We show that for quasivarieties of p-algebras the properties of (i) having decidable first-order theory and (ii) having decidable first-order theory of the finite members, coincide. The only two quasivarieties with these properties are the trivial variety and the variety of Boolean algebras. This contrasts sharply, even for varieties, with the situation in Heyting algebras where decidable varieties do not coincide with finitely decidable ones.
{"title":"Decidable quasivarieties of p-algebras","authors":"Tomasz Kowalski, Katarzyna Słomczyńska","doi":"10.1002/malq.202300064","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202300064","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We show that for quasivarieties of p-algebras the properties of (i) having decidable first-order theory and (ii) having decidable first-order theory of the finite members, coincide. The only two quasivarieties with these properties are the trivial variety and the variety of Boolean algebras. This contrasts sharply, even for varieties, with the situation in Heyting algebras where decidable varieties do not coincide with finitely decidable ones.</p>","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"71 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2025-02-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"143380336","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
<p>In this paper, we examine the locality condition for non-splitting and determine the level of uniqueness of limit models that can be recovered in some stable, but not superstable, abstract elementary classes. In particular we prove the following. Suppose that <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>K</mi> <annotation>$mathcal {K}$</annotation> </semantics></math> is an abstract elementary class satisfying </p><p>Then for <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>ϑ</mi> <annotation>$vartheta$</annotation> </semantics></math> and <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>δ</mi> <annotation>$delta$</annotation> </semantics></math> limit ordinals <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mo><</mo> <msup> <mi>μ</mi> <mo>+</mo> </msup> </mrow> <annotation>$<mu ^+$</annotation> </semantics></math> both with cofinality <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mo>≥</mo> <msubsup> <mi>κ</mi> <mi>μ</mi> <mo>∗</mo> </msubsup> <mrow> <mo>(</mo> <mi>K</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> </mrow> <annotation>$ge kappa ^*_mu (mathcal {K})$</annotation> </semantics></math>, if <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>K</mi> <annotation>$mathcal {K}$</annotation> </semantics></math> satisfies symmetry for <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mi>non</mi> <mi>-</mi> <mi>μ</mi> <mi>-</mi> <mi>splitting</mi> </mrow> <annotation>${rm non}text{-}mutext{-}{rm splitting}$</annotation> </semantics></math> (or just <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mo>(</mo> <mi>μ</mi> <mo>,</mo> <mi>δ</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <annotation>$(mu,delta)$</annotation> </semantics></math>-symmetry), then, for any <span></span><math> <semantics> <msub> <mi>M</mi> <mn>1</mn> </msub> <annotation>$M_1$</annotation> </semantics></math>
{"title":"Limit models in strictly stable abstract elementary classes","authors":"Will Boney, Monica M. VanDieren","doi":"10.1002/malq.202200075","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202200075","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In this paper, we examine the locality condition for non-splitting and determine the level of uniqueness of limit models that can be recovered in some stable, but not superstable, abstract elementary classes. In particular we prove the following. Suppose that <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>K</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$mathcal {K}$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> is an abstract elementary class satisfying\u0000\u0000 </p><p>Then for <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>ϑ</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$vartheta$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> and <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>δ</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$delta$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> limit ordinals <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo><</mo>\u0000 <msup>\u0000 <mi>μ</mi>\u0000 <mo>+</mo>\u0000 </msup>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$<mu ^+$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> both with cofinality <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>≥</mo>\u0000 <msubsup>\u0000 <mi>κ</mi>\u0000 <mi>μ</mi>\u0000 <mo>∗</mo>\u0000 </msubsup>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>K</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$ge kappa ^*_mu (mathcal {K})$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, if <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>K</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$mathcal {K}$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> satisfies symmetry for <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>non</mi>\u0000 <mi>-</mi>\u0000 <mi>μ</mi>\u0000 <mi>-</mi>\u0000 <mi>splitting</mi>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>${rm non}text{-}mutext{-}{rm splitting}$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> (or just <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>μ</mi>\u0000 <mo>,</mo>\u0000 <mi>δ</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$(mu,delta)$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>-symmetry), then, for any <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <msub>\u0000 <mi>M</mi>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 </msub>\u0000 <annotation>$M_1$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> ","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 4","pages":"438-453"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-12-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/malq.202200075","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142859918","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
This paper explores the coloring problem, focusing on the existence of uniformly colored substructures. The study primarily examines random graphs with edge coloring and their generic substructures. The key finding is that the absence of a monochromatic generic substructure corresponds to increased instability, meaning that the colored random graph hereditarily possesses the strict order property.
{"title":"Random graph coloring and the instability","authors":"Akito Tsuboi","doi":"10.1002/malq.202300043","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202300043","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper explores the coloring problem, focusing on the existence of uniformly colored substructures. The study primarily examines random graphs with edge coloring and their generic substructures. The key finding is that the absence of a monochromatic generic substructure corresponds to increased instability, meaning that the colored random graph hereditarily possesses the strict order property.</p>","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 4","pages":"429-437"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-11-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142861169","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
We classify all apartness relations definable in propositional logics extending intuitionistic logic using Heyting algebra semantics. We show that every Heyting algebra which contains a non-trivial apartness term satisfies the weak law of excluded middle, and every Heyting algebra which contains a tight apartness term is in fact a Boolean algebra. This answers a question of Rijke regarding the correct notion of apartness for propositions, and yields a short classification of apartness terms that can occur in a Heyting algebra. We also show that Martin-Löf Type Theory is not able to construct non-trivial apartness relations between propositions.
{"title":"Apartness relations between propositions","authors":"Zoltan A. Kocsis","doi":"10.1002/malq.202300055","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202300055","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We classify all apartness relations definable in propositional logics extending intuitionistic logic using Heyting algebra semantics. We show that every Heyting algebra which contains a non-trivial apartness term satisfies the weak law of excluded middle, and every Heyting algebra which contains a tight apartness term is in fact a Boolean algebra. This answers a question of Rijke regarding the correct notion of apartness for propositions, and yields a short classification of apartness terms that can occur in a Heyting algebra. We also show that Martin-Löf Type Theory is not able to construct non-trivial apartness relations between propositions.</p>","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 4","pages":"414-428"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-11-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142861168","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
We study model theoretic characterizations of various collection schemes over from the viewpoint of Gaifman's splitting theorem. Among other things, we prove that for any and , the following are equivalent:
我们从盖夫曼分裂定理的角度研究了 PA - $mathsf {PA}^-$ 上各种集合方案的模型论特征。其中,我们证明了对于任意 n ≥ 0 $n ge 0$ 和 M ⊧ PA - $M models mathsf {PA}^-$ ,以下内容是等价的:
{"title":"On collection schemes and Gaifman's splitting theorem","authors":"Taishi Kurahashi, Yoshiaki Minami","doi":"10.1002/malq.202400021","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202400021","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We study model theoretic characterizations of various collection schemes over <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <msup>\u0000 <mi>PA</mi>\u0000 <mo>−</mo>\u0000 </msup>\u0000 <annotation>$mathsf {PA}^-$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> from the viewpoint of Gaifman's splitting theorem. Among other things, we prove that for any <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>n</mi>\u0000 <mo>≥</mo>\u0000 <mn>0</mn>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$n ge 0$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> and <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>M</mi>\u0000 <mo>⊧</mo>\u0000 <msup>\u0000 <mi>PA</mi>\u0000 <mo>−</mo>\u0000 </msup>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$M models mathsf {PA}^-$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, the following are equivalent: \u0000\u0000 </p>","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 4","pages":"398-413"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-11-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142860882","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
<p>We analyze the behavior of a perfectly normal nonrealcompact space <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mo>(</mo> <msub> <mi>ω</mi> <mn>1</mn> </msub> <mo>,</mo> <mi>τ</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <annotation>$(omega _1, tau)$</annotation> </semantics></math> on <span></span><math> <semantics> <msub> <mi>ω</mi> <mn>1</mn> </msub> <annotation>$omega _1$</annotation> </semantics></math> such that for every <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mi>γ</mi> <mo><</mo> <msub> <mi>ω</mi> <mn>1</mn> </msub> </mrow> <annotation>$gamma <omega _1$</annotation> </semantics></math>, <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>γ</mi> <annotation>$gamma$</annotation> </semantics></math> is <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>τ</mi> <annotation>$tau$</annotation> </semantics></math>-open and <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mi>γ</mi> <mo>+</mo> <mi>ω</mi> </mrow> <annotation>$gamma +omega$</annotation> </semantics></math> is <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>τ</mi> <annotation>$tau$</annotation> </semantics></math>-closed under Martin's Maximum. We show that there exists a club subset <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>D</mi> <annotation>$D$</annotation> </semantics></math> of <span></span><math> <semantics> <msub> <mi>ω</mi> <mn>1</mn> </msub> <annotation>$omega _1$</annotation> </semantics></math> such that for a stationary subset of <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mi>δ</mi> <mo>∈</mo> <mo>acc</mo> <mo>(</mo> <mi>D</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <annotation>$delta in operatorname{acc}(D)$</annotation> </semantics></math>, for all <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>τ</mi> <annot
{"title":"Perfectly normal nonrealcompact spaces under Martin's Maximum","authors":"Tetsuya Ishiu","doi":"10.1002/malq.202400002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202400002","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We analyze the behavior of a perfectly normal nonrealcompact space <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <msub>\u0000 <mi>ω</mi>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 </msub>\u0000 <mo>,</mo>\u0000 <mi>τ</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$(omega _1, tau)$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> on <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <msub>\u0000 <mi>ω</mi>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 </msub>\u0000 <annotation>$omega _1$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> such that for every <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>γ</mi>\u0000 <mo><</mo>\u0000 <msub>\u0000 <mi>ω</mi>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 </msub>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$gamma <omega _1$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>γ</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$gamma$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> is <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>τ</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$tau$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>-open and <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>γ</mi>\u0000 <mo>+</mo>\u0000 <mi>ω</mi>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$gamma +omega$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> is <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>τ</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$tau$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>-closed under Martin's Maximum. We show that there exists a club subset <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>D</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$D$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> of <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <msub>\u0000 <mi>ω</mi>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 </msub>\u0000 <annotation>$omega _1$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> such that for a stationary subset of <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>δ</mi>\u0000 <mo>∈</mo>\u0000 <mo>acc</mo>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>D</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$delta in operatorname{acc}(D)$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, for all <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>τ</mi>\u0000 <annot","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 4","pages":"388-397"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-10-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/malq.202400002","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142861588","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
We study the meaning of “adding a constant to a language” for any doctrine, and “adding an axiom to a theory” for a primary doctrine, by showing how these are actually two instances of the same construction. We prove their universal properties, and how these constructions are compatible with additional structure on the doctrine. Existence of Kleisli object for comonads in the 2-category of indexed poset is proved in order to build these constructions.
{"title":"Adding a constant and an axiom to a doctrine","authors":"Francesca Guffanti","doi":"10.1002/malq.202300053","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202300053","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We study the meaning of “adding a constant to a language” for any doctrine, and “adding an axiom to a theory” for a primary doctrine, by showing how these are actually two instances of the same construction. We prove their universal properties, and how these constructions are compatible with additional structure on the doctrine. Existence of Kleisli object for comonads in the 2-category of indexed poset is proved in order to build these constructions.</p>","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 3","pages":"294-332"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-10-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142404689","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Denoting by the free group over a two-element alphabet, we show in set-theory without the axiom of choice that the existence of a (2, 2)-paradoxical decomposition of free -sets follows from the conjunction of a weakened consequence of the Hahn-Banach axiom and a weakened consequence of the axiom of choice for pairs. The existence in of a paradoxical decomposition with 4 pieces of the sphere in the 3-dimensional euclidean space follows from the same two statements restricted to the set of real numbers. Our result is linked to the -paradoxical decompositions of free -sets previously obtained by Pawlikowski (, cf. [11]) and then by Sato and Shioya ( and , cf. [13]) with the sole Hahn-Banach axiom.
{"title":"Paradoxical decompositions of free \u0000 \u0000 \u0000 F\u0000 2\u0000 \u0000 $F_2$\u0000 -sets and the Hahn-Banach axiom","authors":"Marianne Morillon","doi":"10.1002/malq.202400003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202400003","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Denoting by <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <msub>\u0000 <mi>F</mi>\u0000 <mn>2</mn>\u0000 </msub>\u0000 <annotation>$F_2$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> the free group over a two-element alphabet, we show in set-theory without the axiom of choice <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>ZF</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$mathsf {ZF}$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> that the existence of a (2, 2)-paradoxical decomposition of free <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <msub>\u0000 <mi>F</mi>\u0000 <mn>2</mn>\u0000 </msub>\u0000 <annotation>$F_2$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>-sets follows from the conjunction of a weakened consequence of the Hahn-Banach axiom and a weakened consequence of the axiom of choice for pairs. The existence in <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>ZF</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$mathsf {ZF}$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> of a paradoxical decomposition with 4 pieces of the sphere in the 3-dimensional euclidean space follows from the same two statements restricted to the set <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>R</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$mathbb {R}$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> of real numbers. Our result is linked to the <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>,</mo>\u0000 <mi>n</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$(m,n)$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>-paradoxical decompositions of free <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <msub>\u0000 <mi>F</mi>\u0000 <mn>2</mn>\u0000 </msub>\u0000 <annotation>$F_2$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>-sets previously obtained by Pawlikowski (<span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>=</mo>\u0000 <mi>n</mi>\u0000 <mo>=</mo>\u0000 <mn>3</mn>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$m=n=3$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, cf. [11]) and then by Sato and Shioya (<span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>=</mo>\u0000 <mn>3</mn>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$m=3$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> and <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>n</mi>\u0000 <mo>=</mo>\u0000 <mn>2</mn>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$n=2$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, cf. [13]) with the sole Hahn-Banach axiom.</p>","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 4","pages":"367-387"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-10-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142859986","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
We prove that any definable family of subsets of a definable infinite set in an o-minimal structure has cardinality at most . We derive some consequences in terms of counting definable types and existence of definable topological spaces.
证明了0 -极小结构中任意可定义无限集a $ a $的可定义子集族的基数不超过| a |$ | a |$。我们从可定义类型的计数和可定义拓扑空间的存在性方面得到了一些结果。
{"title":"A note on the cardinality of definable families of sets in o-minimal structures","authors":"Pablo Andújar Guerrero","doi":"10.1002/malq.202300030","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202300030","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We prove that any definable family of subsets of a definable infinite set <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>A</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$A$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> in an o-minimal structure has cardinality at most <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>|</mo>\u0000 <mi>A</mi>\u0000 <mo>|</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$|A|$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>. We derive some consequences in terms of counting definable types and existence of definable topological spaces.</p>","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 4","pages":"361-366"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/malq.202300030","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142862029","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
<p>In this paper, we investigate the relationships between the cardinalities of the set of injections, the set of surjections, and the set of all functions on a set which is of cardinality <span></span><math> <semantics> <mi>m</mi> <annotation>$mathfrak {m}$</annotation> </semantics></math>, denoted by <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mi>I</mi> <mo>(</mo> <mi>m</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <annotation>$I(mathfrak {m})$</annotation> </semantics></math>, <span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <mi>J</mi> <mo>(</mo> <mi>m</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <annotation>$J(mathfrak {m})$</annotation> </semantics></math> and <span></span><math> <semantics> <msup> <mi>m</mi> <mi>m</mi> </msup> <annotation>$mathfrak {m}^mathfrak {m}$</annotation> </semantics></math>, respectively. Among our results, we show that “<span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <msup> <mo>seq</mo> <mrow> <mn>1</mn> <mo>−</mo> <mn>1</mn> </mrow> </msup> <mrow> <mo>(</mo> <mi>m</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <mo>≠</mo> <mi>I</mi> <mrow> <mo>(</mo> <mi>m</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <mo>≠</mo> <mo>seq</mo> <mrow> <mo>(</mo> <mi>m</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> </mrow> <annotation>$operatorname{seq}^{1-1}(mathfrak {m})ne I(mathfrak {m})ne operatorname{seq}(mathfrak {m})$</annotation> </semantics></math>”, “<span></span><math> <semantics> <mrow> <msup> <mo>seq</mo> <mrow> <mn>1</mn> <mo>−</mo> <mn>1</mn> </mrow> </msup> <mrow> <mo>(</mo> <mi>m</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <mo>≠</mo> <mi>J</mi> <mrow> <mo>(</mo> <mi>m</mi> <mo>)</mo> </mrow> <mo>≠</
在本文中,我们研究了注入集合、射出集合和一个集合上所有函数的集合的心数之间的关系,这些集合的心数为 m $mathfrak {m}$,分别用 I ( m ) $I(mathfrak {m})$、J ( m ) $J(mathfrak {m})$和 m m $mathfrak {m}^mathfrak {m}$表示。Among our results, we show that “ seq 1 − 1 ( m ) ≠ I ( m ) ≠ seq ( m ) $operatorname{seq}^{1-1}(mathfrak {m})ne I(mathfrak {m})ne operatorname{seq}(mathfrak {m})$ ”, “ seq 1 − 1 ( m ) ≠ J ( m ) ≠ seq ( m ) $operatorname{seq}^{1-1}(mathfrak {m})ne J(mathfrak {m})ne operatorname{seq}(mathfrak {m})$ ” and “ seq 1 − 1 ( m ) < m m ≠ seq ( m ) $operatorname{seq}^{1-1}(mathfrak {m})<mathfrak {m}^mathfrak {m}ne operatorname{seq}(mathfrak {m})$ ” are provable for an arbitrary infinite cardinal m $mathfrak {m}$ , and these are the best possible results, in the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory ( ZF $mathsf {ZF}$ ) without the Axiom of Choice.另外,我们还证明,存在一个无限红心 m $mathfrak {m}$,使得 S ( m ) = I ( m ) <; J ( m ) $S(mathfrak {m})=I(mathfrak {m})<J(mathfrak {m})$ 其中 S ( m ) $S(mathfrak {m})$表示一个集合上双射集合的万有性,这个集合的万有性为 m $mathfrak {m}$ 。
{"title":"The set of injections and the set of surjections on a set","authors":"Natthajak Kamkru, Nattapon Sonpanow","doi":"10.1002/malq.202300059","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.202300059","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In this paper, we investigate the relationships between the cardinalities of the set of injections, the set of surjections, and the set of all functions on a set which is of cardinality <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <annotation>$mathfrak {m}$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, denoted by <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>I</mi>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$I(mathfrak {m})$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mi>J</mi>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$J(mathfrak {m})$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math> and <span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <msup>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 </msup>\u0000 <annotation>$mathfrak {m}^mathfrak {m}$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>, respectively. Among our results, we show that “<span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <msup>\u0000 <mo>seq</mo>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 <mo>−</mo>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 </msup>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <mo>≠</mo>\u0000 <mi>I</mi>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <mo>≠</mo>\u0000 <mo>seq</mo>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <annotation>$operatorname{seq}^{1-1}(mathfrak {m})ne I(mathfrak {m})ne operatorname{seq}(mathfrak {m})$</annotation>\u0000 </semantics></math>”, “<span></span><math>\u0000 <semantics>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <msup>\u0000 <mo>seq</mo>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 <mo>−</mo>\u0000 <mn>1</mn>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 </msup>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <mo>≠</mo>\u0000 <mi>J</mi>\u0000 <mrow>\u0000 <mo>(</mo>\u0000 <mi>m</mi>\u0000 <mo>)</mo>\u0000 </mrow>\u0000 <mo>≠</","PeriodicalId":49864,"journal":{"name":"Mathematical Logic Quarterly","volume":"70 3","pages":"275-285"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2024-09-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142404725","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}