首页 > 最新文献

International Relations and Political Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Fortune’s Banter 命运的玩笑
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1007/978-1-137-52873-5_10
M. Wight
{"title":"Fortune’s Banter","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1007/978-1-137-52873-5_10","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-52873-5_10","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"100 4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125949129","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What Confers Political Legitimacy in a Modern Society? 什么赋予现代社会政治合法性?
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0020
M. Wight
In this essay Wight considered several sources of legitimacy for a modern Western society. A well-functioning state bureaucracy is a necessity. Popular consultation involving the consent of the governed is also essential. In Britain elective parliamentary democracy meets this need. Citizens must agree on the principle of respecting current laws pending their revision through legal channels. A new authoritative source of legitimacy may replace an old one if citizens transfer their loyalty to it. Time may either heal the injured and legitimate the results of social conflicts or exacerbate antagonisms. Communist regimes and right-wing autocrats such as General Franco in Spain and the Shah of Iran appealed to a principle of ‘legitimation by success’. Other legitimation myths have included ‘childhood ideas of Robin Hood’, ‘the siege’, and ‘the pilgrimage’, but the most fundamental source of legitimacy resides in the blood shed for a society’s independence and the rebirth of its great founding principles. This bloodshed justifies the society’s rededication to pursuing its unfinished work. An opposing question concerns the individual dissenter’s political legitimacy, which must hinge on certain criteria (such as rationality and conscientiousness) to win moral respect. The ‘rationalist illusion’ supposes that citizens can be critical spectators in the proceedings of their own society and its politics. Such detachment is not attainable, and derives from the fallacy that political life can be reduced to the conscious and purposeful management of material needs.
在这篇文章中,怀特考虑了现代西方社会合法性的几个来源。一个运转良好的国家官僚机构是必要的。征得被统治者同意的民众协商也是必不可少的。在英国,议会选举民主正好满足了这一需求。在现行法律通过法律途径修改之前,公民必须同意尊重现行法律的原则。一个新的权威的合法性来源可能会取代旧的,如果公民转移他们的忠诚。时间可以治愈创伤,使社会冲突的结果合法化,也可以加剧对立。共产主义政权和右翼独裁者,如西班牙的佛朗哥将军和伊朗的沙阿(Shah of Iran),都呼吁“通过成功实现合法化”的原则。其他关于合法性的神话包括“罗宾汉童年的想法”、“围攻”和“朝圣”,但合法性最基本的来源在于为一个社会的独立和其伟大的创始原则的重生而流血。这次流血事件证明了该协会重新致力于完成其未完成的工作是正当的。另一个相反的问题涉及到个别持不同政见者的政治合法性,这必须取决于某些标准(如理性和尽责性),以赢得道德尊重。“理性主义幻觉”假设公民可以在他们自己的社会及其政治进程中成为批判性的旁观者。这种超然是不可能实现的,它源于一种谬论,即政治生活可以简化为对物质需求的有意识和有目的的管理。
{"title":"What Confers Political Legitimacy in a Modern Society?","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0020","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0020","url":null,"abstract":"In this essay Wight considered several sources of legitimacy for a modern Western society. A well-functioning state bureaucracy is a necessity. Popular consultation involving the consent of the governed is also essential. In Britain elective parliamentary democracy meets this need. Citizens must agree on the principle of respecting current laws pending their revision through legal channels. A new authoritative source of legitimacy may replace an old one if citizens transfer their loyalty to it. Time may either heal the injured and legitimate the results of social conflicts or exacerbate antagonisms. Communist regimes and right-wing autocrats such as General Franco in Spain and the Shah of Iran appealed to a principle of ‘legitimation by success’. Other legitimation myths have included ‘childhood ideas of Robin Hood’, ‘the siege’, and ‘the pilgrimage’, but the most fundamental source of legitimacy resides in the blood shed for a society’s independence and the rebirth of its great founding principles. This bloodshed justifies the society’s rededication to pursuing its unfinished work. An opposing question concerns the individual dissenter’s political legitimacy, which must hinge on certain criteria (such as rationality and conscientiousness) to win moral respect. The ‘rationalist illusion’ supposes that citizens can be critical spectators in the proceedings of their own society and its politics. Such detachment is not attainable, and derives from the fallacy that political life can be reduced to the conscious and purposeful management of material needs.","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"174 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122951464","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reflections on International Legitimacy 关于国际合法性的思考
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0017
M. Wight
In this essay, presented at a Sussex history seminar in 1971, Wight set out reflections on international legitimacy—supported by historical examples—in addition to those included in his two essays entitled ‘International Legitimacy’, one published as an article in 1972 in the journal International Relations, and the other as a chapter in his 1977 posthumous book Systems of States. Wight pointed out in this essay that governments on some occasions have set aside established principles of legitimacy in order to serve other purposes—maintaining a preferred balance of power, gaining territory, promoting commercial relations, or pursuing state-consolidation, sometimes with a ‘lack of scruple’. Wight observed that rules regarding legitimacy have furnished grounds ‘for argument, controversy, conflict, even war’. He nonetheless concluded that ‘the influence of principles of legitimacy upon international politics has generally been overestimated’ and ‘has declined rather than grown, with the transition from the dynastic to the popular age’. Prevailing concepts of legality and legitimacy have correspondingly enjoyed less ‘moral ascendancy’.
在这篇1971年在苏塞克斯历史研讨会上发表的文章中,怀特提出了对国际合法性的思考——以历史实例为依据——除了他的两篇题为“国际合法性”的文章(一篇于1972年作为文章发表在《国际关系》杂志上,另一篇作为他1977年死后的著作《国家体系》的一个章节)。怀特在这篇文章中指出,在某些情况下,政府为了服务于其他目的——维持权力平衡、获得领土、促进商业关系或追求国家巩固——而放弃了既定的合法性原则,有时是“毫无顾忌”的。怀特观察到,有关合法性的规则为“争论、争议、冲突,甚至战争”提供了依据。尽管如此,他还是得出结论,“合法性原则对国际政治的影响通常被高估了”,并且“随着王朝时代向大众时代的过渡,合法性原则的影响不仅没有增强,反而有所下降”。盛行的合法性和正当性概念相应地享有较少的“道德优势”。
{"title":"Reflections on International Legitimacy","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0017","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0017","url":null,"abstract":"In this essay, presented at a Sussex history seminar in 1971, Wight set out reflections on international legitimacy—supported by historical examples—in addition to those included in his two essays entitled ‘International Legitimacy’, one published as an article in 1972 in the journal International Relations, and the other as a chapter in his 1977 posthumous book Systems of States. Wight pointed out in this essay that governments on some occasions have set aside established principles of legitimacy in order to serve other purposes—maintaining a preferred balance of power, gaining territory, promoting commercial relations, or pursuing state-consolidation, sometimes with a ‘lack of scruple’. Wight observed that rules regarding legitimacy have furnished grounds ‘for argument, controversy, conflict, even war’. He nonetheless concluded that ‘the influence of principles of legitimacy upon international politics has generally been overestimated’ and ‘has declined rather than grown, with the transition from the dynastic to the popular age’. Prevailing concepts of legality and legitimacy have correspondingly enjoyed less ‘moral ascendancy’.","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"66 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129885478","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Western Values in International Relations 国际关系中的西方价值观
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0004
M. Wight
This essay presents the three main traditions of thinking about international relations in Western societies since the sixteenth century, with particular attention to the ‘middle ground’ between extremes. These extremes are typified by thinkers such as Machiavelli and Hobbes at one pole, and Kant and Wilson at the other. The via media is associated with the development of constitutional government and the rule of law, as represented by thinkers such as Grotius and Gladstone. The essay illustrates the differences among these three traditions by analysing their distinct positions concerning international society, the maintenance of order, intervention, and international morality. ‘Western values’ are most effectively supported by thinkers and leaders who neither deny the existence of international society nor exaggerate its foreseeable prospects for gaining greater cohesion and strength. The middle course—the mainstream of the ‘Western values’ tradition—respects moral standards and sees moral challenges as complex, instead of regarding them as simple or nonexistent.
本文介绍了自16世纪以来西方社会思考国际关系的三种主要传统,特别关注极端之间的“中间立场”。这两个极端的典型代表是马基雅维利和霍布斯,以及康德和威尔逊。以格劳秀斯和格莱斯顿等思想家为代表的媒体与宪政和法治的发展有关。本文通过分析这三种传统在国际社会、维护秩序、干预和国际道德方面的不同立场,来说明它们之间的差异。最有效支持“西方价值观”的思想家和领导人既不否认国际社会的存在,也不夸大国际社会获得更大凝聚力和力量的可预见前景。中间路线——“西方价值观”传统的主流——尊重道德标准,认为道德挑战是复杂的,而不是简单的或不存在的。
{"title":"Western Values in International Relations","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0004","url":null,"abstract":"This essay presents the three main traditions of thinking about international relations in Western societies since the sixteenth century, with particular attention to the ‘middle ground’ between extremes. These extremes are typified by thinkers such as Machiavelli and Hobbes at one pole, and Kant and Wilson at the other. The via media is associated with the development of constitutional government and the rule of law, as represented by thinkers such as Grotius and Gladstone. The essay illustrates the differences among these three traditions by analysing their distinct positions concerning international society, the maintenance of order, intervention, and international morality. ‘Western values’ are most effectively supported by thinkers and leaders who neither deny the existence of international society nor exaggerate its foreseeable prospects for gaining greater cohesion and strength. The middle course—the mainstream of the ‘Western values’ tradition—respects moral standards and sees moral challenges as complex, instead of regarding them as simple or nonexistent.","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130959520","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 15
Machiavellian Temptations: Methodological Warning 马基雅维利的诱惑:方法论警告
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0006
M. Wight
Wight drafted this note in a further effort to elucidate key points about his analysis of the three main traditions of thinking about international relations in Western societies since the sixteenth century (Realism, Rationalism, and Revolutionism). First, he acknowledged that there have been causative factors other than ideas, such as pursuing power and status, meeting security requirements, and serving economic interests. The historical record suggests, however, that the philosophical views of influential decision-makers in the face of perceived necessity have coloured their policies and actions. Second, the argument that new technologies such as nuclear weapons and space rockets have made traditional themes of political philosophy obsolete is a ‘dehumanizing’ proposition; it overlooks the fact that human beings have devised these new capabilities and applied them to the pursuit of human priorities. Third, there may be a ‘preselected’ relevance of the three traditions: Kantian ideals may be most suited to private and personal affairs; Grotian philosophical principles may be most useful in the domestic politics of constitutional states; and Machiavellian approaches may be required in international politics.
怀特起草这篇笔记是为了进一步阐明他对16世纪以来西方社会思考国际关系的三种主要传统(现实主义、理性主义和革命主义)的分析要点。首先,他承认,除了思想之外,还有追求权力和地位、满足安全要求、为经济利益服务等原因。然而,历史记录表明,有影响力的决策者在面对感知到的必要性时,其哲学观点影响了他们的政策和行动。其次,认为核武器和太空火箭等新技术已经使政治哲学的传统主题过时的观点是一种“非人性化”命题;它忽视了这样一个事实,即人类已经发明了这些新能力,并将它们应用于追求人类的优先事项。第三,这三种传统可能存在一种“预先选择的”相关性:康德的理想可能最适合私人和个人事务;格罗田的哲学原则可能在宪政国家的国内政治中最有用;在国际政治中可能需要马基雅维利式的方法。
{"title":"Machiavellian Temptations: Methodological Warning","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0006","url":null,"abstract":"Wight drafted this note in a further effort to elucidate key points about his analysis of the three main traditions of thinking about international relations in Western societies since the sixteenth century (Realism, Rationalism, and Revolutionism). First, he acknowledged that there have been causative factors other than ideas, such as pursuing power and status, meeting security requirements, and serving economic interests. The historical record suggests, however, that the philosophical views of influential decision-makers in the face of perceived necessity have coloured their policies and actions. Second, the argument that new technologies such as nuclear weapons and space rockets have made traditional themes of political philosophy obsolete is a ‘dehumanizing’ proposition; it overlooks the fact that human beings have devised these new capabilities and applied them to the pursuit of human priorities. Third, there may be a ‘preselected’ relevance of the three traditions: Kantian ideals may be most suited to private and personal affairs; Grotian philosophical principles may be most useful in the domestic politics of constitutional states; and Machiavellian approaches may be required in international politics.","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"90 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123534863","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Review of Richard W. Sterling, Ethics in a World of Power: The Political Ideas of Friedrich Meinecke (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1958; London, Oxford University Press, 1959) 理查德·斯特林:《权力世界中的伦理学:弗里德里希·迈内克的政治思想》(普林斯顿,新泽西:普林斯顿大学出版社,1958年);伦敦,牛津大学出版社,1959年)
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0026
M. Wight
Meinecke’s student and friend, Richard Sterling, composed this intellectual biography concerning Meinecke’s political ideas. Born in 1862, Meinecke was raised to venerate Hegel, Ranke, and Bismarck as pillars of the German State and conservative nationalism. Wight summed up Meinecke’s political evolution as follows: ‘In the first World War he justified the ultimatum to Serbia and the invasion of Belgium, he approved of unrestricted submarine warfare, and he explained to the minority peoples of the Central Powers that though the nation-state had been the proper goal for the Germans, it was their duty to remain content with the multi-national state. The shock of defeat started him on an assiduous criticism of his old beliefs. The moral autonomy of the State, the primacy of foreign policy, international relations as the fruitful competition of vigorously egotistic Powers, all gradually dissolved. He moved nearer to Goethe, and as an old man came to find the ultimate truth of politics not in the ideal, super-individual corporate personality of the nation-state, but in the martyrdom of the individual rebel against Hitler’s Reich.’
迈内克的学生和朋友理查德·斯特林(Richard Sterling)撰写了这本关于迈内克政治思想的知识分子传记。迈内克出生于1862年,从小就被教导崇拜黑格尔、兰克和俾斯麦,认为他们是德国国家和保守民族主义的支柱。怀特这样总结迈内克的政治演变:“在第一次世界大战中,他为向塞尔维亚发出最后通牒和入侵比利时辩护,他赞成无限制的潜艇战,他向同盟国的少数民族解释说,尽管民族国家是德国人的正当目标,但他们有责任保持对多民族国家的满意。”失败的打击使他开始对自己的旧信仰进行刻苦的批判。国家的道德自治、外交政策的首要地位、作为强烈自私的大国之间富有成果的竞争的国际关系,都在逐渐消失。他更接近歌德,作为一个老人,他开始发现政治的终极真理,不是在民族国家的理想的、超个人的团体人格中,而是在个人反抗希特勒帝国的殉难中。
{"title":"Review of Richard W. Sterling, Ethics in a World of Power: The Political Ideas of Friedrich Meinecke (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1958; London, Oxford University Press, 1959)","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0026","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0026","url":null,"abstract":"Meinecke’s student and friend, Richard Sterling, composed this intellectual biography concerning Meinecke’s political ideas. Born in 1862, Meinecke was raised to venerate Hegel, Ranke, and Bismarck as pillars of the German State and conservative nationalism. Wight summed up Meinecke’s political evolution as follows: ‘In the first World War he justified the ultimatum to Serbia and the invasion of Belgium, he approved of unrestricted submarine warfare, and he explained to the minority peoples of the Central Powers that though the nation-state had been the proper goal for the Germans, it was their duty to remain content with the multi-national state. The shock of defeat started him on an assiduous criticism of his old beliefs. The moral autonomy of the State, the primacy of foreign policy, international relations as the fruitful competition of vigorously egotistic Powers, all gradually dissolved. He moved nearer to Goethe, and as an old man came to find the ultimate truth of politics not in the ideal, super-individual corporate personality of the nation-state, but in the martyrdom of the individual rebel against Hitler’s Reich.’","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"34 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125668794","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Is There a Philosophy of Statesmanship? 有一种政治哲学吗?
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0009
M. Wight
This essay assumes that readers will be familiar with Wight’s analysis distinguishing three traditions of thinking about international politics and will therefore recognize ‘three types’. The ‘three groups’, Wight observes, consist of (1) ‘idealists’ and ‘revolutionaries’ and ‘Utopians’ committed to serving the ‘general will’ and ‘the cause’; (2) ‘moralists’ and ‘Grotians’ dedicated to upholding treaties and the rule of law; and (3) ‘realists’ and ‘Machiavellians’ concerned with calculating how to defend and advance ‘the national interest’. With regard to survival imperatives, however, Wight holds that ‘all statesmen are realists’. He also qualifies this exposition of three traditions of thinking about international relations by pointing out that some Grotians and moralists have championed ‘a different Utopia’, an ideal distinct from the revolutionary uniformity sought by certain religions and ideologies. This different Utopia was the League of Nations, an institution designed to bring about a peaceful universal legal order. The League’s advocates expected a majority of nations, backed by world public opinion, to maintain peace and order through rational appeals and, if necessary, economic sanctions, with war as a final recourse to restore international amity.
本文假设读者将熟悉怀特的分析,区分国际政治思维的三种传统,因此将认识到“三种类型”。怀特观察到,“三个群体”包括:(1)“理想主义者”、“革命者”和“乌托邦主义者”,他们致力于为“公意”和“事业”服务;(2)致力于维护条约和法治的“道德主义者”和“格罗提主义者”;(3)“现实主义者”和“马基雅维利主义者”关心如何捍卫和推进“国家利益”。然而,关于生存的必要性,怀特认为“所有的政治家都是现实主义者”。他还指出,一些格罗蒂亚和道德家支持“一种不同的乌托邦”,这是一种不同于某些宗教和意识形态所追求的革命统一性的理想,从而对三种思考国际关系的传统进行了阐述。这个不同的乌托邦是国际联盟,一个旨在带来和平的普遍法律秩序的机构。国际联盟的支持者期望大多数国家在世界舆论的支持下,通过合理的呼吁,并在必要时通过经济制裁,以战争作为恢复国际和睦的最后手段,来维持和平与秩序。
{"title":"Is There a Philosophy of Statesmanship?","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0009","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0009","url":null,"abstract":"This essay assumes that readers will be familiar with Wight’s analysis distinguishing three traditions of thinking about international politics and will therefore recognize ‘three types’. The ‘three groups’, Wight observes, consist of (1) ‘idealists’ and ‘revolutionaries’ and ‘Utopians’ committed to serving the ‘general will’ and ‘the cause’; (2) ‘moralists’ and ‘Grotians’ dedicated to upholding treaties and the rule of law; and (3) ‘realists’ and ‘Machiavellians’ concerned with calculating how to defend and advance ‘the national interest’. With regard to survival imperatives, however, Wight holds that ‘all statesmen are realists’. He also qualifies this exposition of three traditions of thinking about international relations by pointing out that some Grotians and moralists have championed ‘a different Utopia’, an ideal distinct from the revolutionary uniformity sought by certain religions and ideologies. This different Utopia was the League of Nations, an institution designed to bring about a peaceful universal legal order. The League’s advocates expected a majority of nations, backed by world public opinion, to maintain peace and order through rational appeals and, if necessary, economic sanctions, with war as a final recourse to restore international amity.","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"9 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126402106","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Communist Theory of International Relations 共产主义国际关系理论
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0010
M. Wight
This essay analyses the distinctive effects of Marxist-Leninist ideology and Communist practice on states ruled by Communist parties and states with non-Communist or ‘bourgeois’ regimes. Communist regimes assert that they are historically destined to triumph over ‘capitalist’ and ‘imperialist’ governments. From 1917 to 1944, the Soviet Union was the sole Communist-governed state. Since 1944 there have been multiple Communist-ruled states. Such states generally have formal state-to-state relations in addition to Communist party-to-party relations. Non-Communist-ruled states may have oppositional relations with domestic and foreign Communist parties as well as formal relations with the foreign ministries of Communist-led states. The Communist Party of the Soviet Union has claimed that its decisions bind all Communist parties, but it has also accepted the primacy of a global gathering of Communist parties. Disputes among Communist parties over doctrine and interests that are theoretically congruent raise questions about the coherence of the ideology. Forming a Communist world-state to suppress national rivalries could offer a solution, but at the cost of abandoning national state sovereignties and the autonomy of specific Communist parties.
本文分析了马克思列宁主义意识形态和共产主义实践对共产党统治的国家和非共产主义或“资产阶级”政权的国家的独特影响。共产主义政权断言,他们在历史上注定要战胜“资本主义”和“帝国主义”政府。从1917年到1944年,苏联是唯一一个由共产党统治的国家。自1944年以来,出现了多个共产党统治的国家。这些国家除了党与党之间的关系外,通常还有正式的国与国关系。非共产党统治的国家可能与国内外共产党有对立关系,也可能与共产党领导的国家的外交部有正式关系。苏联共产党声称,它的决定对所有共产党都有约束力,但它也接受了全球共产党集会的首要地位。共产党之间关于理论上一致的学说和利益的争论引发了对意识形态一致性的质疑。建立一个共产主义世界国家来压制民族竞争可能是一个解决方案,但代价是放弃民族国家主权和特定共产党的自治权。
{"title":"The Communist Theory of International Relations","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0010","url":null,"abstract":"This essay analyses the distinctive effects of Marxist-Leninist ideology and Communist practice on states ruled by Communist parties and states with non-Communist or ‘bourgeois’ regimes. Communist regimes assert that they are historically destined to triumph over ‘capitalist’ and ‘imperialist’ governments. From 1917 to 1944, the Soviet Union was the sole Communist-governed state. Since 1944 there have been multiple Communist-ruled states. Such states generally have formal state-to-state relations in addition to Communist party-to-party relations. Non-Communist-ruled states may have oppositional relations with domestic and foreign Communist parties as well as formal relations with the foreign ministries of Communist-led states. The Communist Party of the Soviet Union has claimed that its decisions bind all Communist parties, but it has also accepted the primacy of a global gathering of Communist parties. Disputes among Communist parties over doctrine and interests that are theoretically congruent raise questions about the coherence of the ideology. Forming a Communist world-state to suppress national rivalries could offer a solution, but at the cost of abandoning national state sovereignties and the autonomy of specific Communist parties.","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"12 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"120944706","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the Abolition of War 《论废除战争
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0015
M. Wight
In this essay Wight advanced four main criticisms of the proposal by Walter Millis for the abolition of what Millis called ‘the war system’. First, the proposal disregards ‘the positive or constructive functions of war in international society’, such as bringing about ‘desirable change’, gaining independence, preserving independence, and maintaining the balance of power. Second, the proposal to abolish war understates ‘the intractability of international conflicts’ and exaggerates the role of armaments and military formations in causing war. The true causes of war reside in ‘human passions and conflicting interests’, not weapons. Third, the proposal to eradicate war fails to recognize the price that must be paid to defeat aggression and establish order. Fourth, no effective alternative institution has been found to replace ‘the war system’ as a means to perform certain functions, including the prevention of detrimental change. The vision of an ‘international government’ ruling the world without war ultimately implies ‘a monopoly of power’, including nuclear arms, perhaps under ‘an American–Russian dyarchy’, despite ‘the intrinsic instability of dyarchy’ and its ‘disagreeableness’ for the rival powers, such as China and France.
在这篇文章中,怀特对沃尔特·米利斯提出的废除米利斯所谓的“战争体系”的建议提出了四个主要批评。首先,该提议忽视了“战争在国际社会中的积极或建设性作用”,例如带来“理想的变化”,获得独立,保持独立以及维持力量平衡。第二,废除战争的提议低估了“国际冲突的棘手性”,夸大了军备和军事编队在引发战争中的作用。战争的真正原因在于“人类的激情和利益冲突”,而不是武器。第三,消灭战争的建议没有认识到战胜侵略和建立秩序所必须付出的代价。第四,没有发现任何有效的替代机构可以取代“战争制度”作为履行某些职能的手段,包括防止有害的变化。“国际政府”在没有战争的情况下统治世界的愿景最终意味着“权力的垄断”,包括核武器,可能在“美俄王朝”的统治下,尽管“王朝的内在不稳定性”以及它对竞争对手(如中国和法国)的“不愉快”。
{"title":"On the Abolition of War","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0015","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0015","url":null,"abstract":"In this essay Wight advanced four main criticisms of the proposal by Walter Millis for the abolition of what Millis called ‘the war system’. First, the proposal disregards ‘the positive or constructive functions of war in international society’, such as bringing about ‘desirable change’, gaining independence, preserving independence, and maintaining the balance of power. Second, the proposal to abolish war understates ‘the intractability of international conflicts’ and exaggerates the role of armaments and military formations in causing war. The true causes of war reside in ‘human passions and conflicting interests’, not weapons. Third, the proposal to eradicate war fails to recognize the price that must be paid to defeat aggression and establish order. Fourth, no effective alternative institution has been found to replace ‘the war system’ as a means to perform certain functions, including the prevention of detrimental change. The vision of an ‘international government’ ruling the world without war ultimately implies ‘a monopoly of power’, including nuclear arms, perhaps under ‘an American–Russian dyarchy’, despite ‘the intrinsic instability of dyarchy’ and its ‘disagreeableness’ for the rival powers, such as China and France.","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"54 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114949063","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Review of Hans J. Morgenthau, Dilemmas of Politics, and Correspondence (University of Chicago Press; and London, Cambridge University Press, 1958) 汉斯·摩根索:《政治困境与函授》(芝加哥大学出版社;伦敦,剑桥大学出版社,1958年)
Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0027
M. Wight
In Wight’s view, ‘Perhaps the most interesting thing about this book is that it does not mention Morgenthau’s colleague at Chicago, Leo Strauss [ … ] Agreed in their concern about the retreat of political science into “the trivial, the formal, the methodological, the purely theoretical, the remotely historical”, they are divided by the gulf of natural law.’ Morgenthau asserted, however, that Wight in his review had made ‘a factual error’. Morgenthau quoted another one of his books, In Defense of the National Interest: ‘There is a profound and neglected truth hidden in Hobbes’s extreme dictum that the state creates morality as well as law and that there is neither morality nor law outside the state. Universal moral principles, such as justice or equality, are capable of guiding political action only to the extent that they have been given concrete content and have been related to political situations by society.’ Morgenthau wrote in criticism of Wight’s review: ‘To say that a truth is “hidden” in an “extreme” dictum can hardly be called an endorsement of the dictum. To call a position “extreme” is not to identify oneself with the position but to disassociate oneself from it. In the quoted passage I was trying to establish the point, in contrast to Hobbes’s, that moral principles are universal and, hence, are not created by the state.’ Wight replied: ‘I am sorry to have misinterpreted Professor Morgenthau, but I rejoice that my error has evoked an authoritative exegesis of a disputed passage.’
在怀特看来,“也许这本书最有趣的地方是,它没有提到摩根索在芝加哥的同事里奥·施特劳斯[…]他们对政治学退步到‘琐碎的、形式的、方法论的、纯理论的、遥远的历史的’的担忧是一致的,他们被自然法的鸿沟分隔开了。”然而,摩根索断言,怀特在他的评论中犯了“一个事实错误”。摩根索引用了他的另一本著作《保卫国家利益》:“在霍布斯的极端格言中,隐藏着一个深刻而被忽视的真理,即国家创造道德和法律,在国家之外既没有道德也没有法律。”普遍的道德原则,例如正义或平等,只有在它们被赋予具体内容并被社会与政治局势联系起来的情况下,才能指导政治行动。摩根索在批评怀特的评论时写道:“把真理‘隐藏’在‘极端’格言中,很难说是对这句格言的认可。”把一种立场称为“极端”,并不是要把自己与这种立场认同,而是要把自己与这种立场分离开来。在引用的段落中,我试图建立一个观点,与霍布斯的观点相反,道德原则是普遍的,因此,不是由国家创造的。怀特回答说:“我很抱歉误解了摩根索教授的意思,但我很高兴我的错误引起了对一段有争议的段落的权威解释。”
{"title":"Review of Hans J. Morgenthau, Dilemmas of Politics, and Correspondence (University of Chicago Press; and London, Cambridge University Press, 1958)","authors":"M. Wight","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0027","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848219.003.0027","url":null,"abstract":"In Wight’s view, ‘Perhaps the most interesting thing about this book is that it does not mention Morgenthau’s colleague at Chicago, Leo Strauss [ … ] Agreed in their concern about the retreat of political science into “the trivial, the formal, the methodological, the purely theoretical, the remotely historical”, they are divided by the gulf of natural law.’ Morgenthau asserted, however, that Wight in his review had made ‘a factual error’. Morgenthau quoted another one of his books, In Defense of the National Interest: ‘There is a profound and neglected truth hidden in Hobbes’s extreme dictum that the state creates morality as well as law and that there is neither morality nor law outside the state. Universal moral principles, such as justice or equality, are capable of guiding political action only to the extent that they have been given concrete content and have been related to political situations by society.’ Morgenthau wrote in criticism of Wight’s review: ‘To say that a truth is “hidden” in an “extreme” dictum can hardly be called an endorsement of the dictum. To call a position “extreme” is not to identify oneself with the position but to disassociate oneself from it. In the quoted passage I was trying to establish the point, in contrast to Hobbes’s, that moral principles are universal and, hence, are not created by the state.’ Wight replied: ‘I am sorry to have misinterpreted Professor Morgenthau, but I rejoice that my error has evoked an authoritative exegesis of a disputed passage.’","PeriodicalId":126645,"journal":{"name":"International Relations and Political Philosophy","volume":"49 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"117106454","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
International Relations and Political Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1