocated to some patients over others. We assess how widely accepted allocation principles could be applied to this case, and we show how these principles provide insufficient guidance. We then propose alternatives that may help guide decision-making in such cases, and we evaluate the possibility of treating patients equally by dividing resources equally. Resource scarcity is not limited to pandemic situations, and many healthcare resources are divisible. This question-how to allocate these divisible resources-deserves greater attention from bioethics.

摘要稀缺医疗资源的伦理分配已受到极大关注,但一个关键问题仍未得到解决:稀缺的、可分割的资源应如何分配?我们介绍了 COVID-19 大流行中的一个案例,在该案例中,稀缺资源被分配给了不同的患者,而不是某些患者优先于其他患者。我们评估了如何将广为接受的分配原则应用于这一案例,并说明了这些原则如何提供了不充分的指导。然后,我们提出了有助于在这种情况下指导决策的替代方案,并评估了通过平均分配资源来平等对待患者的可能性。资源稀缺并不局限于大流行病的情况,许多医疗资源都是可以分割的。这个问题--如何分配这些可分割的资源--值得生命伦理学更多的关注。
{"title":"How Should We Allocate Divisible Resources? An Overlooked Question.","authors":"Noah Berens, Mara Buchbinder","doi":"10.1086/728143","DOIUrl":"10.1086/728143","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractThe ethical allocation of scarce medical resources has received significant attention, yet a key question remains unaddressed: how should scarce, divisible resources be allocated? We present a case from the COVID-19 pandemic in which scarce resources were divided among patients rather than allocated to some patients over others. We assess how widely accepted allocation principles could be applied to this case, and we show how these principles provide insufficient guidance. We then propose alternatives that may help guide decision-making in such cases, and we evaluate the possibility of treating patients equally by dividing resources equally. Resource scarcity is not limited to pandemic situations, and many healthcare resources are divisible. This question-how to allocate these divisible resources-deserves greater attention from bioethics.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 1","pages":"59-64"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139906575","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Letting Go of the Status Quo: One Program's Experience Discontinuing Ethics Committees and Creating Alternative Structures for Engagement. 放弃现状:一个项目终止伦理委员会并创建其他参与结构的经验。
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/732207
Hilary Mabel, Kate M Gordon, Jessica Ginsberg, Jason Lesandrini, Bryan Kibbe, Lexi C White, David Reis, Barquiesha Madison, Jamila Young, Steven Shields, Jameisha Brown, Jordan Potter

AbstractThe authors describe their Ethics Program's transition from utilizing ethics committees to instead implementing a three-initiative structure consisting of Ethics Grand Rounds, an Ethics Liaison Network, and an Ethics Advisory Group. They first outline the history of ethics committees. Then, they discuss the history of their Ethics Program and the challenges that ethics committees posed. Next, they describe their approach to developing new initiatives for non-ethicist healthcare professionals to engage in ethics work and what these initiatives specifically entail. They then describe how they worked to secure buy-in for dissolving their ethics committees and, based on pre- and post-implementation surveys, how this transition has been received by former ethics committee members. Finally, the authors reflect on what has been gained and lost through these changes and offer insights and recommendations for other ethics programs thinking about discontinuing their own ethics committees in favor of more innovative models.

摘要 作者介绍了他们的伦理项目从利用伦理委员会到实施由伦理大查房、伦理联络网和伦理咨询小组组成的三倡议结构的转变过程。他们首先概述了伦理委员会的历史。然后,他们讨论了伦理项目的历史以及伦理委员会带来的挑战。接下来,他们介绍了为非伦理学家医护专业人员参与伦理工作制定新举措的方法,以及这些举措的具体内容。然后,他们介绍了如何努力争取解散伦理委员会的支持,以及根据实施前后的调查,前伦理委员会成员对这一转变的看法。最后,作者反思了这些变革的得失,并为其他考虑解散自己的伦理委员会、转而采用更具创新性的模式的伦理项目提供了见解和建议。
{"title":"Letting Go of the Status Quo: One Program's Experience Discontinuing Ethics Committees and Creating Alternative Structures for Engagement.","authors":"Hilary Mabel, Kate M Gordon, Jessica Ginsberg, Jason Lesandrini, Bryan Kibbe, Lexi C White, David Reis, Barquiesha Madison, Jamila Young, Steven Shields, Jameisha Brown, Jordan Potter","doi":"10.1086/732207","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/732207","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractThe authors describe their Ethics Program's transition from utilizing ethics committees to instead implementing a three-initiative structure consisting of Ethics Grand Rounds, an Ethics Liaison Network, and an Ethics Advisory Group. They first outline the history of ethics committees. Then, they discuss the history of their Ethics Program and the challenges that ethics committees posed. Next, they describe their approach to developing new initiatives for non-ethicist healthcare professionals to engage in ethics work and what these initiatives specifically entail. They then describe how they worked to secure buy-in for dissolving their ethics committees and, based on pre- and post-implementation surveys, how this transition has been received by former ethics committee members. Finally, the authors reflect on what has been gained and lost through these changes and offer insights and recommendations for other ethics programs thinking about discontinuing their own ethics committees in favor of more innovative models.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 4","pages":"260-273"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142630214","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Characteristics and Outcomes of Safe Discharge Planning Bioethics Consultations of a Single Ethics Service at a Large Medical Center. 大型医疗中心单一伦理服务机构的安全出院规划生物伦理咨询的特点和结果。
Q3 Medicine Pub Date : 2024-01-01 DOI: 10.1086/732213
Breckin Horton, Adira Hulkower, Sarah Garijo-Garde, Elizabeth Chuang

AbstractBackground: Clinical ethics consults are sometimes requested for patients who lack capacity and do not assent to discharge recommendations, particularly those with neurocognitive or psychiatric disorders desiring home discharge. Balancing the risks and benefits of overriding patient preferences involves considering dignity, values, clinical information, and available resources. Outcomes of such consultations lack characterization in the literature.

Methods: We examined clinical ethics consultations from December 2015 to June 2023 at a large, urban academic medical center serving a diverse community with high poverty rates. Time to readmission and proportion readmitted within 30 days were analyzed by discharge disposition.

Results: Among 1,163 ethics consults, 167 were for discharge planning. The median age was 65.4. Of these, 56.7 percent were male; 29.9 percent, Black, non-Hispanic; 26.9 percent, Hispanic; and 19.1 percent, White, non-Hispanic. More than 37 percent had a psychiatric diagnosis, with a similar percentage affected by dementia. Discharge to skilled nursing facilities (SNFs), home without nursing care, home with nursing care, subacute rehabilitation facilities, and elopement constituted 33, 26, 26, 2, and 2 percent, respectively. The discharged-to-home group showed the highest average days to readmission (243), while the average for the discharged-to-SNF group was 153. These differences were not statistically significant when controlling for age, gender, and comorbid conditions.

Conclusions: Half of the patients consulted for discharge planning were discharged home and were not at higher risk for early readmission. This higher-than-expected percentage may reflect increased attention to patient values when bioethics is involved.

摘要背景:对于缺乏行为能力且不同意出院建议的患者,尤其是那些患有神经认知或精神障碍、希望出院回家的患者,有时会要求进行临床伦理咨询。要在患者的偏好与风险之间取得平衡,需要考虑患者的尊严、价值观、临床信息和可用资源。此类咨询的结果在文献中缺乏描述:我们研究了一家大型城市学术医疗中心从 2015 年 12 月到 2023 年 6 月的临床伦理咨询情况,该中心服务于贫困率较高的多元化社区。根据出院处置分析了再入院时间和 30 天内再入院的比例:在 1,163 次伦理咨询中,有 167 次是为了出院规划。年龄中位数为 65.4 岁。其中,56.7% 为男性;29.9% 为非西班牙裔黑人;26.9% 为西班牙裔;19.1% 为非西班牙裔白人。超过 37% 的患者有精神病诊断,受痴呆症影响的比例与此相似。出院到专业护理机构(SNFs)、无护理家庭、有护理家庭、亚急性康复机构和私奔的比例分别为 33%、26%、26%、2% 和 2%。出院回家组再次入院的平均天数最高(243 天),而出院到 SNF 组的平均天数为 153 天。在控制年龄、性别和合并症后,这些差异在统计学上并不显著:结论:在接受出院规划咨询的患者中,有一半人出院回家了,他们并不存在较高的早期再入院风险。这一高于预期的比例可能反映出在涉及生命伦理学时,患者的价值观得到了更多关注。
{"title":"Characteristics and Outcomes of Safe Discharge Planning Bioethics Consultations of a Single Ethics Service at a Large Medical Center.","authors":"Breckin Horton, Adira Hulkower, Sarah Garijo-Garde, Elizabeth Chuang","doi":"10.1086/732213","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/732213","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>AbstractBackground: Clinical ethics consults are sometimes requested for patients who lack capacity and do not assent to discharge recommendations, particularly those with neurocognitive or psychiatric disorders desiring home discharge. Balancing the risks and benefits of overriding patient preferences involves considering dignity, values, clinical information, and available resources. Outcomes of such consultations lack characterization in the literature.</p><p><strong>Methods: </strong>We examined clinical ethics consultations from December 2015 to June 2023 at a large, urban academic medical center serving a diverse community with high poverty rates. Time to readmission and proportion readmitted within 30 days were analyzed by discharge disposition.</p><p><strong>Results: </strong>Among 1,163 ethics consults, 167 were for discharge planning. The median age was 65.4. Of these, 56.7 percent were male; 29.9 percent, Black, non-Hispanic; 26.9 percent, Hispanic; and 19.1 percent, White, non-Hispanic. More than 37 percent had a psychiatric diagnosis, with a similar percentage affected by dementia. Discharge to skilled nursing facilities (SNFs), home without nursing care, home with nursing care, subacute rehabilitation facilities, and elopement constituted 33, 26, 26, 2, and 2 percent, respectively. The discharged-to-home group showed the highest average days to readmission (243), while the average for the discharged-to-SNF group was 153. These differences were not statistically significant when controlling for age, gender, and comorbid conditions.</p><p><strong>Conclusions: </strong>Half of the patients consulted for discharge planning were discharged home and were not at higher risk for early readmission. This higher-than-expected percentage may reflect increased attention to patient values when bioethics is involved.</p>","PeriodicalId":39646,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Clinical Ethics","volume":"35 4","pages":"229-236"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142630196","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of Clinical Ethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1