首页 > 最新文献

Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Self Matters 自我很重要
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2617
M. Guillot, L. O'brien
We argue that relating to myself as me provides, as such, a reason to care about myself: grasping that an event involves me, instead of another, makes it matter in a special way. Further, this self-concern is not simply a matter of seeing in myself some instrumental value for other ends. We use as our foil a recent skeptical challenge to this view offered in Setiya (2015). We think the case against self-concern is powered by unwarrantedly narrow construals of three key notions. One is the notion of a first-personal way of relating to oneself. A narrow account of the first person in terms of special epistemic relations to oneself makes it easy to overlook a source of non-instrumental reasons of self-concern, located in the special relation a subject has to herself as agent. Two is the notion of what it is to be a reason. And three is the notion of self-concern itself. We show that the skeptical case rests in part on a slide towards neighbouring but distinct notions of egoism and selfishness. We also argue that Setiya’s notion of self-love, offered to capture the pre-theoretical intuition of self-concern, cannot do it justice.
我们认为,把我自己作为我来对待,提供了一个关心我自己的理由:抓住一个事件涉及到我,而不是别人,使它以一种特殊的方式重要。此外,这种自我关注不仅仅是在自己身上看到一些对其他目的的工具价值。我们用最近在Setiya(2015)中提出的对这一观点的质疑作为陪衬。我们认为,反对自我关注的理由是对三个关键概念的片面理解。一个是第一人称与自己联系的方式。从与自己的特殊认知关系的角度来狭隘地描述第一人称,很容易忽视自我关注的非工具原因的来源,它位于主体与作为主体的自己的特殊关系中。二是关于什么是理性的概念。第三是自我关注的概念本身。我们表明,怀疑的情况部分取决于滑向邻近但明显的利己主义和自私的概念。我们还认为,Setiya的自爱概念,是为了捕捉自我关注的前理论直觉,不能做到公正。
{"title":"Self Matters","authors":"M. Guillot, L. O'brien","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2617","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2617","url":null,"abstract":"We argue that relating to myself as me provides, as such, a reason to care about myself: grasping that an event involves me, instead of another, makes it matter in a special way. Further, this self-concern is not simply a matter of seeing in myself some instrumental value for other ends. We use as our foil a recent skeptical challenge to this view offered in Setiya (2015). We think the case against self-concern is powered by unwarrantedly narrow construals of three key notions. One is the notion of a first-personal way of relating to oneself. A narrow account of the first person in terms of special epistemic relations to oneself makes it easy to overlook a source of non-instrumental reasons of self-concern, located in the special relation a subject has to herself as agent. Two is the notion of what it is to be a reason. And three is the notion of self-concern itself. We show that the skeptical case rests in part on a slide towards neighbouring but distinct notions of egoism and selfishness. We also argue that Setiya’s notion of self-love, offered to capture the pre-theoretical intuition of self-concern, cannot do it justice.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82261907","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Spinoza on the Essences of Singular Things 斯宾诺莎论奇异事物的本质
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2266
Sebastian Bender
Essences play a central role in Spinoza’s philosophy, not only in his metaphysics, but also in his philosophy of mind, his theory of affects, and his political philosophy. Despite their importance, however, it is surprisingly difficult to determine what exactly essences are for Spinoza. On a widespread reading, the essence of X is nothing but the concept of X. This paper argues against this identification of essences and concepts. Spinozistic concepts are maximally inclusive: the concept of X contains everything that is needed to make X conceivable. The essence of X, in contrast, is more limited in scope and does not include everything that is needed to make X conceivable. Thus, Spinoza avoids the ‘overloading’ of essences and the problems that would ensue. The account developed in this paper has a surprising implication, namely that the essences of non-divine, singular things do not suffice to render these things fully conceivable on Spinoza’s view. Thus, Spinoza breaks with a tradition according to which the essence of a thing states ‘what the thing is.’ As a result, his conception of essence is much further removed from traditional Aristotelian accounts, and from other seventeenth-century accounts, than usually acknowledged.
本质在斯宾诺莎的哲学中起着核心作用,不仅在他的形而上学中,而且在他的心灵哲学,他的情感理论和他的政治哲学中。然而,尽管它们很重要,但要确定斯宾诺莎的本质究竟是什么却出奇地困难。在广泛的阅读中,X的本质只不过是X的概念。本文反对这种本质和概念的认同。斯宾诺莎的概念具有最大的包容性:X的概念包含了使X可以想象所需的一切。相比之下,X的本质在范围上更有限,不包括使X可以想象的所有东西。因此,斯宾诺莎避免了本质的“超载”和随之而来的问题。在这篇论文中发展的描述有一个令人惊讶的含义,即非神性的本质,奇异的事物并不足以使这些事物在斯宾诺莎的观点中完全可以想象。因此,斯宾诺莎打破了一种传统,根据这种传统,事物的本质陈述了“事物是什么”。因此,他的本质概念与传统的亚里士多德理论,以及其他17世纪的理论,有很大的不同。
{"title":"Spinoza on the Essences of Singular Things","authors":"Sebastian Bender","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2266","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2266","url":null,"abstract":"Essences play a central role in Spinoza’s philosophy, not only in his metaphysics, but also in his philosophy of mind, his theory of affects, and his political philosophy. Despite their importance, however, it is surprisingly difficult to determine what exactly essences are for Spinoza. On a widespread reading, the essence of X is nothing but the concept of X. This paper argues against this identification of essences and concepts. Spinozistic concepts are maximally inclusive: the concept of X contains everything that is needed to make X conceivable. The essence of X, in contrast, is more limited in scope and does not include everything that is needed to make X conceivable. Thus, Spinoza avoids the ‘overloading’ of essences and the problems that would ensue. The account developed in this paper has a surprising implication, namely that the essences of non-divine, singular things do not suffice to render these things fully conceivable on Spinoza’s view. Thus, Spinoza breaks with a tradition according to which the essence of a thing states ‘what the thing is.’ As a result, his conception of essence is much further removed from traditional Aristotelian accounts, and from other seventeenth-century accounts, than usually acknowledged.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89390704","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Eschatology and the Limits of Philosophy in the Phaedo 《斐多篇》中的末世论与哲学的局限
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2619
Travis Butler
An abiding puzzle in the Phaedo is the transition in the text from initial pessimism about the possibility of wisdom during human life to a more optimistic view. Prominent interpretations posit different kinds or degrees of wisdom at issue in the two sets of passages. By contrast, I argue that the pessimistic view rests on the implicit premise that the soul cannot be completely purified during human life—a premise which arises from an initial conception of impurity and its cause. In developing his eschatology, Socrates refines this conception and rejects the implicit premise. Because the embodied soul can be completely purified, it can achieve philosophical wisdom as well.
斐多篇中一个持久的谜题是文本从最初对人类生活中智慧可能性的悲观主义过渡到更乐观的观点。突出的解释在两组段落中提出了不同种类或程度的智慧。相比之下,我认为悲观的观点建立在一个隐含的前提上,即灵魂在人的一生中不可能完全净化——这个前提源于对不洁净及其原因的最初概念。在发展他的末世论时,苏格拉底精炼了这个概念,拒绝了隐含的前提。因为化身的灵魂可以得到完全的净化,它也可以获得哲学智慧。
{"title":"Eschatology and the Limits of Philosophy in the Phaedo","authors":"Travis Butler","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2619","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2619","url":null,"abstract":"An abiding puzzle in the Phaedo is the transition in the text from initial pessimism about the possibility of wisdom during human life to a more optimistic view. Prominent interpretations posit different kinds or degrees of wisdom at issue in the two sets of passages. By contrast, I argue that the pessimistic view rests on the implicit premise that the soul cannot be completely purified during human life—a premise which arises from an initial conception of impurity and its cause. In developing his eschatology, Socrates refines this conception and rejects the implicit premise. Because the embodied soul can be completely purified, it can achieve philosophical wisdom as well.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83542370","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Inconceivability Argument 不可思议的论点
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2268
Brian Cutter
This paper develops and defends a new argument against physicalist views of consciousness: the inconceivability argument. The argument has two main premises. First, it is not (ideally, positively) conceivable that phenomenal truths are grounded in physical truths. (For example, one cannot positively conceive of a situation in which someone has a vivid experience of pink wholly in virtue of the movements of colorless, insentient atoms.) Second, (ideal, positive) inconceivability is a guide to falsity. I attempt to show that the inconceivability argument enjoys a significant advantage over the more familiar conceivability argument. One can reasonably endorse the inconceivability argument without endorsing the conceivability argument, but one cannot reasonably endorse the conceivability argument without also endorsing the inconceivability argument.
本文提出并捍卫了一个反对物理主义意识观的新论点:不可思议论。这个论点有两个主要前提。首先,(理想的,积极的)不能想象现象真理是建立在物理真理的基础上的。(例如,一个人无法积极地想象这样一种情况:一个人完全凭借无色、无知觉的原子的运动而生动地体验到粉红色。)第二,(理想的,积极的)不可思议是虚假的向导。我试图证明不可思议论证比我们更熟悉的可想象论证有一个显著的优势。一个人可以合理地赞同不可想象的论点而不赞同可想象的论点,但一个人不能合理地赞同可想象的论点而不赞同不可想象的论点。
{"title":"The Inconceivability Argument","authors":"Brian Cutter","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2268","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2268","url":null,"abstract":"This paper develops and defends a new argument against physicalist views of consciousness: the inconceivability argument. The argument has two main premises. First, it is not (ideally, positively) conceivable that phenomenal truths are grounded in physical truths. (For example, one cannot positively conceive of a situation in which someone has a vivid experience of pink wholly in virtue of the movements of colorless, insentient atoms.) Second, (ideal, positive) inconceivability is a guide to falsity. I attempt to show that the inconceivability argument enjoys a significant advantage over the more familiar conceivability argument. One can reasonably endorse the inconceivability argument without endorsing the conceivability argument, but one cannot reasonably endorse the conceivability argument without also endorsing the inconceivability argument.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83363005","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Governing Conception of Laws 法律的支配概念
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2272
Nina Emery
In her paper, “The Non-Governing Conception of Laws,” Helen Beebee argues that it is not a conceptual truth that laws of nature govern, and thus that one need not insist on a metaphysical account of laws that makes sense of their governing role. I agree with the first point but not the second. Although it is not a conceptual truth, the fact that laws govern follows straightforwardly from an important (though under-appreciated) principle of scientific theory choice combined with a highly plausible claim about the connection between scientific theory choice and theory choice in metaphysics. I present and defend this argument and then show how the resulting understanding of governance gives rise to an especially strong version of recent explanatory circularity arguments against Humeanism about laws of nature. Finally, I present three options for a further understanding of the governance relation that are compatible with my argument.
海伦·比比(Helen Beebee)在她的论文《法律的非支配概念》(The Non-Governing concept of Laws)中认为,自然法则支配并不是一个概念上的真理,因此,人们不需要坚持对法律进行形而上学的解释,从而理解它们的支配作用。我同意第一点,但不同意第二点。虽然这不是一个概念上的真理,但规律支配的事实直接遵循了科学理论选择的一个重要原则(尽管没有得到充分的重视),并结合了一个关于科学理论选择与形而上学理论选择之间联系的高度似是而非的主张。我提出并捍卫了这一论点,然后展示了对治理的理解如何产生了一个特别强烈的版本,即最近的解释性循环论点,反对人文主义关于自然法则的观点。最后,为了进一步理解与我的论点相一致的治理关系,我提出了三个选项。
{"title":"The Governing Conception of Laws","authors":"Nina Emery","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2272","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2272","url":null,"abstract":"In her paper, “The Non-Governing Conception of Laws,” Helen Beebee argues that it is not a conceptual truth that laws of nature govern, and thus that one need not insist on a metaphysical account of laws that makes sense of their governing role. I agree with the first point but not the second. Although it is not a conceptual truth, the fact that laws govern follows straightforwardly from an important (though under-appreciated) principle of scientific theory choice combined with a highly plausible claim about the connection between scientific theory choice and theory choice in metaphysics. I present and defend this argument and then show how the resulting understanding of governance gives rise to an especially strong version of recent explanatory circularity arguments against Humeanism about laws of nature. Finally, I present three options for a further understanding of the governance relation that are compatible with my argument.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84316358","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
The Nomic Likelihood Account of Laws 法律的经济学可能性解释
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2265
Christopher J. G. Meacham
An adequate account of laws should satisfy at least five desiderata: it should provide a unified account of laws and chances, it should yield plausible relations between laws and chances, it should vindicate numerical chance assignments, it should accommodate dynamical and non-dynamical chances, and it should accommodate a plausible range of nomic possibilities. No extant account of laws satisfies these desiderata. This paper presents a non-Humean account of laws, the Nomic Likelihood Account, that does.
对法律的充分解释应该至少满足五个要求:它应该提供对法律和机会的统一解释,它应该在法律和机会之间产生合理的关系,它应该证明数字机会分配是正确的,它应该容纳动态和非动态的机会,它应该容纳一个合理的经济学可能性范围。现存的任何法律都不能满足这些要求。本文提出了一种非休谟的定律解释,即Nomic Likelihood account。
{"title":"The Nomic Likelihood Account of Laws","authors":"Christopher J. G. Meacham","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2265","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2265","url":null,"abstract":"An adequate account of laws should satisfy at least five desiderata: it should provide a unified account of laws and chances, it should yield plausible relations between laws and chances, it should vindicate numerical chance assignments, it should accommodate dynamical and non-dynamical chances, and it should accommodate a plausible range of nomic possibilities. No extant account of laws satisfies these desiderata. This paper presents a non-Humean account of laws, the Nomic Likelihood Account, that does.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78245484","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Intersectional Feminist Theory as a Non-Ideal Theory: Asian American Women Navigating Identity and Power 作为非理想理论的交叉性女性主义理论:亚裔美国女性身份与权力的导航
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2622
Youjin Kong
This paper develops an account of intersectional feminist theory by critically examining the notion of identity implicitly assumed in major critiques of intersectionality. Critics take intersectionality to fragment women along the lines of identity categories such as race, class, and sexuality. Underlying this interpretation, I argue, is the metaphysical assumption that identity is a fixed entity. This is a misunderstanding of identity that neglects how identity is actually lived. By exploring how Asian American women experience their “Asian” identity in their everyday lives (e.g., the “Asian-as-patriarchal vs. White-as-gender-progressive” stereotype, growing anti-Asian racism amid COVID-19, and Asian-Black feminist solidarities), I demonstrate that Asian identity is not fixed but changing according to how it is related to power. I identify and discuss three characteristic types of the identity-power relationship: manifestation of power-as-oppression through the construction of identity, reproduction of power-as-oppression, and creation of new forms of power, namely resistance and solidarity, through the reconstruction of identity. The lives of multiply-oppressed women (e.g., Asian women) can be understood as the locus at which the identity-power relationship is worked out, that is, the power dynamics of oppression are manifested, reproduced, and resisted through the (re)construction of identity. Building on this analysis and engaging discussions on non-ideal theory in social/political philosophy, I argue that intersectional feminist theory can be best explained as a non-ideal theory in a strong sense: a theory that, by focusing on the lives of the multiply oppressed, presents the intersecting dynamics of oppression as central and theory-guiding.
本文通过批判性地考察在交叉性的主要批评中隐含的身份概念,发展了交叉性女权主义理论的叙述。评论家们用交叉性来划分女性的身份类别,如种族、阶级和性别。我认为,这种解释的基础是形而上学的假设,即身份是一个固定的实体。这是对身份的误解,忽视了身份的实际生活方式。通过探索亚裔美国女性在日常生活中如何体验他们的“亚洲”身份(例如,“亚洲人是父权vs白人是性别进步”的刻板印象,在COVID-19期间日益增长的反亚洲种族主义,以及亚洲黑人女权主义者的团结),我证明了亚洲人的身份不是固定的,而是根据它与权力的关系而变化的。我识别并讨论了身份-权力关系的三种特征类型:通过身份的建构来表现权力作为压迫,权力作为压迫的再生产,以及通过身份的重建来创造新的权力形式,即抵抗和团结。多重被压迫女性(如亚洲女性)的生活可以被理解为身份-权力关系形成的轨迹,即压迫的权力动态通过身份的(重新)建构得到表现、再现和抵抗。基于这一分析和对社会/政治哲学中非理想理论的讨论,我认为交叉女权主义理论可以被最好地解释为一种强烈意义上的非理想理论:一种通过关注众多受压迫者的生活,将压迫的交叉动态作为中心和理论指导的理论。
{"title":"Intersectional Feminist Theory as a Non-Ideal Theory: Asian American Women Navigating Identity and Power","authors":"Youjin Kong","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2622","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2622","url":null,"abstract":"This paper develops an account of intersectional feminist theory by critically examining the notion of identity implicitly assumed in major critiques of intersectionality. Critics take intersectionality to fragment women along the lines of identity categories such as race, class, and sexuality. Underlying this interpretation, I argue, is the metaphysical assumption that identity is a fixed entity. This is a misunderstanding of identity that neglects how identity is actually lived. By exploring how Asian American women experience their “Asian” identity in their everyday lives (e.g., the “Asian-as-patriarchal vs. White-as-gender-progressive” stereotype, growing anti-Asian racism amid COVID-19, and Asian-Black feminist solidarities), I demonstrate that Asian identity is not fixed but changing according to how it is related to power. I identify and discuss three characteristic types of the identity-power relationship: manifestation of power-as-oppression through the construction of identity, reproduction of power-as-oppression, and creation of new forms of power, namely resistance and solidarity, through the reconstruction of identity. The lives of multiply-oppressed women (e.g., Asian women) can be understood as the locus at which the identity-power relationship is worked out, that is, the power dynamics of oppression are manifested, reproduced, and resisted through the (re)construction of identity. Building on this analysis and engaging discussions on non-ideal theory in social/political philosophy, I argue that intersectional feminist theory can be best explained as a non-ideal theory in a strong sense: a theory that, by focusing on the lives of the multiply oppressed, presents the intersecting dynamics of oppression as central and theory-guiding.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77219072","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Fear of the Past 对过去的恐惧
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2269
D. Bordini, G. Torrengo
A widespread (and often tacit) assumption is that fear is an anticipatory emotion and, as such, inherently future-oriented. Prima facie, such an assumption is threatened by cases where we seem to be afraid of things in the past: if it is possible to fear the past, then fear entertains no special relation with the future—or so some have argued. This seems to force us to choose between an account of fear as an anticipatory emotion (supported by pre-theoretical intuitions as well as empirical research in psychology) and admitting cases of past-oriented fear. In this paper, we argue for a proposal that dissolves this dilemma. Our claim is: with the right account in place, the future-orientation of fear can be made compatible with, and is actually explanatory of, cases where we are genuinely afraid of something in the past. So, there is no need to choose: fear is still future-oriented, even when we are genuinely afraid of things in the past. The key is a correct understanding of what fear’s temporal orientation amounts to, and the framework we offer here provides us with such an understanding.
一个广为流传的(通常也是心照不宣的)假设是,恐惧是一种预期情绪,因此,它本质上是面向未来的。从表面上看,这种假设受到了我们似乎害怕过去事物的案例的威胁:如果有可能害怕过去,那么恐惧与未来就没有特殊的关系——至少有些人是这样认为的。这似乎迫使我们在将恐惧描述为一种预期情绪(由理论前的直觉和心理学的实证研究支持)和承认过去导向的恐惧之间做出选择。在本文中,我们提出了一个解决这一困境的建议。我们的观点是:在正确的解释下,恐惧的未来取向可以与我们过去真正害怕的事情相一致,并且实际上可以解释。所以,没有必要选择:恐惧仍然是面向未来的,即使我们真的害怕过去的事情。关键是正确理解恐惧的时间取向是什么,我们在这里提供的框架为我们提供了这样的理解。
{"title":"Fear of the Past","authors":"D. Bordini, G. Torrengo","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2269","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2269","url":null,"abstract":"A widespread (and often tacit) assumption is that fear is an anticipatory emotion and, as such, inherently future-oriented. Prima facie, such an assumption is threatened by cases where we seem to be afraid of things in the past: if it is possible to fear the past, then fear entertains no special relation with the future—or so some have argued. This seems to force us to choose between an account of fear as an anticipatory emotion (supported by pre-theoretical intuitions as well as empirical research in psychology) and admitting cases of past-oriented fear. In this paper, we argue for a proposal that dissolves this dilemma. Our claim is: with the right account in place, the future-orientation of fear can be made compatible with, and is actually explanatory of, cases where we are genuinely afraid of something in the past. So, there is no need to choose: fear is still future-oriented, even when we are genuinely afraid of things in the past. The key is a correct understanding of what fear’s temporal orientation amounts to, and the framework we offer here provides us with such an understanding.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83760782","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two Concepts of Double Prevention 双重预防的两个概念
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2620
Bradford Skow
Is double prevention causation? Some say yes and some say no, but the answer is yes and no. Interrupting double prevention, where A prevents B from continuing to prevent something, is causation, while blocking double prevention, where A intervenes before B has begun preventing anything, is not. I present two arguments for this thesis. First, it sorts canonical examples of double prevention correctly. Second, well-known theoretical arguments that double prevention is not causation only show that blocking double prevention is not causation.
双重预防是因果吗?有些人说是,有些人说是,但答案是肯定的和否定的。中断双重预防,即A阻止B继续阻止某事,是因果关系,而阻断双重预防,即A在B开始阻止任何事情之前进行干预,则不是因果关系。我为这篇论文提出了两个论点。首先,它正确地分类了双重预防的典型例子。其次,众所周知的双重预防不是因果关系的理论论点只表明阻止双重预防不是因果关系。
{"title":"Two Concepts of Double Prevention","authors":"Bradford Skow","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2620","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2620","url":null,"abstract":"Is double prevention causation? Some say yes and some say no, but the answer is yes and no. Interrupting double prevention, where A prevents B from continuing to prevent something, is causation, while blocking double prevention, where A intervenes before B has begun preventing anything, is not. I present two arguments for this thesis. First, it sorts canonical examples of double prevention correctly. Second, well-known theoretical arguments that double prevention is not causation only show that blocking double prevention is not causation.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78962279","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ontology as a Guide to Politics? Judith Butler on Interdependency, Vulnerability, and Nonviolence 本体论是政治的指南?朱迪思·巴特勒谈相互依赖、脆弱性和非暴力
IF 0.6 3区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.3998/ergo.2624
J. Wearing
In recent work, Judith Butler has sought to develop a ‘new bodily ontology’ with a substantive normative upshot: recognition of our shared bodily condition, they argue, can support an ethic of nonviolence and a renewed commitment to egalitarian social conditions. However, the route from Butler’s ontological claims to their ethico-political commitments is not clear: how can the general ontological features of embodiment Butler identifies introduce constraints on behaviour or political arrangements? Ontology, one might think, is neutral on questions of politics. In this paper I reconstruct Butler’s response to this challenge, arguing that there is an interesting and plausible path from ontology to politics. I draw on Heidegger’s ontological/ontic distinction to elucidate the central concepts of Butler’s ontology: vulnerability, precariousness, and interdependency. I argue that one of Butler’s central attempts to derive an ethic of nonviolence from ontology is unpersuasive, resting on a conflation of the ontological and ontic senses of ‘interdependency’. Nonetheless, I contend that Butler is right that genuinely acknowledging our vulnerability is likely to make us more responsive to the claims of others, loosening the grip of ideals of invulnerability and sovereign independence. These ideals and the violence they encourage amount to a disavowal of our ontological condition, while commitment to nonviolence is a way of acknowledging
在最近的工作中,朱迪思·巴特勒(Judith Butler)试图发展一种具有实质性规范结果的“新身体本体论”:他们认为,认识到我们共有的身体状况,可以支持非暴力伦理和对平等社会条件的重新承诺。然而,从巴特勒的本体论主张到他们的伦理政治承诺的路线并不清楚:巴特勒所识别的体现的一般本体论特征如何能够引入对行为或政治安排的约束?有人可能会认为,本体论在政治问题上是中立的。在本文中,我重构了巴特勒对这一挑战的回应,认为从本体论到政治有一条有趣而可信的道路。我利用海德格尔的本体论/本体论的区别来阐明巴特勒本体论的核心概念:脆弱性、不稳定性和相互依赖性。我认为巴特勒从本体论中推导出非暴力伦理的核心尝试之一是没有说服力的,它建立在“相互依赖”的本体论和本体论意义的合并上。尽管如此,我认为巴特勒是对的,真诚地承认我们的脆弱可能会让我们对他人的要求做出更积极的回应,放松对坚不可摧和主权独立理想的束缚。这些理想和它们所鼓励的暴力等于否定我们的本体论条件,而承诺非暴力是承认它的一种方式。既然承认失败就是道德上的失败,我们就有责任以承认我们共有的本体论条件的方式行动——即使有人对巴特勒的本体论的细节提出异议,这一普遍结论也会引起人们的兴趣。
{"title":"Ontology as a Guide to Politics? Judith Butler on Interdependency, Vulnerability, and Nonviolence","authors":"J. Wearing","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2624","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2624","url":null,"abstract":"In recent work, Judith Butler has sought to develop a ‘new bodily ontology’ with a substantive normative upshot: recognition of our shared bodily condition, they argue, can support an ethic of nonviolence and a renewed commitment to egalitarian social conditions. However, the route from Butler’s ontological claims to their ethico-political commitments is not clear: how can the general ontological features of embodiment Butler identifies introduce constraints on behaviour or political arrangements? Ontology, one might think, is neutral on questions of politics. In this paper I reconstruct Butler’s response to this challenge, arguing that there is an interesting and plausible path from ontology to politics. I draw on Heidegger’s ontological/ontic distinction to elucidate the central concepts of Butler’s ontology: vulnerability, precariousness, and interdependency. I argue that one of Butler’s central attempts to derive an ethic of nonviolence from ontology is unpersuasive, resting on a conflation of the ontological and ontic senses of ‘interdependency’. Nonetheless, I contend that Butler is right that genuinely acknowledging our vulnerability is likely to make us more responsive to the claims of others, loosening the grip of ideals of invulnerability and sovereign independence. These ideals and the violence they encourage amount to a disavowal of our ontological condition, while commitment to nonviolence is a way of acknowledging</em it. Since a failure of acknowledgement is an ethical failure, we have a responsibility to act in ways that acknowledge our shared ontological condition—a general conclusion that is of interest even if one contests the specifics of Butler’s ontology.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89033612","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1