首页 > 最新文献

Washington Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
Regulating Real-World Surveillance 规范现实世界的监控
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2015-10-27 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2681128
M. Kaminski
A number of laws govern information gathering, or surveillance, by private parties in the physical world. But we lack a compelling theory of privacy harm that accounts for the state’s interest in enacting these laws. Without a theory of privacy harm, these laws will be enacted piecemeal. Legislators will have a difficult time justifying the laws to constituents; the laws will not be adequately tailored to legislative interest; and courts will find it challenging to weigh privacy harms against other strong values, such as freedom of expression. This Article identifies the government interest in enacting laws governing surveillance by private parties. Using social psychologist Irwin Altman’s framework of “boundary management” as a jumping-off point, I conceptualize privacy harm as interference in an individual’s ability to dynamically manage disclosure and social boundaries. Stemming from this understanding of privacy, the government has two related interests in enacting laws prohibiting surveillance: an interest in providing notice so that an individual can adjust her behavior; and an interest in prohibiting surveillance to prevent undesirable behavioral shifts. Framing the government interest, or interests, this way has several advantages. First, it descriptively maps on to existing laws: These laws either help individuals manage their desired level of disclosure by requiring notice, or prevent individuals from resorting to undesirable behavioral shifts by banning surveillance. Second, the framework helps us assess the strength and legitimacy of the legislative interest in these laws. Third, it allows courts to understand how First Amendment interests are in fact internalized in privacy laws. And fourth, it provides guidance to legislators for the enactment of new laws governing a range of new surveillance technologies — from automated license plate readers (ALPRs) to robots to drones.
在现实世界中,有许多法律规范着私人团体的信息收集或监视。但我们缺乏一个令人信服的隐私损害理论,来解释国家在制定这些法律时的利益。如果没有隐私损害理论,这些法律将零敲碎打地颁布。立法者将很难向选民证明这些法律的合理性;法律将不能充分适应立法利益;法院会发现,将隐私损害与言论自由等其他重要价值进行权衡是一项挑战。这条规定了政府在制定管理私人团体监视的法律方面的利益。以社会心理学家Irwin Altman的“边界管理”框架为出发点,我将隐私伤害概念化为对个人动态管理信息披露和社会边界的能力的干扰。基于对隐私的这种理解,政府在制定禁止监视的法律时有两个相关的利益:一是提供通知,以便个人可以调整自己的行为;以及对禁止监视以防止不良行为转变的兴趣。以这种方式构建政府利益有几个好处。首先,它描述了现有法律:这些法律要么通过要求通知来帮助个人管理他们想要的披露水平,要么通过禁止监视来防止个人诉诸于不受欢迎的行为转变。其次,该框架有助于我们评估这些法律中立法利益的力量和合法性。第三,它使法院能够理解第一修正案的利益实际上是如何内化在隐私法中的。第四,它为立法者制定管理一系列新监控技术的新法律提供指导,这些技术包括自动车牌识别器(alpr)、机器人和无人机。
{"title":"Regulating Real-World Surveillance","authors":"M. Kaminski","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2681128","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2681128","url":null,"abstract":"A number of laws govern information gathering, or surveillance, by private parties in the physical world. But we lack a compelling theory of privacy harm that accounts for the state’s interest in enacting these laws. Without a theory of privacy harm, these laws will be enacted piecemeal. Legislators will have a difficult time justifying the laws to constituents; the laws will not be adequately tailored to legislative interest; and courts will find it challenging to weigh privacy harms against other strong values, such as freedom of expression. This Article identifies the government interest in enacting laws governing surveillance by private parties. Using social psychologist Irwin Altman’s framework of “boundary management” as a jumping-off point, I conceptualize privacy harm as interference in an individual’s ability to dynamically manage disclosure and social boundaries. Stemming from this understanding of privacy, the government has two related interests in enacting laws prohibiting surveillance: an interest in providing notice so that an individual can adjust her behavior; and an interest in prohibiting surveillance to prevent undesirable behavioral shifts. Framing the government interest, or interests, this way has several advantages. First, it descriptively maps on to existing laws: These laws either help individuals manage their desired level of disclosure by requiring notice, or prevent individuals from resorting to undesirable behavioral shifts by banning surveillance. Second, the framework helps us assess the strength and legitimacy of the legislative interest in these laws. Third, it allows courts to understand how First Amendment interests are in fact internalized in privacy laws. And fourth, it provides guidance to legislators for the enactment of new laws governing a range of new surveillance technologies — from automated license plate readers (ALPRs) to robots to drones.","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"90 1","pages":"1113"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2015-10-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68253795","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Enlightened Regulatory Capture 开明的监管俘获
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2013-08-08 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2298205
D. Thaw
Regulatory capture generally evokes negative images of private interests exerting excessive influence on government action to advance their own agendas at the expense of the public interest. There are some cases, however, where this conventional wisdom is exactly backwards. This Article explores the first verifiable case, taken from healthcare cybersecurity, where regulatory capture enabled regulators to harness private expertise to advance exclusively public goals. Comparing this example to other attempts at harnessing industry expertise reveals a set of characteristics under which regulatory capture can be used in the public interest. These include: 1) legislatively-mandated adoption of recommendations by an advisory committee comprising private interests and "reduced-bias" subject matter experts; 2) relaxed procedural constraints for committee action to prevent internal committee capture; 3) and opportunities for committee participation to be worthwhile for representatives of private parties beyond the mere opportunity to advance their own interests. This Article presents recommendations based on those characteristics as to how and when legislatures may endeavor to replicate this success in other industries to improve both the legitimacy and efficacy of the regulatory process.
监管俘获通常会让人联想到私人利益对政府行为施加过度影响,以牺牲公众利益为代价推进自己的议程的负面形象。然而,在某些情况下,这种传统智慧完全是倒退的。本文探讨了第一个可验证的案例,该案例取自医疗保健网络安全,其中监管捕获使监管机构能够利用私人专业知识专门推进公共目标。将这个例子与其他利用行业专业知识的尝试进行比较,可以发现一组特征,在这些特征下,监管捕获可以用于公共利益。这些措施包括:1)由私人利益和“减少偏见”主题专家组成的咨询委员会通过立法授权的建议;2)放宽委员会行动的程序限制,防止内部委员会被俘获;3)对私人政党代表来说,参与委员会的机会不仅仅是促进他们自己利益的机会。本文根据这些特点提出建议,说明立法机构如何以及何时可以努力在其他行业复制这一成功,以提高监管过程的合法性和有效性。
{"title":"Enlightened Regulatory Capture","authors":"D. Thaw","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2298205","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2298205","url":null,"abstract":"Regulatory capture generally evokes negative images of private interests exerting excessive influence on government action to advance their own agendas at the expense of the public interest. There are some cases, however, where this conventional wisdom is exactly backwards. This Article explores the first verifiable case, taken from healthcare cybersecurity, where regulatory capture enabled regulators to harness private expertise to advance exclusively public goals. Comparing this example to other attempts at harnessing industry expertise reveals a set of characteristics under which regulatory capture can be used in the public interest. These include: 1) legislatively-mandated adoption of recommendations by an advisory committee comprising private interests and \"reduced-bias\" subject matter experts; 2) relaxed procedural constraints for committee action to prevent internal committee capture; 3) and opportunities for committee participation to be worthwhile for representatives of private parties beyond the mere opportunity to advance their own interests. This Article presents recommendations based on those characteristics as to how and when legislatures may endeavor to replicate this success in other industries to improve both the legitimacy and efficacy of the regulatory process.","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"89 1","pages":"329"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2013-08-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2298205","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68077153","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 12
The Miranda Warning 米兰达警告
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2013-03-01 DOI: 10.4135/9781452229300.n1203
F. Schauer
I. INTRODUCTION- ISOLATING MIRANDA'S IMPORTLargely as a consequence of American television and movies, Miranda v. Arizona1 may well be the most famous appellate case in the world. On the screen, innumerable actors playing American police officers give Miranda warnings to other actors playing suspects, a portrayal that reflects the reality of genuine police officers giving genuine Miranda warnings to genuine suspects millions of times every year. Indeed, such has been the influence of Miranda that Russian television cops give something like a Miranda warning to suspects even though no actual Russian law imposes such an obligation on real Russian cops.2 And it is said that in countries where no such right actually exists, suspects have still been known, when arrested, to demand their Miranda rights.3Among the most interesting dimensions of Miranda's worldwide fame is that the case's prominence is largely a function of the warning itself.4 Television and motion pictures feature Miranda warnings not because of any suspected viewer interest in whether suspects actually have a right to remain silent,5 nor on account of the underlying substance of the right to have a lawyer during interrogation,6 nor because the general public is concerned about the right to appointed counsel for the indigent.7 None of this, to put it mildly, makes for good theater. What is good theater is the ritual of the arrest, and the Miranda warning, typically given in almost exactly the terms set forth in the Supreme Court's opinion, is a prominent feature of the ritual, even apart from the role that the warning is actually designed to serve.Professor Kamisar - with his characteristic attention to detail in support of spirited argument - provides an insightful judicial and political history of the retrenching that has marked much of Miranda's history since the Supreme Court's decision in 1966.8 In lamenting Miranda's erosion, I largely sympathize with Kamisar. But if there is a worry about the erosion of Miranda,9 it must be a worry not about the erosion of the right to remain silent itself, which existed independent of Miranda,10 nor about the right to counsel during interrogation, whose recognition and enforcement again preceded Miranda. u Instead, it must be a worry about the requirement that the police provide a warning in a certain way under certain conditions.12 Once we understand the import of various pre-Miranda decisions, we can appreciate that Miranda is about the warning itself, rather than about what the warning is a warning of. And when we understand Miranda in this way, we can focus on just what role the warning is designed to serve, and what the Court in Miranda thought it was doing in specifying almost exactly the form that the warning was to take. It is precisely this focus that will be the subject of my attention in this Response.In being about a warning, Miranda is about communication. Specifically, it is about two different dimensions of communication. One of
由于美国电视和电影的影响,米兰达诉亚利桑那州案可能是世界上最著名的上诉案件。在银幕上,无数扮演美国警察的演员对其他扮演嫌疑人的演员发出米兰达警告,这一刻画反映了每年数百万次真正的警察对真正的嫌疑人发出米兰达警告的现实。事实上,米兰达的影响是如此之大,以至于俄罗斯电视上的警察会给嫌疑人一些类似米兰达警告的东西,尽管俄罗斯法律并没有把这样的义务强加给真正的俄罗斯警察据说,在实际上不存在这种权利的国家,嫌疑犯在被捕时仍然会要求他们的米兰达权利。米兰达举世闻名的一个最有趣的方面是,案件的突出程度很大程度上是这一警告本身的作用电视和电影中出现米兰达警告,不是因为怀疑观众对嫌疑人是否真的有保持沉默的权利感兴趣,也不是因为在审讯期间有律师的基本权利,也不是因为一般公众关心为穷人指定律师的权利委婉地说,这些都不是好的戏剧。好的戏剧是逮捕的仪式,而米兰达警告,通常以几乎完全符合最高法院意见中规定的条款给出,是仪式的一个突出特征,即使不考虑警告实际上所起的作用。卡米萨教授——以他特有的对细节的关注来支持激烈的争论——提供了一个深刻的司法和政治历史上的缩减,这标志着自1966年最高法院的决定以来米兰达的历史。在哀叹米兰达的侵蚀,我很大程度上同情卡米萨。但是,如果有人担心《米兰达》受到侵蚀的话,那就不是担心保持沉默的权利本身受到侵蚀,因为它独立于《米兰达》而存在,也不是担心在审讯期间请律师的权利受到侵蚀,因为这种权利的承认和执行再次早于《米兰达》。相反,这一定是对警察在特定条件下以特定方式提供警告的要求的担忧一旦我们理解了《米兰达》判决之前各种决定的重要性,我们就会明白,《米兰达》是关于警告本身的,而不是关于警告是什么。当我们以这种方式理解《米兰达》时,我们可以关注警告的作用,以及法院在《米兰达》中认为自己在做什么,以至于几乎完全指定了警告的形式。正是这一重点将成为我在本《答复》中关注的主题。米兰达是一种警告,也是一种交流。具体来说,它是关于交流的两个不同维度。其中之一是对米兰达判决的实质内容,即警察必须在某些条件下告知嫌疑人他们有权保持沉默,有权在审讯时请律师在场,如果他们贫穷,则有权指定律师《米兰达》的另一个沟通维度是最高法院以极其清晰和规则般的措辞向警察传达其要求的方式——警察是裁决的主要对象。我将依次考虑这两个交际维度。即使在米兰达之前,非自愿供词也被清楚地理解为违反了第五修正案关于禁止强迫自证其罪的规定和第十四修正案对正当程序的保证即使在米兰达之前,嫌疑犯仍然被允许放弃他们反对自证其罪的特权。…
{"title":"The Miranda Warning","authors":"F. Schauer","doi":"10.4135/9781452229300.n1203","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4135/9781452229300.n1203","url":null,"abstract":"I. INTRODUCTION- ISOLATING MIRANDA'S IMPORTLargely as a consequence of American television and movies, Miranda v. Arizona1 may well be the most famous appellate case in the world. On the screen, innumerable actors playing American police officers give Miranda warnings to other actors playing suspects, a portrayal that reflects the reality of genuine police officers giving genuine Miranda warnings to genuine suspects millions of times every year. Indeed, such has been the influence of Miranda that Russian television cops give something like a Miranda warning to suspects even though no actual Russian law imposes such an obligation on real Russian cops.2 And it is said that in countries where no such right actually exists, suspects have still been known, when arrested, to demand their Miranda rights.3Among the most interesting dimensions of Miranda's worldwide fame is that the case's prominence is largely a function of the warning itself.4 Television and motion pictures feature Miranda warnings not because of any suspected viewer interest in whether suspects actually have a right to remain silent,5 nor on account of the underlying substance of the right to have a lawyer during interrogation,6 nor because the general public is concerned about the right to appointed counsel for the indigent.7 None of this, to put it mildly, makes for good theater. What is good theater is the ritual of the arrest, and the Miranda warning, typically given in almost exactly the terms set forth in the Supreme Court's opinion, is a prominent feature of the ritual, even apart from the role that the warning is actually designed to serve.Professor Kamisar - with his characteristic attention to detail in support of spirited argument - provides an insightful judicial and political history of the retrenching that has marked much of Miranda's history since the Supreme Court's decision in 1966.8 In lamenting Miranda's erosion, I largely sympathize with Kamisar. But if there is a worry about the erosion of Miranda,9 it must be a worry not about the erosion of the right to remain silent itself, which existed independent of Miranda,10 nor about the right to counsel during interrogation, whose recognition and enforcement again preceded Miranda. u Instead, it must be a worry about the requirement that the police provide a warning in a certain way under certain conditions.12 Once we understand the import of various pre-Miranda decisions, we can appreciate that Miranda is about the warning itself, rather than about what the warning is a warning of. And when we understand Miranda in this way, we can focus on just what role the warning is designed to serve, and what the Court in Miranda thought it was doing in specifying almost exactly the form that the warning was to take. It is precisely this focus that will be the subject of my attention in this Response.In being about a warning, Miranda is about communication. Specifically, it is about two different dimensions of communication. One of ","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"88 1","pages":"155"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2013-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70579584","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
A Modified Theory of the Law of Federal Courts: The Case of Arising under Jurisdiction 联邦法院法律理论的修正:管辖权下产生的案例
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2013-02-24 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2223523
S. Grossi
On February 20, 2013, the Supreme Court announced its decision in Gunn v. Minton. There the Court revisited the scope of statutory “arising under” jurisdiction in the context of a legal malpractice suit premised on alleged attorney errors committed in a prior patent litigation. The significance of the decision transcends the specific context in which it arose. Although Gunn involved patent law arising under jurisdiction, 28 U.S.C. §1338, that jurisdictional standard is interpreted in precisely the same manner as the identically worded §1331 standard. Hence, the decision in Gunn applies to a full range of federal question cases in which a federal issue is embedded in a state-law claim. In addition, Gunn provides insight into the ongoing clash between principle and docket-management concerns that has become so characteristic of Supreme Court decisions in the realm of procedure.The Gunn opinion was much anticipated by the legal community since prior decisions by the Court had generated considerable confusion as to the scope of arising under jurisdiction in so-called “federal-ingredient” cases. Some commentators hoped that the Court would adopt the creation test as the exclusive measure of jurisdiction. Others hoped for a clarification of the federal-ingredient test. Still others, like this author, hoped that the Court would redirect the jurisdictional analysis to the traditional fundamental principles that once animated federal question jurisdiction. As I explain in my article, everyone will be disappointed by the result. The specific jurisdictional issue in Gunn focused on what had come to be known as the third and fourth prongs of the “Grable test,” namely, whether the federal ingredient embedded in the plaintiff’s state-law claim was substantial and whether the exercise of jurisdiction over that claim would upset the congressionally mandated balance between federal and state courts. Lower courts had been struggling with the interpretation and application of both prongs. Some had adopted detailed and highly technical doctrinal tests that led to counterintuitive results where jurisdiction was denied over concededly “significant” federal questions. Others had adopted a more holistic approach, seemingly designed to apply Grable test and, at the same time, avoid that test’s obvious strictures.Some lower courts actually confessed that the jurisdictional determination was subjective and speculative and that, under similar circumstances, different judges might reach different conclusions. While the Gunn Court did address both Grable prongs, it did little other than endorse its previous iterations of those elements, providing neither a defense for them nor a principled method through which they might be applied. Thus, much of the confusion over federal jurisdictional standards that preceded Gunn remains largely unresolved.In this article, I begin by assessing the development of statutory arising under jurisdiction from its nineteenth century roots to the
2013年2月20日,最高法院宣布了Gunn v. Minton一案的判决。在一宗以先前的专利诉讼中涉嫌律师错误为前提的法律渎职诉讼中,法院重新审视了法定“在”管辖权下产生的范围。这一决定的意义超越了它产生的具体背景。尽管Gunn案涉及在管辖权下产生的专利法,《美国法典》第28编第1338条,但该管辖权标准与第1331条措辞相同的标准应以完全相同的方式解释。因此,冈恩案的判决适用于所有联邦问题案件,在这些案件中,联邦问题包含在州法主张中。此外,Gunn对原则和案单管理之间的持续冲突提供了深刻的见解,这种冲突已成为最高法院在程序领域的判决的特征。法律界很期待Gunn的意见,因为法院以前的决定对所谓“联邦成分”案件的管辖范围造成了相当大的混乱。有些评论人士希望法院采用创造检验作为司法管辖权的唯一衡量标准。其他人则希望联邦成分测试能得到澄清。还有一些人,如本作者,希望法院将管辖权分析转向曾经推动联邦问题管辖权的传统基本原则。正如我在文章中所解释的那样,每个人都会对结果感到失望。冈恩案中具体的管辖权问题集中在被称为“格拉布尔检验”的第三和第四个方面,即,原告的州法索赔中包含的联邦成分是否实质性,以及对该索赔行使管辖权是否会打破国会规定的联邦法院和州法院之间的平衡。下级法院一直在努力解释和适用这两方面。有些州采用了详细和高度技术性的理论检验,导致违反直觉的结果,即否认对公认的"重大"联邦问题的管辖权。其他人则采用了一种更全面的方法,似乎是为了应用格拉布尔测试而设计的,同时避免了该测试明显的局限性。一些下级法院实际上承认管辖权的确定是主观的和推测性的,在类似的情况下,不同的法官可能得出不同的结论。虽然Gunn法院确实处理了Grable的这两个方面,但它除了支持之前对这些要素的迭代之外,几乎没有做什么,既没有为这些要素提供辩护,也没有提供适用这些要素的原则方法。因此,在冈恩案之前,关于联邦司法标准的许多困惑在很大程度上仍未得到解决。在本文中,我首先评估了管辖权下产生的成文法的发展,从其19世纪的根源到法院最近的判决。在这里,我将考察由最高法院在基础诉讼案件中发展起来的基本原则指南针,并由大法官卡多佐(Cardozo)在Meridian的Gully v. First Nat Bank一案中简洁地综合。在该案中,最高法院认可了一种统一的管辖权理论,该理论侧重于联邦问题在案件中的作用,询问案件是否真正涉及联邦法律,因为如果案件确实涉及联邦法律,管辖权的行使将与国会为联邦问题案件提供论坛的意图内在地一致。以这一基本原则模型为基础,我接着考察了最近出现的案例,并表明,从20世纪80年代开始,指南针迷失了方向,取而代之的是一堆越来越复杂的理论测试,与逻辑和成熟的司法原则脱节。在这里,焦点从争议的联邦性质转移到一种政策驱动的模式,这种模式严重偏重于案件管理问题。冈恩为最高法院提供了一个重新获得指南针的机会,或者,至少,提供一个可理解的地图,帮助下级联邦法院在司法创造的迷宫中导航。但是,本院错过了这个机会。相反,最高法院继续沿着一条偏离管辖权基本原则的曲折的理论道路前进,其结果往往与国会规定的为解释和适用联邦法律原则提供一个联邦论坛的目标不符。
{"title":"A Modified Theory of the Law of Federal Courts: The Case of Arising under Jurisdiction","authors":"S. Grossi","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2223523","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2223523","url":null,"abstract":"On February 20, 2013, the Supreme Court announced its decision in Gunn v. Minton. There the Court revisited the scope of statutory “arising under” jurisdiction in the context of a legal malpractice suit premised on alleged attorney errors committed in a prior patent litigation. The significance of the decision transcends the specific context in which it arose. Although Gunn involved patent law arising under jurisdiction, 28 U.S.C. §1338, that jurisdictional standard is interpreted in precisely the same manner as the identically worded §1331 standard. Hence, the decision in Gunn applies to a full range of federal question cases in which a federal issue is embedded in a state-law claim. In addition, Gunn provides insight into the ongoing clash between principle and docket-management concerns that has become so characteristic of Supreme Court decisions in the realm of procedure.The Gunn opinion was much anticipated by the legal community since prior decisions by the Court had generated considerable confusion as to the scope of arising under jurisdiction in so-called “federal-ingredient” cases. Some commentators hoped that the Court would adopt the creation test as the exclusive measure of jurisdiction. Others hoped for a clarification of the federal-ingredient test. Still others, like this author, hoped that the Court would redirect the jurisdictional analysis to the traditional fundamental principles that once animated federal question jurisdiction. As I explain in my article, everyone will be disappointed by the result. The specific jurisdictional issue in Gunn focused on what had come to be known as the third and fourth prongs of the “Grable test,” namely, whether the federal ingredient embedded in the plaintiff’s state-law claim was substantial and whether the exercise of jurisdiction over that claim would upset the congressionally mandated balance between federal and state courts. Lower courts had been struggling with the interpretation and application of both prongs. Some had adopted detailed and highly technical doctrinal tests that led to counterintuitive results where jurisdiction was denied over concededly “significant” federal questions. Others had adopted a more holistic approach, seemingly designed to apply Grable test and, at the same time, avoid that test’s obvious strictures.Some lower courts actually confessed that the jurisdictional determination was subjective and speculative and that, under similar circumstances, different judges might reach different conclusions. While the Gunn Court did address both Grable prongs, it did little other than endorse its previous iterations of those elements, providing neither a defense for them nor a principled method through which they might be applied. Thus, much of the confusion over federal jurisdictional standards that preceded Gunn remains largely unresolved.In this article, I begin by assessing the development of statutory arising under jurisdiction from its nineteenth century roots to the ","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"88 1","pages":"961"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2013-02-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68005108","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Unpacking New Policing: Confessions of a Former Neighborhood District Attorney 拆解新警务:一位前地区检察官的自白
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2012-07-23 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.436580
Alafair S. Burke
This Article attempts to reframe a burgeoning scholarly debate about the appropriateness of neighborhood self-governance as both a means to local crime control and a normatively worthy end in itself. On one side of the existing debate stands an emerging and influential group of "new discretion" scholars, who defend the delegation of discretion to police officers attempting to enforce social norms that are often ambiguous. These scholars argue that the support and involvement of so-called "communities" in such law enforcement efforts can be an adequate substitute for traditional judicial scrutiny of police discretion, particularly the prohibition against vague criminal laws. On the other side of the debate are traditional civil libertarians who view norm-based policing and the theories of self-governance underlying it as thinly disguised forms of majoritarianism. This Article has two primary goals. One goal is to use the author's experience as a community-based prosecutor to critique the new discretion scholars' reliance upon malleable notions of community to determine the legality of police programs. The second goal is to develop a more meaningful distinction among new policing efforts. Specifically, this Article advocates a distinction between civil and criminal initiatives. This approach would retain the existing prohibition against vague criminal laws. However, it would permit cities to implement strategies requiring police discretion, as long as those strategies avoid traditional criminal investigation, prosecution, and punishment. Such an approach would force cities either to adopt nontraditional responses to public safety problems or to be scrutinized under the traditional rules governing criminal law and procedure.
本文试图重新构建一种新兴的学术辩论,即社区自治作为一种控制当地犯罪的手段和本身具有规范价值的目的的适当性。在现有的争论中,有一个新兴的、有影响力的“新自由裁量权”学者团体站在一边,他们为将自由裁量权授权给试图执行往往模棱两可的社会规范的警察辩护。这些学者认为,所谓“社区”对这种执法工作的支持和参与可以充分取代对警察自由裁量权的传统司法审查,特别是禁止含糊的刑法。辩论的另一方是传统的公民自由主义者,他们认为以规范为基础的警务和其背后的自治理论是几乎不加掩饰的多数主义形式。本文有两个主要目标。一个目标是利用作者作为社区检察官的经验来批评新的自由裁量权学者依赖可塑的社区概念来确定警察计划的合法性。第二个目标是在新的警务工作之间建立更有意义的区别。具体而言,本文主张区分民事主动与刑事主动。这种做法将保留现有的禁止含糊的刑法的规定。然而,它将允许城市实施需要警察自由裁量权的策略,只要这些策略避免传统的刑事调查、起诉和惩罚。这种做法将迫使城市要么对公共安全问题采取非传统的应对措施,要么接受传统的刑法和刑事诉讼规则的审查。
{"title":"Unpacking New Policing: Confessions of a Former Neighborhood District Attorney","authors":"Alafair S. Burke","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.436580","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.436580","url":null,"abstract":"This Article attempts to reframe a burgeoning scholarly debate about the appropriateness of neighborhood self-governance as both a means to local crime control and a normatively worthy end in itself. On one side of the existing debate stands an emerging and influential group of \"new discretion\" scholars, who defend the delegation of discretion to police officers attempting to enforce social norms that are often ambiguous. These scholars argue that the support and involvement of so-called \"communities\" in such law enforcement efforts can be an adequate substitute for traditional judicial scrutiny of police discretion, particularly the prohibition against vague criminal laws. On the other side of the debate are traditional civil libertarians who view norm-based policing and the theories of self-governance underlying it as thinly disguised forms of majoritarianism. This Article has two primary goals. One goal is to use the author's experience as a community-based prosecutor to critique the new discretion scholars' reliance upon malleable notions of community to determine the legality of police programs. The second goal is to develop a more meaningful distinction among new policing efforts. Specifically, this Article advocates a distinction between civil and criminal initiatives. This approach would retain the existing prohibition against vague criminal laws. However, it would permit cities to implement strategies requiring police discretion, as long as those strategies avoid traditional criminal investigation, prosecution, and punishment. Such an approach would force cities either to adopt nontraditional responses to public safety problems or to be scrutinized under the traditional rules governing criminal law and procedure.","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"78 1","pages":"985"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2012-07-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68781435","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Understanding the First Amendment 理解第一修正案
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2012-06-01 DOI: 10.4135/9781452229843.n2
R. Post
It is a rare privilege to be read and engaged by such thoughtful and insightful commentators as the Washington Law Review has assembled. It is exhilarating to participate in a conversation of this range and intensity. I am very grateful to the Washington Law Review, Ronald K.L. Collins and David Skover, and the University of Washington School of Law, for making this symposium possible. As I read the contributions to this symposium, I am put in mind of Oliver Wendell Holmes' famous injunction that "[w]e must think things not words, or at least we must constantly translate our words into the facts for which they stand, if we are to keep to the real and the true."1 Although lawyers love words and language, "the real justification of a rule of law," Holmes argued, "is that it helps to bring about a social end which we desire."2 Holmes' advice was to pay close attention to whether our legal words in fact function to serve our social ends. Nowhere is the disjunction between words and ends more apparent than in First Amendment jurisprudence. We suffer from First Amendment hypertrophy. Doctrine proliferates endlessly and meaninglessly. Around every corner is yet another confusing First Amendment "test." We barely ever stop to ask what social ends are actually served by this barrage of inconsistent and abstract doctrine. We rarely take time to "translate our [First Amendment] words into the facts for which they stand." The illuminating contribution of Bruce E.H. Johnson and Sarah K. Duran3 seems fortunately almost immune from this affliction. Strategic Lawsuits Against Public Participation (SLAPPs) are theoretically interesting precisely because they illustrate the disjunction between legal words and social ends. Plaintiffs bring SLAPP suits to enforce rights created by substantive legal doctrine. Substantive legal doctrine, especially when subject to constitutional standards that determine whether particular speech acts should receive First Amendment immunity, ought accurately to reflect our values. At first blush, therefore, SLAPP suits ought not to be problematic; defendants should prevail whenever constitutional standards provide that their speech deserves constitutional protection. This way of thinking, however, does not pay sufficient attention to how legal standards actually function. It fails to appreciate the transaction costs associated with litigation enforcing substantive doctrine. Defending even an unmeritorious suit can be costly and timeconsuming, and this expense will likely discourage otherwise protected participation in public discussion. The anti-SLAPP statutes Johnson and Duran discuss are designed to address and nullify such transaction costs. They not only shift attorneys' fees, but they also create pathways for the "prompt and inexpensive" resolution of SLAPP suits.4 Johnson and Duran invite us to theorize the actual behavioral effects of enforcing substantive First Amendment standards; they direct our attention to the reality that
能被《华盛顿法律评论》这样有思想、有见地的评论员阅读和参与是一种难得的荣幸。参与到这种范围和强度的对话中是令人振奋的。我非常感谢《华盛顿法律评论》、Ronald K.L. Collins和David Skover以及华盛顿大学法学院使这次研讨会成为可能。当我读到这次研讨会的投稿时,我想起了奥利弗·温德尔·霍姆斯(Oliver Wendell Holmes)的著名训令:“我们必须思考事物而不是语言,或者至少我们必须不断地将我们的语言转化为它们所代表的事实,如果我们要坚持真实和真实的话。”虽然律师喜欢文字和语言,但霍姆斯认为,“法治的真正理由在于,它有助于实现我们所希望的社会目标。”福尔摩斯的建议是要密切关注我们的法律词汇是否实际上服务于我们的社会目的。在第一修正案的判例中,词语和词尾之间的脱节最为明显。我们受到第一修正案肥大症的困扰。教义无休止地、毫无意义地扩散。在每个角落都有另一个令人困惑的第一修正案“测试”。我们几乎从来没有停下来问过,这些不一致的抽象教条实际上是为了什么社会目的服务的。我们很少花时间“把我们的(第一修正案)文字翻译成它们所代表的事实”。幸运的是,布鲁斯·e·h·约翰逊和萨拉·k·杜兰的富有启发性的贡献似乎几乎没有受到这种困扰。反对公众参与的战略诉讼(SLAPPs)在理论上是有趣的,因为它们说明了法律用语与社会目的之间的脱节。原告提起SLAPP诉讼是为了执行实体法原则所赋予的权利。实体法理论,特别是在确定特定言论行为是否应获得第一修正案豁免的宪法标准的情况下,应该准确地反映我们的价值观。因此,乍一看,SLAPP诉讼应该没有问题;只要宪法标准规定被告的言论应受到宪法保护,被告就应占上风。然而,这种思维方式没有对法律标准的实际作用给予足够的重视。它未能认识到与执行实体原则的诉讼相关的交易成本。即使是为不值得的诉讼辩护也可能是昂贵和耗时的,而且这种费用可能会阻碍原本受保护的公众讨论的参与。Johnson和Duran讨论的反slapp法规旨在解决和消除此类交易成本。它们不仅降低了律师费,而且还为SLAPP诉讼的“迅速和廉价”解决创造了途径约翰逊和杜兰邀请我们理论化执行第一修正案实质性标准的实际行为影响;它们将我们的注意力引向教义背后的现实。第一修正案的实质性规则应该考虑第一修正案权利诉讼的交易成本,这是一种深刻的见解。它最终源于福尔摩斯启发的法律现实主义。约翰逊和杜兰关注的是执行第一修正案原则的成本如何影响公众话语的实际参与。美国最高法院系统地以这种方式进行推理的第一个判决是《纽约时报公司诉沙利文案》(New York Times Co. v. Sullivan),该案确立了“实际恶意”规则,正是为了使诽谤诉讼的交易成本无效它设计了实际恶意规则,以预测和消除诽谤责任的普通和其他宪法上可辩护的实质性规则的“寒蝉效应”。约翰逊和杜兰分析的反slapp法规是为了达到完全相同的结果而制定的立法干预措施反slapp法规预见并消除了第一修正案诉讼所产生的寒蝉效应。…
{"title":"Understanding the First Amendment","authors":"R. Post","doi":"10.4135/9781452229843.n2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4135/9781452229843.n2","url":null,"abstract":"It is a rare privilege to be read and engaged by such thoughtful and insightful commentators as the Washington Law Review has assembled. It is exhilarating to participate in a conversation of this range and intensity. I am very grateful to the Washington Law Review, Ronald K.L. Collins and David Skover, and the University of Washington School of Law, for making this symposium possible. As I read the contributions to this symposium, I am put in mind of Oliver Wendell Holmes' famous injunction that \"[w]e must think things not words, or at least we must constantly translate our words into the facts for which they stand, if we are to keep to the real and the true.\"1 Although lawyers love words and language, \"the real justification of a rule of law,\" Holmes argued, \"is that it helps to bring about a social end which we desire.\"2 Holmes' advice was to pay close attention to whether our legal words in fact function to serve our social ends. Nowhere is the disjunction between words and ends more apparent than in First Amendment jurisprudence. We suffer from First Amendment hypertrophy. Doctrine proliferates endlessly and meaninglessly. Around every corner is yet another confusing First Amendment \"test.\" We barely ever stop to ask what social ends are actually served by this barrage of inconsistent and abstract doctrine. We rarely take time to \"translate our [First Amendment] words into the facts for which they stand.\" The illuminating contribution of Bruce E.H. Johnson and Sarah K. Duran3 seems fortunately almost immune from this affliction. Strategic Lawsuits Against Public Participation (SLAPPs) are theoretically interesting precisely because they illustrate the disjunction between legal words and social ends. Plaintiffs bring SLAPP suits to enforce rights created by substantive legal doctrine. Substantive legal doctrine, especially when subject to constitutional standards that determine whether particular speech acts should receive First Amendment immunity, ought accurately to reflect our values. At first blush, therefore, SLAPP suits ought not to be problematic; defendants should prevail whenever constitutional standards provide that their speech deserves constitutional protection. This way of thinking, however, does not pay sufficient attention to how legal standards actually function. It fails to appreciate the transaction costs associated with litigation enforcing substantive doctrine. Defending even an unmeritorious suit can be costly and timeconsuming, and this expense will likely discourage otherwise protected participation in public discussion. The anti-SLAPP statutes Johnson and Duran discuss are designed to address and nullify such transaction costs. They not only shift attorneys' fees, but they also create pathways for the \"prompt and inexpensive\" resolution of SLAPP suits.4 Johnson and Duran invite us to theorize the actual behavioral effects of enforcing substantive First Amendment standards; they direct our attention to the reality that ","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"87 1","pages":"549"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2012-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70584819","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Precaution, Science, and Learning While Doing in Natural Resource Management 自然资源管理中的预防、科学与边学边做
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2007-04-24 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.982203
H. Doremus
Dealing with uncertainty is widely recognized as the key challenge for environmental and natural resource decision-making. Too often, though, that challenge is considered only from an ex ante perspective, treating uncertainty as an invariant feature that must be accounted for but cannot be changed. With respect to many natural resource management decisions, that picture is misleading. Decisions which are iterative or similar can provide significant opportunities for learning. Where such opportunities are available and inaction is not feasible or desirable, learning while doing can provide the benefits of both the precautionary principle and scientific decision-making, while minimizing the key weaknesses of each. After highlighting the benefits of a learning-while-doing approach for natural resource management, this paper briefly addresses how management agencies might be encouraged to adopt such an approach.
处理不确定性被广泛认为是环境和自然资源决策的关键挑战。然而,这种挑战往往只是从事前的角度来考虑的,将不确定性视为必须考虑但不能改变的不变特征。就许多自然资源管理决定而言,这种情况具有误导性。迭代或相似的决策可以提供重要的学习机会。在有这种机会而不采取行动是不可行的或不可取的情况下,边做边学可以提供预防原则和科学决策的好处,同时尽量减少两者的主要弱点。在强调了边做边学的自然资源管理方法的好处之后,本文简要介绍了如何鼓励管理机构采用这种方法。
{"title":"Precaution, Science, and Learning While Doing in Natural Resource Management","authors":"H. Doremus","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.982203","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.982203","url":null,"abstract":"Dealing with uncertainty is widely recognized as the key challenge for environmental and natural resource decision-making. Too often, though, that challenge is considered only from an ex ante perspective, treating uncertainty as an invariant feature that must be accounted for but cannot be changed. With respect to many natural resource management decisions, that picture is misleading. Decisions which are iterative or similar can provide significant opportunities for learning. Where such opportunities are available and inaction is not feasible or desirable, learning while doing can provide the benefits of both the precautionary principle and scientific decision-making, while minimizing the key weaknesses of each. After highlighting the benefits of a learning-while-doing approach for natural resource management, this paper briefly addresses how management agencies might be encouraged to adopt such an approach.","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"82 1","pages":"547"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2007-04-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67923512","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 32
Jurisdiction and Merits 管辖权及是非曲直
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2005-08-19 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.680565
H. Wasserman
Federal courts frequently make the mistake of treating factual elements of federal causes of action as going to the jurisdiction of the federal court; courts hold that the failure to prove some element requires dismissal of the civil action for lack of subject matter jurisdiction, rather than for failure to state a claim. This arises most frequently as to elements in three federal causes of action: the quantum-of-employees element in employment discrimination claims, the "affecting commerce" element under the Sherman Act, and the state action requirement in constitutional actions. Characterizing a factual issue as going to jurisdiction (the power or authority of a court to hear and resolve the dispute between the parties) or substantive merits of the cause of action (going to who should win the case and why) affects the time and manner in which that issue is adjudicated and resolved within the litigation process. It also implicates the basic positivist imperative of treating distinct legal conceptions in a distinct manner. The solution is a plain-language, positive-law approach to the separation of jurisdiction and merits. A court determines its subject matter jurisdiction by examining the language of the jurisdiction-granting statute, the statute enacted pursuant to Congress' structural power and empowering the court to hear and resolve civil actions. All other facts that may come into play in the case are relevant solely to the underlying substantive cause of action and to whether the plaintiff has established a violation of rights entitling her to relief. These facts, if disputed, await resolution at full trial on the merits.
联邦法院经常错误地将联邦诉因的事实要素视为属于联邦法院的管辖权;法院认为,不能证明某些要件的,可以因缺乏标的管辖权而驳回民事诉讼,而不是因未提出索赔而驳回民事诉讼。这种情况最常出现在三个联邦诉因中的要素:就业歧视索赔中的雇员数量要素,《谢尔曼法》下的“影响商业”要素,以及宪法诉讼中的州行动要求。将事实问题定性为管辖权(法院审理和解决当事人之间争议的权力或权威)或诉因的实质是非(谁应该赢得案件以及为什么)会影响该问题在诉讼过程中裁决和解决的时间和方式。它还暗示了以不同方式对待不同法律概念的基本实证主义必要性。解决的办法是用通俗易懂的语言、实在法的方法来区分管辖权和是非对错。法院通过审查授予管辖权的法规的语言来确定其主体管辖权,该法规是根据国会的结构性权力制定的,并授权法院审理和解决民事诉讼。在案件中可能起作用的所有其他事实仅与潜在的实质性诉因有关,并与原告是否认定侵犯了她有权获得救济的权利有关。这些事实如有争议,待根据是非曲直进行充分审判后解决。
{"title":"Jurisdiction and Merits","authors":"H. Wasserman","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.680565","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.680565","url":null,"abstract":"Federal courts frequently make the mistake of treating factual elements of federal causes of action as going to the jurisdiction of the federal court; courts hold that the failure to prove some element requires dismissal of the civil action for lack of subject matter jurisdiction, rather than for failure to state a claim. This arises most frequently as to elements in three federal causes of action: the quantum-of-employees element in employment discrimination claims, the \"affecting commerce\" element under the Sherman Act, and the state action requirement in constitutional actions. Characterizing a factual issue as going to jurisdiction (the power or authority of a court to hear and resolve the dispute between the parties) or substantive merits of the cause of action (going to who should win the case and why) affects the time and manner in which that issue is adjudicated and resolved within the litigation process. It also implicates the basic positivist imperative of treating distinct legal conceptions in a distinct manner. The solution is a plain-language, positive-law approach to the separation of jurisdiction and merits. A court determines its subject matter jurisdiction by examining the language of the jurisdiction-granting statute, the statute enacted pursuant to Congress' structural power and empowering the court to hear and resolve civil actions. All other facts that may come into play in the case are relevant solely to the underlying substantive cause of action and to whether the plaintiff has established a violation of rights entitling her to relief. These facts, if disputed, await resolution at full trial on the merits.","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"80 1","pages":"643"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2005-08-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67797530","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
On Apology and Consilience 论道歉与和解
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2002-07-24 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.320110
E. O'Connor, Douglas H. Yarn
This article chimes in on the current debate about the proper relationship between apology and the law. Several states are considering legislation designed to shield apologies from the courtroom, and mediators are increasing their focus on the importance of apologies. The article develops an evolutionary economic analysis of apology that combines the tools of economics, game theory and biology to more fully understand its role in dispute resolution. When the analysis is applied to the uses of apology before and at trial, a more sophisticated understanding of the relationship between apology and the law emerges.
这篇文章对当前关于道歉与法律之间的适当关系的争论进行了回应。几个州正在考虑立法,以避免道歉在法庭上发生,调解人也越来越关注道歉的重要性。本文结合经济学、博弈论和生物学的工具,对道歉进行了进化经济学分析,以更全面地理解道歉在争端解决中的作用。当这一分析应用于审判前和审判中道歉的使用时,对道歉与法律之间关系的更复杂的理解就出现了。
{"title":"On Apology and Consilience","authors":"E. O'Connor, Douglas H. Yarn","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.320110","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.320110","url":null,"abstract":"This article chimes in on the current debate about the proper relationship between apology and the law. Several states are considering legislation designed to shield apologies from the courtroom, and mediators are increasing their focus on the importance of apologies. The article develops an evolutionary economic analysis of apology that combines the tools of economics, game theory and biology to more fully understand its role in dispute resolution. When the analysis is applied to the uses of apology before and at trial, a more sophisticated understanding of the relationship between apology and the law emerges.","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"77 1","pages":"1121-1192"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2002-07-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.320110","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68573470","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 44
The Asymmetry of State Sovereign Immunity 国家主权豁免的不对称
IF 1.3 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2001-06-14 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.271791
R. Seamon
This article discusses whether a State has sovereign immunity from claims for just compensation. The article concludes that the States are indeed immune from just-compensation suits brought against them in federal court; States are not necessarily immune, however, from just-compensation suits brought against them in their own courts of general jurisdiction. Thus, the States' immunity in federal court is not symmetrical to the States' immunity in their own courts. This asymmetry, the article explains, is the result of the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The Due Process Clause obligates a State to provide just compensation every time the State takes private property for public use. A State may be able to meet that obligation through a non-judicial compensation scheme. If a State fails to establish an adequate non-judicial scheme for providing just compensation, the State's remedial obligation falls upon the State's courts. A State's courts thereby play an important role in enabling the State to meet its due process obligations. Unlike a State's own courts, the federal courts cannot enable a State to meet the State's due process obligations. Thus, the existence of a federal-court remedy does not excuse the State's failure to provide its own remedies. By the same token, the absence of a federal-court remedy for a State's failure to pay constitutionally required just compensation does not imply the absence of a remedy in the State's own courts. For this reason, the Supreme Court case law indicating that States are immune from just-compensation suits brought in federal court does not support recognizing a similar immunity in a State's own courts.
该条讨论国家是否对公正赔偿要求享有主权豁免。文章的结论是,各州确实免于联邦法院对其提起的公正赔偿诉讼;然而,国家不一定不受在本国具有一般管辖权的法院对其提起的公正赔偿诉讼的影响。因此,各州在联邦法院的豁免与各州在本国法院的豁免是不对称的。文章解释说,这种不对称是宪法第十四修正案的正当程序条款造成的。正当程序条款要求各州在每次将私有财产用于公共用途时提供公正的赔偿。一个国家也许能够通过非司法赔偿办法来履行这项义务。如果一个国家未能制定提供公正赔偿的适当的非司法办法,则该国的补救义务由其法院承担。因此,一国法院在使该国能够履行其正当程序义务方面发挥着重要作用。与各州的法院不同,联邦法院不能使各州履行其正当程序义务。因此,联邦法院补救办法的存在并不能成为国家不提供自己的补救办法的借口。出于同样的原因,对一个州未能支付宪法所要求的公正赔偿而没有联邦法院的补救并不意味着在该州自己的法院没有补救。因此,最高法院的判例法指出,各州对联邦法院提起的公正赔偿诉讼享有豁免权,这并不支持在各州法院承认类似的豁免权。
{"title":"The Asymmetry of State Sovereign Immunity","authors":"R. Seamon","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.271791","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.271791","url":null,"abstract":"This article discusses whether a State has sovereign immunity from claims for just compensation. The article concludes that the States are indeed immune from just-compensation suits brought against them in federal court; States are not necessarily immune, however, from just-compensation suits brought against them in their own courts of general jurisdiction. Thus, the States' immunity in federal court is not symmetrical to the States' immunity in their own courts. This asymmetry, the article explains, is the result of the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The Due Process Clause obligates a State to provide just compensation every time the State takes private property for public use. A State may be able to meet that obligation through a non-judicial compensation scheme. If a State fails to establish an adequate non-judicial scheme for providing just compensation, the State's remedial obligation falls upon the State's courts. A State's courts thereby play an important role in enabling the State to meet its due process obligations. Unlike a State's own courts, the federal courts cannot enable a State to meet the State's due process obligations. Thus, the existence of a federal-court remedy does not excuse the State's failure to provide its own remedies. By the same token, the absence of a federal-court remedy for a State's failure to pay constitutionally required just compensation does not imply the absence of a remedy in the State's own courts. For this reason, the Supreme Court case law indicating that States are immune from just-compensation suits brought in federal court does not support recognizing a similar immunity in a State's own courts.","PeriodicalId":46514,"journal":{"name":"Washington Law Review","volume":"6 1","pages":"1067"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2001-06-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68271539","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Washington Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1