首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Biomedical Semantics最新文献

英文 中文
The Origin of Cross-Cultural Differences in Referential Intuitions: Perspective Taking in the Gödel Case 参照直觉跨文化差异的起源:Gödel案例的视角
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-08-07 DOI: 10.1093/jos/ffab010
Jincai Li
How do proper names refer? This question about reference is critical for philosophers studying language, linguists investigating meaning and reference, and psycholinguists interested in how children acquire names. Over the past century, philosophers have put forward two classical theories to explain the link between a name and the entity it refers to, i.e., the descriptivist theory proposed by Frege (1892/1948), Russell (1905) and Searle (1958) among others, and the causal-historical view most notably advocated by Kripke (1980). On the former account, a name gets its referent through associated definite descriptions. Thus, when a speaker uses a name, they typically refer to whoever best fits the descriptive content attached to that name. For instance, the name “Kamala Harris” refers to the lady Kamala Harris because she is the sole individual who could uniquely satisfy the descriptive content “the first female vice president of the United States” that is commonly associated with the name nowadays. In contrast, according to the Kripkean causal-historical view, a name refers to a person via a link that is originated in the initial naming ceremony and then gets passed down through a community of speakers. Kripke contends that proper names are rigid designators and they continue to refer to the individuals who were initially given the name, even when they turn out to have none of the properties that speakers associate with this name (1980). That means, on the causal-historical picture, the name “Kamala Harris” would still refer to the person Kamala Harris even if she had not been elected the vice president of the United States. In the philosophical literature, the received wisdom is that Kripke supported his causalhistorical view of reference with the famous “Gödel” thought experiment. Suppose the only thing most people have heard about the mathematician Kurt Gödel is that he is the person who proved the incompleteness of arithmetic, which thus is the only possible definite description these people could associate with Gödel. And now imagine that the person who bears this name (Kurt Gödel) didn’t actually prove the theorem, but instead stole it from a fellow named Schmidt who did all the work. In this case, the descriptivist theory predicts that the name “Gödel” would refer to Schmidt, because Schmidt is the person best fitting
专有名称如何指代?这个关于指称的问题对于研究语言的哲学家,研究意义和指称的语言学家,以及对儿童如何获得名字感兴趣的心理语言学家来说是至关重要的。在过去的一个世纪里,哲学家们提出了两种经典理论来解释名称与其所指代的实体之间的联系,即Frege(1892/1948)、Russell(1905)和Searle(1958)等人提出的描述主义理论,以及Kripke(1980)最引人注目的因果历史观点。在前一种情况下,名称通过相关的确定描述获得其所指。因此,当演讲者使用一个名称时,他们通常指的是最适合该名称附带的描述性内容的人。例如,“卡玛拉·哈里斯”这个名字指的是卡玛拉·哈里斯女士,因为她是唯一一个能够独特地满足“美国第一位女副总统”这一描述内容的人,这一描述内容如今通常与这个名字联系在一起。相反,根据Kripkean的因果历史观点,一个名字是通过一个链接来指代一个人的,这个链接起源于最初的命名仪式,然后通过说话者的社区传递下去。Kripke认为专有名称是一种严格的指示,它们继续指代最初被赋予该名称的个人,即使他们最终没有说话者与该名称相关的任何属性(1980)。这意味着,在因果历史的图景中,“卡玛拉·哈里斯”这个名字仍然指的是卡玛拉·哈里斯这个人,即使她没有被选为美国副总统。在哲学文献中,公认的智慧是克里普克用著名的“Gödel”思想实验来支持他的因果史观。假设大多数人听说过的关于数学家Kurt Gödel的唯一一件事就是他是证明了算术不完备性的人,因此这是这些人能联想到Gödel的唯一可能的明确描述。现在想象一下,拥有这个名字的人(Kurt Gödel)实际上并没有证明这个定理,而是从一个名叫施密特的家伙那里偷来的,他做了所有的工作。在这种情况下,描述主义理论预测“Gödel”这个名字指的是施密特,因为施密特是最合适的人选
{"title":"The Origin of Cross-Cultural Differences in Referential Intuitions: Perspective Taking in the Gödel Case","authors":"Jincai Li","doi":"10.1093/jos/ffab010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffab010","url":null,"abstract":"How do proper names refer? This question about reference is critical for philosophers studying language, linguists investigating meaning and reference, and psycholinguists interested in how children acquire names. Over the past century, philosophers have put forward two classical theories to explain the link between a name and the entity it refers to, i.e., the descriptivist theory proposed by Frege (1892/1948), Russell (1905) and Searle (1958) among others, and the causal-historical view most notably advocated by Kripke (1980). On the former account, a name gets its referent through associated definite descriptions. Thus, when a speaker uses a name, they typically refer to whoever best fits the descriptive content attached to that name. For instance, the name “Kamala Harris” refers to the lady Kamala Harris because she is the sole individual who could uniquely satisfy the descriptive content “the first female vice president of the United States” that is commonly associated with the name nowadays. In contrast, according to the Kripkean causal-historical view, a name refers to a person via a link that is originated in the initial naming ceremony and then gets passed down through a community of speakers. Kripke contends that proper names are rigid designators and they continue to refer to the individuals who were initially given the name, even when they turn out to have none of the properties that speakers associate with this name (1980). That means, on the causal-historical picture, the name “Kamala Harris” would still refer to the person Kamala Harris even if she had not been elected the vice president of the United States. In the philosophical literature, the received wisdom is that Kripke supported his causalhistorical view of reference with the famous “Gödel” thought experiment. Suppose the only thing most people have heard about the mathematician Kurt Gödel is that he is the person who proved the incompleteness of arithmetic, which thus is the only possible definite description these people could associate with Gödel. And now imagine that the person who bears this name (Kurt Gödel) didn’t actually prove the theorem, but instead stole it from a fellow named Schmidt who did all the work. In this case, the descriptivist theory predicts that the name “Gödel” would refer to Schmidt, because Schmidt is the person best fitting","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"64 1","pages":"415-440"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-08-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74534964","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
A Note on the Cardinalities of Sets of Scalar Alternatives 关于标量备选集的基数的注记
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-06-25 DOI: 10.1093/jos/ffab011
S. Mascarenhas
Formal theories of scalar implicature appeal crucially to a set of alternatives. These are the alternative statements that a speaker could have made but chose not to in pragmatic accounts, and the alternative statements that figure in the computation of exhaustivity operators in grammatical approaches. I show that the three sufficiently explicit theories of alternatives in the literature generate sets of alternatives that grow at least exponentially as a function of the input, and that these theories generate very large sets even for relatively small inputs. For pragmatic accounts of scalar implicature, I argue these results are hard or impossible to square with what we know independently about manipulating alternatives from the psychology of human reasoning. I propose that they pose a weaker but more general challenge for grammatical approaches, since alternatives as required by exhaustivity operators occur elsewhere in grammar, for example as part of the semantics of operators like “only” and “even.”
标量蕴涵的形式理论对一组备选方案至关重要。这些是说话者本可以在语用中做出但选择不做的替代陈述,以及在语法方法中计算穷竭运算符的替代陈述。我展示了文献中三个足够明确的选择理论产生的选择集,至少作为输入的函数呈指数增长,并且这些理论即使对于相对较小的输入也会产生非常大的选择集。对于标量蕴涵的实用主义解释,我认为这些结果很难或不可能与我们从人类推理心理学中独立了解的操纵选择相一致。我认为它们对语法方法构成了较弱但更普遍的挑战,因为穷竭运算符所要求的替代出现在语法的其他地方,例如作为“only”和“even”等运算符的语义的一部分。
{"title":"A Note on the Cardinalities of Sets of Scalar Alternatives","authors":"S. Mascarenhas","doi":"10.1093/jos/ffab011","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffab011","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Formal theories of scalar implicature appeal crucially to a set of alternatives. These are the alternative statements that a speaker could have made but chose not to in pragmatic accounts, and the alternative statements that figure in the computation of exhaustivity operators in grammatical approaches. I show that the three sufficiently explicit theories of alternatives in the literature generate sets of alternatives that grow at least exponentially as a function of the input, and that these theories generate very large sets even for relatively small inputs. For pragmatic accounts of scalar implicature, I argue these results are hard or impossible to square with what we know independently about manipulating alternatives from the psychology of human reasoning. I propose that they pose a weaker but more general challenge for grammatical approaches, since alternatives as required by exhaustivity operators occur elsewhere in grammar, for example as part of the semantics of operators like “only” and “even.”","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"73 1","pages":"473-482"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-06-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86077672","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Contribution of Gestures to the Semantics of Non-Canonical Questions 手势对非规范问题语义的贡献
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-06-14 DOI: 10.1093/JOS/FFAB007
Michela Ippolito
The symbolic gesture MAT (mano a tulipano) used by native speakers of Italian characterizes non-canonical wh questions when used both as a co-speech and pro-speech gesture. MAT can be executed with either a fast tempo contour or a slow tempo contour. Tempo is semantically significant: descriptively, a fast tempo characterizes a biased but information-seeking non-canonical question; a slow tempo characterizes a rhetorical non-canonical question. I argue that the fast contour is the default tempo of MAT and that it brings about a biased interpretation. Slowing down the movement occurs when the feature [slow] is added: the semantic contribution of this feature is to add the presupposition that the question is resolved in the conversational context, resulting in the rhetorical interpretation of the question.
意大利语母语者使用的象征性手势MAT (mano a tulipano)在作为共同言语和支持言语的手势使用时具有非规范的wh问题特征。MAT可以用快节奏轮廓或慢节奏轮廓来执行。语速在语义上是重要的:在描述上,快的语速是一个有偏见但寻求信息的非规范问题的特征;慢节奏是修辞性非规范问题的特点。我认为快速轮廓是MAT的默认节奏,它带来了有偏见的解释。当添加[slow]特征时,动作会减慢:该特征的语义贡献是添加了问题在会话上下文中得到解决的前提,从而导致对问题的修辞解释。
{"title":"The Contribution of Gestures to the Semantics of Non-Canonical Questions","authors":"Michela Ippolito","doi":"10.1093/JOS/FFAB007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/JOS/FFAB007","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 The symbolic gesture MAT (mano a tulipano) used by native speakers of Italian characterizes non-canonical wh questions when used both as a co-speech and pro-speech gesture. MAT can be executed with either a fast tempo contour or a slow tempo contour. Tempo is semantically significant: descriptively, a fast tempo characterizes a biased but information-seeking non-canonical question; a slow tempo characterizes a rhetorical non-canonical question. I argue that the fast contour is the default tempo of MAT and that it brings about a biased interpretation. Slowing down the movement occurs when the feature [slow] is added: the semantic contribution of this feature is to add the presupposition that the question is resolved in the conversational context, resulting in the rhetorical interpretation of the question.","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"13 1","pages":"363-392"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-06-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84995235","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Subclausal Local Contexts 分条款的地方背景
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/JOS/FFAB004
A. Anvari, Kyle Blumberg
One of the central topics in semantic theory over the last few decades concerns the nature of local contexts. Recently, theorists have tried to develop general, non-stipulative accounts of local contexts (Ingason, 2016; Mandelkern & Romoli, 2017a; Schlenker, 2009). In this paper, we contribute to this literature by drawing attention to the local contexts of subclausal expressions. More specifically, we focus on the local contexts of quantificational determiners, e.g. ‘all’, ‘both’, etc. Our central tool for probing the local contexts of subclausal elements is the principle Maximize Presupposition! (Percus, 2006; Singh, 2011). The empirical basis of our investigation concerns some data discussed by Anvari (2018b), e.g. the fact that sentences such as ‘All of the two presidential candidates are crooked’ are unacceptable. In order to explain this, we suggest that the local context of determiners needs to contain the information carried by their restrictor. However, no existing non-stipulative account predicts this. Consequently, we think that the local contexts of subclausal expressions will likely have to be stipulated. This result has important consequences for debates in semantics and pragmatics, e.g. those around the so-called “explanatory problem” for dynamic semantics (Heim, 1990; Schlenker, 2009; Soames, 1982).
在过去的几十年里,语义理论的中心议题之一是局部语境的性质。最近,理论家们试图发展对当地背景的一般的、非规定性的解释(Ingason, 2016;Mandelkern & Romoli, 2017a;Schlenker, 2009)。在本文中,我们通过提请注意分条款表达的局部上下文来贡献这一文献。更具体地说,我们关注定量限定词的局部语境,例如“all”、“both”等。我们探索子条款要素的局部语境的核心工具是最大化预设原则!(Percus, 2006;辛格,2011)。我们调查的经验基础涉及Anvari (2018b)讨论的一些数据,例如,“所有两个总统候选人都是扭曲的”这样的句子是不可接受的。为了解释这一点,我们建议限定词的局部上下文需要包含限定词所携带的信息。然而,没有现有的非规定帐户预测到这一点。因此,我们认为很可能必须规定分条款用语的当地情况。这一结果对语义学和语用学的争论产生了重要影响,例如围绕动态语义学的所谓“解释问题”(Heim, 1990;Schlenker, 2009;兜,1982)。
{"title":"Subclausal Local Contexts","authors":"A. Anvari, Kyle Blumberg","doi":"10.1093/JOS/FFAB004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/JOS/FFAB004","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 One of the central topics in semantic theory over the last few decades concerns the nature of local contexts. Recently, theorists have tried to develop general, non-stipulative accounts of local contexts (Ingason, 2016; Mandelkern & Romoli, 2017a; Schlenker, 2009). In this paper, we contribute to this literature by drawing attention to the local contexts of subclausal expressions. More specifically, we focus on the local contexts of quantificational determiners, e.g. ‘all’, ‘both’, etc. Our central tool for probing the local contexts of subclausal elements is the principle Maximize Presupposition! (Percus, 2006; Singh, 2011). The empirical basis of our investigation concerns some data discussed by Anvari (2018b), e.g. the fact that sentences such as ‘All of the two presidential candidates are crooked’ are unacceptable. In order to explain this, we suggest that the local context of determiners needs to contain the information carried by their restrictor. However, no existing non-stipulative account predicts this. Consequently, we think that the local contexts of subclausal expressions will likely have to be stipulated. This result has important consequences for debates in semantics and pragmatics, e.g. those around the so-called “explanatory problem” for dynamic semantics (Heim, 1990; Schlenker, 2009; Soames, 1982).","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"174 1","pages":"393-414"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78542982","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Why and how to engage expert stakeholders in ontology development: insights from social and behavioural sciences. 为什么以及如何让专家利益相关者参与本体开发:来自社会和行为科学的见解。
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-03-23 DOI: 10.1186/s13326-021-00240-6
Emma Norris, Janna Hastings, Marta M Marques, Ailbhe N Finnerty Mutlu, Silje Zink, Susan Michie

Background: Incorporating the feedback of expert stakeholders in ontology development is important to ensure content is appropriate, comprehensive, meets community needs and is interoperable with other ontologies and classification systems. However, domain experts are often not formally engaged in ontology development, and there is little available guidance on how this involvement should best be conducted and managed. Social and behavioural science studies often involve expert feedback in the development of tools and classification systems but have had little engagement with ontology development. This paper aims to (i) demonstrate how expert feedback can enhance ontology development, and (ii) provide practical recommendations on how to conduct expert feedback in ontology development using methodologies from the social and behavioural sciences.

Main body: Considerations for selecting methods for engaging stakeholders are presented. Mailing lists and issue trackers as existing methods used frequently in ontology development are discussed. Advisory boards and working groups, feedback tasks, consensus exercises, discussions and workshops are presented as potential methods from social and behavioural sciences to incorporate in ontology development.

Conclusions: A variety of methods from the social and behavioural sciences exist to enable feedback from expert stakeholders in ontology development. Engaging domain experts in ontology development enables depth and clarity in ontology development, whilst also establishing advocates for an ontology upon its completion.

背景:在本体开发中纳入专家利益相关者的反馈对于确保内容适当、全面、满足社区需求以及与其他本体和分类系统可互操作非常重要。然而,领域专家通常没有正式参与本体开发,而且关于如何最好地进行和管理这种参与,几乎没有可用的指导。社会和行为科学研究通常涉及工具和分类系统开发中的专家反馈,但很少涉及本体开发。本文旨在(i)展示专家反馈如何增强本体开发,以及(ii)就如何使用社会科学和行为科学的方法在本体开发中进行专家反馈提供实用建议。主体:介绍了选择利益相关者参与方法的考虑因素。讨论了本体开发中常用的邮件列表和问题跟踪方法。咨询委员会和工作组、反馈任务、共识练习、讨论和研讨会被认为是社会和行为科学纳入本体发展的潜在方法。结论:社会科学和行为科学中存在各种方法,可以在本体开发中获得专家利益相关者的反馈。让领域专家参与本体开发可以使本体开发具有深度和清晰度,同时也可以在本体完成后为其建立倡导者。
{"title":"Why and how to engage expert stakeholders in ontology development: insights from social and behavioural sciences.","authors":"Emma Norris, Janna Hastings, Marta M Marques, Ailbhe N Finnerty Mutlu, Silje Zink, Susan Michie","doi":"10.1186/s13326-021-00240-6","DOIUrl":"10.1186/s13326-021-00240-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p><strong>Background: </strong>Incorporating the feedback of expert stakeholders in ontology development is important to ensure content is appropriate, comprehensive, meets community needs and is interoperable with other ontologies and classification systems. However, domain experts are often not formally engaged in ontology development, and there is little available guidance on how this involvement should best be conducted and managed. Social and behavioural science studies often involve expert feedback in the development of tools and classification systems but have had little engagement with ontology development. This paper aims to (i) demonstrate how expert feedback can enhance ontology development, and (ii) provide practical recommendations on how to conduct expert feedback in ontology development using methodologies from the social and behavioural sciences.</p><p><strong>Main body: </strong>Considerations for selecting methods for engaging stakeholders are presented. Mailing lists and issue trackers as existing methods used frequently in ontology development are discussed. Advisory boards and working groups, feedback tasks, consensus exercises, discussions and workshops are presented as potential methods from social and behavioural sciences to incorporate in ontology development.</p><p><strong>Conclusions: </strong>A variety of methods from the social and behavioural sciences exist to enable feedback from expert stakeholders in ontology development. Engaging domain experts in ontology development enables depth and clarity in ontology development, whilst also establishing advocates for an ontology upon its completion.</p>","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"12 1","pages":"4"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-03-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7985588/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10339022","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Deferred Reference of Proper Names 专有名称的延迟引用
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-03-08 DOI: 10.1093/JOS/FFAB001
Katarzyna Kijania-Placek, P. Banás
In this paper, we argue that proper names have deferred uses. Following Geoffrey Nunberg, we describe the deferred reference mechanism by which a linguistic expression refers to something in the world by exploiting a contextually salient relation between an index and the referent in question. Nunberg offered a thorough analysis of deferred uses of indexicals but claimed that proper names do not permit such uses. We, however, offer a number of examples of uses of proper names which pass grammatical tests for deferred usage, as put forward by Nunberg.
在本文中,我们认为专有名称具有延迟用途。按照Geoffrey Nunberg的说法,我们描述了递延引用机制,通过这种机制,语言表达通过利用索引和所指之间的上下文显著关系来引用世界上的事物。纽伯格对指数的延迟使用进行了全面的分析,但声称专有名称不允许这样的使用。然而,我们提供了一些专有名称用法的例子,这些例子通过了Nunberg提出的递延用法的语法测试。
{"title":"Deferred Reference of Proper Names","authors":"Katarzyna Kijania-Placek, P. Banás","doi":"10.1093/JOS/FFAB001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/JOS/FFAB001","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In this paper, we argue that proper names have deferred uses. Following Geoffrey Nunberg, we describe the deferred reference mechanism by which a linguistic expression refers to something in the world by exploiting a contextually salient relation between an index and the referent in question. Nunberg offered a thorough analysis of deferred uses of indexicals but claimed that proper names do not permit such uses. We, however, offer a number of examples of uses of proper names which pass grammatical tests for deferred usage, as put forward by Nunberg.","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"11 1","pages":"195-219"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-03-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83490162","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Disjunction in Negative Contexts: A Cross-Linguistic Experimental Study 否定语境中的析取:跨语言实验研究
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/jos/ffab002
Oana Lungu, Anamaria Fălăuș, F. Panzeri
This squib reports experimental findings from a study investigating the interpretation of simple disjunction in negative contexts in four languages: Italian, French, English, Romanian. We provide evidence that casts doubt on the robustness of the distinction between PPI disjunction languages and non-PPI disjunction languages. The difference turns out to be less clear-cut than assumed in the theoretical (e.g., Szabolcsi 2002, Spector 2014, Nicolae 2017) or experimental literature (e.g., Crain 2012, Guasti et al. 2017). The results reported here inform current accounts of positive polarity and flesh out some methodological issues raised by the various tasks used in experimental investigations of the polarity sensitivity of disjunction.
本文报道了一项研究的实验结果,该研究调查了四种语言(意大利语、法语、英语、罗马尼亚语)在否定语境中对简单分离的解释。我们提供的证据对PPI分离语言和非PPI分离语言之间区别的鲁棒性产生了怀疑。事实证明,这种差异并不像理论(例如,Szabolcsi 2002, Spector 2014, Nicolae 2017)或实验文献(例如,Crain 2012, Guasti et al. 2017)中假设的那样明确。这里报告的结果为目前关于正极性的描述提供了信息,并充实了在分离极性敏感性的实验研究中使用的各种任务所提出的一些方法问题。
{"title":"Disjunction in Negative Contexts: A Cross-Linguistic Experimental Study","authors":"Oana Lungu, Anamaria Fălăuș, F. Panzeri","doi":"10.1093/jos/ffab002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffab002","url":null,"abstract":"This squib reports experimental findings from a study investigating the interpretation of simple disjunction in negative contexts in four languages: Italian, French, English, Romanian. We provide evidence that casts doubt on the robustness of the distinction between PPI disjunction languages and non-PPI disjunction languages. The difference turns out to be less clear-cut than assumed in the theoretical (e.g., Szabolcsi 2002, Spector 2014, Nicolae 2017) or experimental literature (e.g., Crain 2012, Guasti et al. 2017). The results reported here inform current accounts of positive polarity and flesh out some methodological issues raised by the various tasks used in experimental investigations of the polarity sensitivity of disjunction.","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"27 1 1","pages":"221-247"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82705749","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
The Semantics of Emotive Markers and Other Illocutionary Content 情绪标记语与其他言外内容的语义
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/jos/ffab005
J. Rett
I coin the term ‘emotive markers’ to describe words like fortunately and alas which encode not-at-issue information about the speaker’s emotive attitude towards the content of the utterances they occur in. I argue that there are important differences emotive markers and other encoders of not-at-issue content, in particular utterance modifiers like frankly or evidential adverbs like apparently. In contrast to these, emotive markers can result in Moore’s Paradox and always range over their local argument. I conclude that the contribution of emotive markers should be treated as ‘illocutionary content’, on par with the speaker’s other Discourse Commitments (Gunlogson, 2001), and I model this analysis in the dynamic sub-sentential update framework in Farkas and Bruce (2010).
我创造了“情感标记”这个词来描述像“幸运”和“唉”这样的词,它们编码了关于说话者对话语内容的情感态度的非争议信息。我认为情绪标记和非争议内容的其他编码器存在重要差异,特别是像坦率这样的话语修饰语或像显然这样的证据副词。与此相反,情感标记可能导致摩尔悖论,并且总是超出其局部争论的范围。我的结论是,情绪标记的贡献应该被视为“言外内容”,与说话者的其他话语承诺一样(Gunlogson, 2001),我在Farkas和Bruce(2010)的动态子句更新框架中对这一分析进行了建模。
{"title":"The Semantics of Emotive Markers and Other Illocutionary Content","authors":"J. Rett","doi":"10.1093/jos/ffab005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffab005","url":null,"abstract":"I coin the term ‘emotive markers’ to describe words like fortunately and alas which encode not-at-issue information about the speaker’s emotive attitude towards the content of the utterances they occur in. I argue that there are important differences emotive markers and other encoders of not-at-issue content, in particular utterance modifiers like frankly or evidential adverbs like apparently. In contrast to these, emotive markers can result in Moore’s Paradox and always range over their local argument. I conclude that the contribution of emotive markers should be treated as ‘illocutionary content’, on par with the speaker’s other Discourse Commitments (Gunlogson, 2001), and I model this analysis in the dynamic sub-sentential update framework in Farkas and Bruce (2010).","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"18 1","pages":"305-340"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89414645","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 22
The Semantics of Comparatives: A Difference-Based Approach 比较级语义:一种基于差异的方法
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/jos/ffab003
Linmin Zhang, Jia Ling
1 Degree semantics has been developed to study how the meanings of 2 measurement and comparison are encoded in natural language. Within degree 3 semantics, this paper proposes a difference-based (or subtraction-based) approach 4 to analyze the semantics of comparatives. The motivation is the measurability and 5 comparability of differences involved in comparatives. The main claim is that 6 comparatives encode a subtraction equation among three scalar values: two 7 measurements along an interval scale and the difference between them. We 8 contribute two innovations: (i) using interval arithmetic to implement subtraction, 9 and (ii) analyzing comparative morpheme -er/more as an additive particle, denoting 10 the default, most general, positive difference. Our analysis inherits existing insights 11 in the literature. Moreover, the innovations bring new conceptual and empirical 12 advantages. In particular, we address the interpretation of comparatives containing 13 than-clause-internal quantifiers and various kinds of numerical differentials. We also 14 account for three puzzles with regard to the scope island issue, the monotonicity of 15 than-clauses, and the discourse status of the standard in comparison. 16
1度语义学是研究测量和比较的意义如何在自然语言中编码而发展起来的。在3级语义中,本文提出了一种基于差异(或基于减法)的方法来分析比较级的语义。动机是比较物中差异的可测量性和可比性。主要的主张是,6比较值编码了三个标量值之间的减法方程:沿着间隔尺度的两个7测量值以及它们之间的差值。我们贡献了两项创新:(i)使用区间算法实现减法,9和(ii)分析比较语素-er/more作为加性粒子,表示默认的,最普遍的,正差异。我们的分析继承了文献中已有的见解。此外,这些创新还带来了新的概念和经验优势。特别地,我们讨论了包含13个比子句内部量词和各种数值微分的比较级的解释。我们还解释了范围岛问题、15个比子句的单调性以及标准在比较中的话语地位三个方面的困惑。16
{"title":"The Semantics of Comparatives: A Difference-Based Approach","authors":"Linmin Zhang, Jia Ling","doi":"10.1093/jos/ffab003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffab003","url":null,"abstract":"1 Degree semantics has been developed to study how the meanings of 2 measurement and comparison are encoded in natural language. Within degree 3 semantics, this paper proposes a difference-based (or subtraction-based) approach 4 to analyze the semantics of comparatives. The motivation is the measurability and 5 comparability of differences involved in comparatives. The main claim is that 6 comparatives encode a subtraction equation among three scalar values: two 7 measurements along an interval scale and the difference between them. We 8 contribute two innovations: (i) using interval arithmetic to implement subtraction, 9 and (ii) analyzing comparative morpheme -er/more as an additive particle, denoting 10 the default, most general, positive difference. Our analysis inherits existing insights 11 in the literature. Moreover, the innovations bring new conceptual and empirical 12 advantages. In particular, we address the interpretation of comparatives containing 13 than-clause-internal quantifiers and various kinds of numerical differentials. We also 14 account for three puzzles with regard to the scope island issue, the monotonicity of 15 than-clauses, and the discourse status of the standard in comparison. 16","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"35 1","pages":"249-303"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89547589","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Coordinating Ifs 协调Ifs
IF 1.9 3区 工程技术 Q3 MATHEMATICAL & COMPUTATIONAL BIOLOGY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/jos/ffab006
Justin Khoo
Accounting for the behavior of conjoined and disjoined if-clauses is not easy for standard theories of conditionals that treat if as either an operator or restrictor. In this paper, I discuss four observations about coordinated if-clauses, and motivate a semantics for conditionals that reorients the compositional structure of the restrictor theory. On my proposal, if-clauses provide restrictions on modal domains, but they do so by way of a higher type intermediary—a set of propositions—that is collapsed by the modal. I argue that combining this view with an independently plausible type-shifting operation applied to or and and predicts the range of data we find for conditionals with coordinated if-clauses.
对于将if视为操作符或限制符的标准条件理论来说,考虑连用和不连用if-子句的行为并不容易。在本文中,我讨论了关于协调if-子句的四个观察结果,并激发了条件的语义,重新定位了限制子理论的组合结构。在我的建议中,if-子句提供了对模态域的限制,但它们是通过一种更高类型的中介——一组被模态分解的命题——来实现的。我认为,将此视图与应用于或和的独立可信的类型转换操作相结合,并预测我们为具有协调if-子句的条件找到的数据范围。
{"title":"Coordinating Ifs","authors":"Justin Khoo","doi":"10.1093/jos/ffab006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffab006","url":null,"abstract":"Accounting for the behavior of conjoined and disjoined if-clauses is not easy for standard theories of conditionals that treat if as either an operator or restrictor. In this paper, I discuss four observations about coordinated if-clauses, and motivate a semantics for conditionals that reorients the compositional structure of the restrictor theory. On my proposal, if-clauses provide restrictions on modal domains, but they do so by way of a higher type intermediary—a set of propositions—that is collapsed by the modal. I argue that combining this view with an independently plausible type-shifting operation applied to or and and predicts the range of data we find for conditionals with coordinated if-clauses.","PeriodicalId":15055,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Biomedical Semantics","volume":"25 1","pages":"341-361"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81054393","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"工程技术","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of Biomedical Semantics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1