首页 > 最新文献

Cognitive Neuroscience最新文献

英文 中文
Criteria for empirical theories of consciousness should focus on the explanatory power of mechanisms, not on functional equivalence. 意识经验理论的标准应该关注机制的解释力,而不是功能对等。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-11-18 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1838470
Johannes J Fahrenfort, Simon van Gaal

Doerig and colleagues put forward the notion that we need hard and theory-neutral criteria by which to arbitrate between empirical (mechanistic) theories of consciousness. However, most of the criteria that they propose are not theory neutral because they focus on functional equivalence between systems. Because empirical theories of consciousness are mechanistic rather than functionalist, we think these criteria are not helpful when arbitrating between them.

Doerig和他的同事们提出了这样一个观点,即我们需要硬性的、理论中立的标准来在经验主义(机械论)的意识理论之间进行仲裁。然而,他们提出的大多数标准都不是理论中立的,因为他们关注的是系统之间的功能等价。因为意识的经验理论是机械论的而不是功能论的,我们认为这些标准在它们之间进行仲裁时没有帮助。
{"title":"Criteria for empirical theories of consciousness should focus on the explanatory power of mechanisms, not on functional equivalence.","authors":"Johannes J Fahrenfort,&nbsp;Simon van Gaal","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1838470","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1838470","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Doerig and colleagues put forward the notion that we need hard and theory-neutral criteria by which to arbitrate between empirical (mechanistic) theories of consciousness. However, most of the criteria that they propose are not theory neutral because they focus on functional equivalence between systems. Because empirical theories of consciousness are mechanistic rather than functionalist, we think these criteria are not helpful when arbitrating between them.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 2","pages":"93-94"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1838470","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38616159","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Supracategorical fear information revealed by aversively conditioning multiple categories. 厌恶条件反射多类别揭示的超范畴恐惧信息。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-11-01 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1839039
Seth M Levine, Miriam Kumpf, Rainer Rupprecht, Jens V Schwarzbach

Fear-generalization is a critical function for survival, in which an organism extracts information from a specific instantiation of a threat (e.g., the western diamondback rattlesnake in my front yard on Sunday) and learns to fear - and accordingly respond to - pertinent higher-order information (e.g., snakes live in my yard). Previous work investigating fear-conditioning in humans has used functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) to demonstrate that activity patterns representing stimuli from an aversively-conditioned category (CS+) are more similar to each other than those of a neutral category (CS-). Here we used fMRI and multiple aversively-conditioned categories to ask whether we would find only similarity increases within the CS+ categories or also similarity increases between the CS+ categories. Using representational similarity analysis, we correlated several models to activity patterns underlying different brain regions and found that, following fear-conditioning, between-category and within-category similarity increased for the CS+ categories in the insula, superior frontal gyrus (SFG), and the right temporal pole. When specifically investigating fear-generalization, these between- and within-category effects were detected in the SFG. These results advance prior pattern-based neuroimaging work by exploring the effect of aversively-conditioning multiple categories and indicate an extended role for such regions in potentially representing supracategorical information during fear-learning.

恐惧泛化是生存的关键功能,生物体从威胁的具体实例中提取信息(例如,周日我家前院的西部菱形响尾蛇),并学会恐惧——并相应地对相关的高阶信息做出反应(例如,我家院子里住着蛇)。先前研究人类恐惧条件反射的工作使用了功能性磁共振成像(fMRI)来证明,来自负面条件类别(CS+)的刺激的活动模式比来自中性类别(CS-)的刺激更相似。在这里,我们使用功能磁共振成像和多个反向条件类别来询问我们是否会发现只有CS+类别内的相似性增加,还是CS+类别之间的相似性增加。利用表征相似性分析,我们将几个模型与不同脑区活动模式相关联,发现在恐惧条件反射之后,CS+类别在脑岛、额上回和右颞极的类别间和类别内相似性增加。当专门研究恐惧泛化时,这些类别间和类别内效应在SFG中被检测到。这些结果通过探索多类别的负面条件反射效应,推进了基于先验模式的神经成像工作,并表明这些区域在恐惧学习过程中潜在地代表超分类信息方面的扩展作用。
{"title":"Supracategorical fear information revealed by aversively conditioning multiple categories.","authors":"Seth M Levine,&nbsp;Miriam Kumpf,&nbsp;Rainer Rupprecht,&nbsp;Jens V Schwarzbach","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1839039","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1839039","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Fear-generalization is a critical function for survival, in which an organism extracts information from a specific instantiation of a threat (e.g., the western diamondback rattlesnake in my front yard on Sunday) and learns to fear - and accordingly respond to - pertinent higher-order information (e.g., snakes live in my yard). Previous work investigating fear-conditioning in humans has used functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) to demonstrate that activity patterns representing stimuli from an aversively-conditioned category (CS+) are more similar to each other than those of a neutral category (CS-). Here we used fMRI and <i>multiple</i> aversively-conditioned categories to ask whether we would find only similarity increases <i>within</i> the CS+ categories or also similarity increases <i>between</i> the CS+ categories. Using representational similarity analysis, we correlated several models to activity patterns underlying different brain regions and found that, following fear-conditioning, between-category and within-category similarity increased for the CS+ categories in the insula, superior frontal gyrus (SFG), and the right temporal pole. When specifically investigating fear-<i>generalization</i>, these between- and within-category effects were detected in the SFG. These results advance prior pattern-based neuroimaging work by exploring the effect of aversively-conditioning multiple categories and indicate an extended role for such regions in potentially representing supracategorical information during fear-learning.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 1","pages":"28-39"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1839039","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38651212","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Theories of consciousness are solutions in need of problems. 意识理论是需要问题的解决方案。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-11-11 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1841744
Stephen M Fleming

Doerig et al. point out a number of shortcomings with existing theories of consciousness and argue they should be systematically constrained by empirical data. In this commentary I suggest a further constraint - the potential functions of (the contents of) consciousness. One such candidate function in humans is the social sharing of reportable mental states. The social function of consciousnessprovides a general framework within which to understand the evolution and neurobiology of conscious awareness.

Doerig等人指出了现有意识理论的一些缺陷,并认为它们应该系统地受到经验数据的约束。在这篇评论中,我提出了一个进一步的限制——意识(内容)的潜在功能。人类的一个候选功能是可报告的精神状态的社会分享。意识的社会功能为理解意识的进化和神经生物学提供了一个总体框架。
{"title":"Theories of consciousness are solutions in need of problems.","authors":"Stephen M Fleming","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1841744","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1841744","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Doerig et al. point out a number of shortcomings with existing theories of consciousness and argue they should be systematically constrained by empirical data. In this commentary I suggest a further constraint - the potential functions of (the contents of) consciousness. One such candidate function in humans is the social sharing of reportable mental states. The social function of consciousnessprovides a general framework within which to understand the evolution and neurobiology of conscious awareness.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 2","pages":"86-88"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1841744","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38695688","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Proposal to create discussion forum to consider evidence on theories of consciousness. 建议建立讨论论坛来考虑意识理论的证据。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-12-14 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1846026
Stan Klein

I consider the Doerig, Schruger, Herzog (this issue) paper to be a very important paper on the multiple empirical theories of consciousness (ToCs). The paper compared 13 different approaches. It would be wonderful to create a forum for all interested parties to discuss the many issues this paper brought up. Equally important is what the paper didn't bring up. Namely, how do the different empirical approaches connect to qualia, the subjective aspects of consciousness. In my mind, qualia is the biggest mystery facing present science. It would be good to see how the multiple interpretations might connect to qualia.

我认为Doerig, Schruger, Herzog(本期)的论文是关于意识的多重经验理论(ToCs)的一篇非常重要的论文。这篇论文比较了13种不同的方法。为所有感兴趣的各方创建一个论坛来讨论本文提出的许多问题,这将是一件很棒的事情。同样重要的是论文中没有提到的东西。也就是说,不同的经验主义方法是如何与意识的主观方面——感质联系起来的。在我看来,质是当今科学面临的最大谜团。看看这些多重解释是如何与质感联系在一起的,这将是件好事。
{"title":"Proposal to create discussion forum to consider evidence on theories of consciousness.","authors":"Stan Klein","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1846026","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1846026","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>I consider the Doerig, Schruger, Herzog (this issue) paper to be a very important paper on the multiple empirical theories of consciousness (ToCs). The paper compared 13 different approaches. It would be wonderful to create a forum for all interested parties to discuss the many issues this paper brought up. Equally important is what the paper didn't bring up. Namely, how do the different empirical approaches connect to qualia, the subjective aspects of consciousness. In my mind, qualia is the biggest mystery facing present science. It would be good to see how the multiple interpretations might connect to qualia.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 2","pages":"91-92"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1846026","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38704608","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Hard criteria for empirical theories of consciousness. 意识的经验理论的硬性标准。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-07-14 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1772214
Adrien Doerig, Aaron Schurger, Michael H Herzog

Consciousness is now a well-established field of empirical research. A large body of experimental results has been accumulated and is steadily growing. In parallel, many Theories of Consciousness (ToCs) have been proposed. These theories are diverse in nature, ranging from computational to neurophysiological and quantum theoretical approaches. This contrasts with other fields of natural science, which host a smaller number of competing theories. We suggest that one reason for this abundance of extremely different theories may be the lack of stringent criteria specifying how empirical data constrains ToCs. First, we argue that consciousness is a well-defined topic from an empirical point of view and motivate a purely empirical stance on the quest for consciousness. Second, we present a checklist of criteria that, we propose, empirical ToCs need to cope with. Third, we review 13 of the most influential ToCs and subject them to the criteria. Our analysis helps to situate these different ToCs in the theoretical landscapeand sheds light on their strengths and weaknesses from a strictly empirical point of view.

意识现在是一个成熟的实证研究领域。已经积累了大量的实验成果,并在不断发展壮大。与此同时,许多意识理论(ToCs)也被提出。这些理论在本质上是多种多样的,从计算到神经生理学和量子理论方法。这与自然科学的其他领域形成鲜明对比,后者拥有较少数量的相互竞争的理论。我们认为,出现如此多截然不同的理论的一个原因可能是缺乏严格的标准来规定经验数据如何约束toc。首先,我们认为,从经验的角度来看,意识是一个定义良好的主题,并激发了对意识追求的纯粹经验立场。其次,我们提出了一份标准清单,我们建议经验性toc需要处理这些标准。第三,我们审查了13个最具影响力的toc,并将其纳入标准。我们的分析有助于将这些不同的toc置于理论景观中,并从严格的实证角度阐明它们的优缺点。
{"title":"Hard criteria for empirical theories of consciousness.","authors":"Adrien Doerig,&nbsp;Aaron Schurger,&nbsp;Michael H Herzog","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1772214","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1772214","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Consciousness is now a well-established field of empirical research. A large body of experimental results has been accumulated and is steadily growing. In parallel, many Theories of Consciousness (ToCs) have been proposed. These theories are diverse in nature, ranging from computational to neurophysiological and quantum theoretical approaches. This contrasts with other fields of natural science, which host a smaller number of competing theories. We suggest that one reason for this abundance of extremely different theories may be the lack of stringent criteria specifying how empirical data constrains ToCs. First, we argue that consciousness is a well-defined topic from an empirical point of view and motivate a purely empirical stance on the quest for consciousness. Second, we present a checklist of criteria that, we propose, empirical ToCs need to cope with. Third, we review 13 of the most influential ToCs and subject them to the criteria. Our analysis helps to situate these different ToCs in the theoretical landscapeand sheds light on their strengths and weaknesses from a strictly empirical point of view.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 2","pages":"41-62"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1772214","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38158102","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 81
Feeling & knowing: Making minds conscious. 感觉和认知:使头脑有意识。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-12-15 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1846027
Antonio Damasio
(1) Let me begin by thanking Doerig et al. for including my work in their survey of empirical theories of consciousness (although I am a bit spooked by being assigned the number 13!), especially given the authors’ concern for the large number of currently competing theories. I also appreciate their idea that the reason for this abundance may be a lack of stringent selection criteria although I suggest that the problem actually begins prior to the selection of proposals: it concerns the clarification of what exactly is the point of these studies. This is not a new problem. I recall spending many hours, most of them pleasant, discussing this very issue with some of the most distinguished contributors to the field ― Gerald Edelman, Giulio Tononi, Francis Crick, Christof Koch, Stanislas Dehaene, Jean Pierre Changeux, David Chalmers, Stuart Hameroff, Roger Penrose ― but no clear agreement ever emerged as to what the exact phenomenon was that we were so devoted to understanding. My position, then and now, is that the approach to consciousness must begin with introspection. We can inspect our mental processes and decide, on the basis of their psychological analysis, what the phenomenon of interest is. Subsequently, we can use facts drawn from physics, chemistry, biology, and neuroscience to build hypotheses regarding the mechanisms behind the phenomenon. (2) Introspection tells me that consciousness consists of an enrichment of the basic process of mind. Minds are made of flowing, representational, imagetic patterns based on varied sensory mappings, primarily related to perception and memory recall. The flow of images is not ‘conscious,’ per se, but can be rendered conscious by adding to it knowledge to the effect that the ongoing mental contents belong to a particular organism. (3) The above transformation is first accomplished by feelings. Feelings are hybrid processes, based largely on the body’s interior and carried out, physiologically, as an interaction between (i) homeostatically driven, life-regulatory routines occurring in the chemical-visceral interior, and (ii) interoceptive maps generated at multiple peripheral levels (e.g., spinal ganglia; trigeminal ganglion) and central nervous system (e.g., brainstem nuclei; insular cortices; cingulate cortices). Whereas exteroception accomplishes the mapping of external objects and actions that are strictly separate from the perceiving organism, interoception accomplishes the mapping of internal organism events. As a result, an interaction between ‘object of perception’ and ‘subject’ is maintained throughout the process and results in a unique hybrid. Moreover, the anatomical and physiological features of interoception are also unique. The critical step in the generation of consciousness, then, is the revelation, made within the mind, that the mind belongs to and is located within a specific living organism. This revelation is firstly accomplished by feeling but is complemented by (a) proprioceptive sig
{"title":"Feeling & knowing: Making minds conscious.","authors":"Antonio Damasio","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1846027","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1846027","url":null,"abstract":"(1) Let me begin by thanking Doerig et al. for including my work in their survey of empirical theories of consciousness (although I am a bit spooked by being assigned the number 13!), especially given the authors’ concern for the large number of currently competing theories. I also appreciate their idea that the reason for this abundance may be a lack of stringent selection criteria although I suggest that the problem actually begins prior to the selection of proposals: it concerns the clarification of what exactly is the point of these studies. This is not a new problem. I recall spending many hours, most of them pleasant, discussing this very issue with some of the most distinguished contributors to the field ― Gerald Edelman, Giulio Tononi, Francis Crick, Christof Koch, Stanislas Dehaene, Jean Pierre Changeux, David Chalmers, Stuart Hameroff, Roger Penrose ― but no clear agreement ever emerged as to what the exact phenomenon was that we were so devoted to understanding. My position, then and now, is that the approach to consciousness must begin with introspection. We can inspect our mental processes and decide, on the basis of their psychological analysis, what the phenomenon of interest is. Subsequently, we can use facts drawn from physics, chemistry, biology, and neuroscience to build hypotheses regarding the mechanisms behind the phenomenon. (2) Introspection tells me that consciousness consists of an enrichment of the basic process of mind. Minds are made of flowing, representational, imagetic patterns based on varied sensory mappings, primarily related to perception and memory recall. The flow of images is not ‘conscious,’ per se, but can be rendered conscious by adding to it knowledge to the effect that the ongoing mental contents belong to a particular organism. (3) The above transformation is first accomplished by feelings. Feelings are hybrid processes, based largely on the body’s interior and carried out, physiologically, as an interaction between (i) homeostatically driven, life-regulatory routines occurring in the chemical-visceral interior, and (ii) interoceptive maps generated at multiple peripheral levels (e.g., spinal ganglia; trigeminal ganglion) and central nervous system (e.g., brainstem nuclei; insular cortices; cingulate cortices). Whereas exteroception accomplishes the mapping of external objects and actions that are strictly separate from the perceiving organism, interoception accomplishes the mapping of internal organism events. As a result, an interaction between ‘object of perception’ and ‘subject’ is maintained throughout the process and results in a unique hybrid. Moreover, the anatomical and physiological features of interoception are also unique. The critical step in the generation of consciousness, then, is the revelation, made within the mind, that the mind belongs to and is located within a specific living organism. This revelation is firstly accomplished by feeling but is complemented by (a) proprioceptive sig","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 2","pages":"65-66"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1846027","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38713443","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 28
A Unified Neural Theory of Conscious Seeing, Hearing, Feeling, and Knowing. 有意识的看、听、感觉和认识的统一神经理论。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-11-06 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1839401
Stephen Grossberg

Adaptive Resonance Theory does more than satisfy 'hard criteria' for ToCs.

自适应共振理论不仅仅满足toc的“硬标准”。
{"title":"A Unified Neural Theory of Conscious Seeing, Hearing, Feeling, and Knowing.","authors":"Stephen Grossberg","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1839401","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1839401","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Adaptive Resonance Theory does more than satisfy 'hard criteria' for ToCs.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 2","pages":"69-73"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1839401","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38559939","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Higher-order theories do just fine. 高阶理论做得很好。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-11-11 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1839402
Matthias Michel, Hakwan Lau

Doerig et al. have set several criteria that theories of consciousness need to fulfill. By these criteria, higher-order theories fare better than most existing theories. But they also argue that higher-order theories may not be able to answer both the 'small network argument' and the 'other systems argument'. In response, we focus on the case of the Perceptual Reality Monitoring theory to explain why higher-order theories do just fine.

Doerig等人设定了意识理论需要满足的几个标准。根据这些标准,高阶理论比大多数现有理论表现得更好。但他们也认为,高阶理论可能无法同时回答“小网络论点”和“其他系统论点”。作为回应,我们将重点放在感知现实监测理论的案例上,以解释为什么高阶理论做得很好。
{"title":"Higher-order theories do just fine.","authors":"Matthias Michel,&nbsp;Hakwan Lau","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1839402","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1839402","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Doerig et al. have set several criteria that theories of consciousness need to fulfill. By these criteria, higher-order theories fare better than most existing theories. But they also argue that higher-order theories may not be able to answer both the 'small network argument' and the 'other systems argument'. In response, we focus on the case of the Perceptual Reality Monitoring theory to explain why higher-order theories do just fine.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 2","pages":"77-78"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1839402","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38593461","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The hard problem makes the easy problems hard - a reply to Doerig et al. 困难的问题使简单的问题变得困难——这是对Doerig等人的回答。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-11-11 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1838469
Yair Pinto, Timo Stein

In their paper Doerig et al. argue that we should put the hard problem aside and focus on empirical data to solve the 'easy' problems of consciousness - finding the neural and functional correlates of consciousness. In other words 'shut up and measure'. This has worked well with other thorny issues, such as explaining life, so why not adopt this approach here? We argue that despite the popularity of this view it is not feasible. In order to collect any consciousness data one needs to take an implicit or explicit stance on the hard problem.

在他们的论文中,Doerig等人认为,我们应该把困难的问题放在一边,专注于经验数据来解决意识的“容易”问题——找到意识的神经和功能关联。换句话说就是“闭嘴测量”。这在其他棘手的问题上很有效,比如解释生命,那么为什么不在这里采用这种方法呢?我们认为,尽管这种观点很流行,但它是不可行的。为了收集意识数据,人们需要对这个难题采取明确或含蓄的立场。
{"title":"The hard problem makes the easy problems hard - a reply to Doerig et al.","authors":"Yair Pinto,&nbsp;Timo Stein","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1838469","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1838469","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In their paper Doerig et al. argue that we should put the hard problem aside and focus on empirical data to solve the 'easy' problems of consciousness - finding the neural and functional correlates of consciousness. In other words 'shut up and measure'. This has worked well with other thorny issues, such as explaining life, so why not adopt this approach here? We argue that despite the popularity of this view it is not feasible. In order to collect any consciousness data one needs to take an implicit or explicit stance on the hard problem.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 2","pages":"97-98"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1838469","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38593463","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
The Readiness Potential reflects planning-based expectation, not uncertainty, in the timing of action. 准备潜力反映的是基于计划的预期,而不是行动时机的不确定性。
IF 2 4区 医学 Q3 Neuroscience Pub Date : 2021-01-01 Epub Date: 2020-11-06 DOI: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1824176
Eoin Travers, Maja Friedemann, Patrick Haggard

Actions are guided by a combination of external cues, internal intentions, and stored knowledge. Self-initiated voluntary actions, produced without immediate external cues, may be preceded by a slow EEG Readiness Potential (RP) that progressively increases prior to action. The cognitive significance of this neural event is controversial. Some accounts link the RP to the fact that timing of voluntary actions is generated endogenously, without external constraints. Others link it to the unique role of a planning process, and therefore of temporal expectation, in voluntary actions. In many previous experiments, actions are unconstrained by external cues, but also potentially involve preplanning and anticipation. To separate these factors, we developed a reinforcement learning paradigm where participants learned, through trial and error, the optimal time to act. If the RP reflects freedom from external constraint, its amplitude should be greater early in learning, when participants do not yet know when to act. Conversely, if the RP reflects planning, it should be greater later on, when participants have learned, and plan in advance, the time of action. We found that RP amplitudes grew with learning, suggesting that this neural activity reflects planning and anticipation for the forthcoming action, rather than freedom from external constraint.

行动是由外部线索、内部意图和储存的知识共同引导的。自发自发的动作,在没有直接外部提示的情况下产生,可能在动作之前有一个缓慢的脑电图准备电位(RP),在行动之前逐渐增加。这个神经事件的认知意义是有争议的。一些说法将RP与自愿行动的时机是内生产生的这一事实联系起来,没有外部限制。另一些人则把它与计划过程的独特作用联系起来,因此也与自愿行动中的暂时预期联系起来。在许多先前的实验中,行动不受外部线索的约束,但也可能涉及预先计划和预期。为了分离这些因素,我们开发了一个强化学习范例,参与者通过试验和错误来学习最佳的行动时间。如果RP反映了不受外部约束的自由,那么在学习早期,当参与者还不知道何时采取行动时,它的幅度应该更大。相反,如果RP反映了计划,那么当参与者学习并提前计划行动时,它应该更大。我们发现,RP振幅随着学习而增长,这表明这种神经活动反映了对即将到来的行动的计划和预期,而不是从外部约束中解脱出来。
{"title":"The Readiness Potential reflects planning-based expectation, not uncertainty, in the timing of action.","authors":"Eoin Travers,&nbsp;Maja Friedemann,&nbsp;Patrick Haggard","doi":"10.1080/17588928.2020.1824176","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2020.1824176","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Actions are guided by a combination of external cues, internal intentions, and stored knowledge. Self-initiated <i>voluntary actions,</i> produced without immediate external cues, may be preceded by a slow EEG Readiness Potential (RP) that progressively increases prior to action. The cognitive significance of this neural event is controversial. Some accounts link the RP to the fact that timing of voluntary actions is generated endogenously, without external constraints. Others link it to the unique role of a planning process, and therefore of temporal expectation, in voluntary actions. In many previous experiments, actions are unconstrained by external cues, but also potentially involve preplanning and anticipation. To separate these factors, we developed a reinforcement learning paradigm where participants learned, through trial and error, the optimal time to act. If the RP reflects freedom from external constraint, its amplitude should be greater early in learning, when participants do not yet know when to act. Conversely, if the RP reflects planning, it should be greater later on, when participants have learned, and plan in advance, the time of action. We found that RP amplitudes grew with learning, suggesting that this neural activity reflects planning and anticipation for the forthcoming action, rather than freedom from external constraint.</p>","PeriodicalId":10413,"journal":{"name":"Cognitive Neuroscience","volume":"12 1","pages":"14-27"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1080/17588928.2020.1824176","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"38666227","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 20
期刊
Cognitive Neuroscience
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1