首页 > 最新文献

Journal of the American Philosophical Association最新文献

英文 中文
Liveliness as a Theory of Meaning in Life: Problems and Prospects 作为生命意义理论的活跃性:问题与展望
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-20 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.26
KIRK LOUGHEED
I aim to more fully develop a theory of meaning in life based on the concept of life force that is important to a substantial number of Africans in the sub-Sahara region. While life force implies a large invisible ontology, Thaddeus Metz has recently developed an entirely naturalistic version of it known as liveliness. However, he also offers two objections that hinge on the idea that life force cannot accommodate intuitions that certain types of knowledge and progress are valuable for their own sakes. I respond by noting that elsewhere Metz has developed a defense of the intrinsic value of knowledge by appealing to the idea that meeting a person's existential needs can be important for self-realization and hence for their meaning. If this is right, then the community ought to support such a person in their pursuit of knowledge even if doing so leads to no useful outcomes.
我的目标是更全面地发展一种基于生命力概念的生命意义理论,这对撒哈拉以南地区的大量非洲人来说很重要。虽然生命力意味着一个巨大的、看不见的本体论,但塞迪斯·梅斯(Thaddeus Metz)最近开发了一个完全自然的版本,称为活力。然而,他也提出了两种反对意见,这两种反对意见的依据是,生命的力量不能适应直觉,即某些类型的知识和进步就其本身而言是有价值的。我的回应是,梅斯在其他地方提出了一种对知识内在价值的辩护,他认为满足一个人的存在需求对自我实现及其意义很重要。如果这是正确的,那么社会应该支持这样的人追求知识,即使这样做不会导致有用的结果。
{"title":"Liveliness as a Theory of Meaning in Life: Problems and Prospects","authors":"KIRK LOUGHEED","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.26","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.26","url":null,"abstract":"I aim to more fully develop a theory of meaning in life based on the concept of life force that is important to a substantial number of Africans in the sub-Sahara region. While life force implies a large invisible ontology, Thaddeus Metz has recently developed an entirely naturalistic version of it known as <jats:italic>liveliness</jats:italic>. However, he also offers two objections that hinge on the idea that life force cannot accommodate intuitions that certain types of knowledge and progress are valuable for their own sakes. I respond by noting that elsewhere Metz has developed a defense of the intrinsic value of knowledge by appealing to the idea that meeting a person's existential needs can be important for self-realization and hence for their meaning. If this is right, then the community ought to support such a person in their pursuit of knowledge even if doing so leads to no useful outcomes.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":"126 23","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138514602","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Institutional Genidentity 机构Genidentity
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-20 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.23
JOSHUA RUST
An abbreviated history of marriage helps motivate the question of whether ancient Roman marriage and contemporary love marriage could qualify as stages of the same (token) institution despite carrying significantly different functions, deontological powers, and constitutive rules. Having raised the question of institutional identity over time, I proceed to answer the question by appealing to Kurt Lewin's notion of genidentity. Lewin intends the notion of genidentity to track the spatiotemporal unfolding of different physical and biological processes, such as ontogenesis. I extend the notion of genidentity to the institutional sphere by identifying two ‘re-anchoring mechanisms’ that would describe the conditions under which institutions with different characteristics could nevertheless qualify as the same institution across time. First, formal institutions can be re-anchored by way of a self-amending secondary rule. Second, informal institutions can be re-anchored by leveraging the inherent indeterminacy of the exemplars that indexically define them. I then argue ancient Roman marriage and contemporary love marriage are genidentical in virtue of the actions of a (mostly) informal re-anchoring mechanism.
一个简短的婚姻史有助于激发一个问题,即古罗马婚姻和当代爱情婚姻是否可以作为同一(象征性)制度的阶段,尽管它们具有显著不同的功能、道义权力和构成规则。随着时间的推移,我提出了制度认同的问题,我通过诉诸库尔特·勒温(Kurt Lewin)的genidentity概念来回答这个问题。Lewin打算用genidentity的概念来追踪不同物理和生物过程的时空展开,比如个体发生(ontogenesis)。我通过确定两种“再锚定机制”,将genidentity的概念扩展到制度领域,这两种机制将描述具有不同特征的制度在不同时期仍有资格成为同一制度的条件。首先,正式制度可以通过自我修正的次要规则重新锚定。其次,非正式制度可以通过利用以指数方式定义它们的范例的固有不确定性来重新锚定。然后,我认为古罗马的婚姻和当代的爱情婚姻在(大部分)非正式的重新锚定机制的作用下是相同的。
{"title":"Institutional Genidentity","authors":"JOSHUA RUST","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.23","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.23","url":null,"abstract":"An abbreviated history of marriage helps motivate the question of whether ancient Roman marriage and contemporary love marriage could qualify as stages of the same (token) institution despite carrying significantly different functions, deontological powers, and constitutive rules. Having raised the question of institutional identity over time, I proceed to answer the question by appealing to Kurt Lewin's notion of genidentity. Lewin intends the notion of genidentity to track the spatiotemporal unfolding of different physical and biological processes, such as ontogenesis. I extend the notion of genidentity to the institutional sphere by identifying two ‘re-anchoring mechanisms’ that would describe the conditions under which institutions with different characteristics could nevertheless qualify as the same institution across time. First, formal institutions can be re-anchored by way of a self-amending secondary rule. Second, informal institutions can be re-anchored by leveraging the inherent indeterminacy of the exemplars that indexically define them. I then argue ancient Roman marriage and contemporary love marriage are genidentical in virtue of the actions of a (mostly) informal re-anchoring mechanism.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":"127 25","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138514633","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Humanism: A Reconsideration 人文主义:重新思考
2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-23 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.18
ALEKSY TARASENKO-STRUC
Abstract Humanism is the view that people treat others inhumanely when we fail to see them as human beings, so that our treatment of them will tend to be more humane when we (fully) see their humanity. Recently, humanist views have been criticized on the grounds that the perpetrators of inhumanity regard their victims as human and treat them inhumanely partly for this reason. I argue that the two most common objections to humanist views (and their relatives) are unpersuasive: not only does the evidence marshaled against these views fail to disprove them, it could threaten them only if some questionable assumptions were granted. By providing necessary conceptual ground clearing and routing common lines of attack, I hope to determine what it would take for a humanist project to succeed, thereby paving the way for a full defense of humanism that fulfills its explanatory ambitions.
人文主义是这样一种观点:当我们没有把别人当作人来看待时,人们就会不人道地对待他们,所以当我们(完全)看到他们的人性时,我们对待他们就会更加人道。最近,人道主义观点受到了批评,理由是,不人道的肇事者将受害者视为人,并在一定程度上因此而不人道地对待他们。我认为,对人文主义观点(及其相关观点)最常见的两种反对意见是缺乏说服力的:反对这些观点的证据不仅无法反驳它们,而且只有在一些可疑的假设得到认可时,这些证据才会威胁到它们。我希望通过提供必要的概念上的澄清和确定共同的攻击路线,来确定一个人文主义项目要取得成功需要什么,从而为充分捍卫人文主义铺平道路,从而实现其解释性的雄心。
{"title":"Humanism: A Reconsideration","authors":"ALEKSY TARASENKO-STRUC","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.18","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.18","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Humanism is the view that people treat others inhumanely when we fail to see them as human beings, so that our treatment of them will tend to be more humane when we (fully) see their humanity. Recently, humanist views have been criticized on the grounds that the perpetrators of inhumanity regard their victims as human and treat them inhumanely partly for this reason. I argue that the two most common objections to humanist views (and their relatives) are unpersuasive: not only does the evidence marshaled against these views fail to disprove them, it could threaten them only if some questionable assumptions were granted. By providing necessary conceptual ground clearing and routing common lines of attack, I hope to determine what it would take for a humanist project to succeed, thereby paving the way for a full defense of humanism that fulfills its explanatory ambitions.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":"46 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135368325","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Idealist Panpsychism and Spacetime Structure 唯心主义泛心论与时空结构
2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-09 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.17
DAMIAN ALEKSIEV
Abstract This paper presents a novel argument against one theoretically attractive form of panpsychism. I argue that ‘idealist panpsychism’ is false because it cannot account for spacetime's structure. Idealist panpsychists posit that fundamental reality is purely experiential. Moreover, they posit that consciousness at the fundamental level metaphysically grounds and explains both the facts of physics and the facts of human consciousness. I argue that if idealist panpsychism is true, human consciousness and consciousness at the fundamental level will have the same metrical structure. However, as I demonstrate, human consciousness does not exhibit the same metrical structure as spacetime. Consequently, the idealist panpsychist faces an explanatory gap between the fundamental consciousness she posits and spacetime. Idealist panpsychism is incompatible with the existence of such an explanatory gap. Thus, idealist panpsychists must either close this explanatory gap (which I argue they lack the resources to do), or idealist panpsychism is false.
摘要本文提出了一种新颖的论点,反对一种理论上有吸引力的泛心论形式。我认为“唯心主义泛心论”是错误的,因为它不能解释时空的结构。唯心主义泛心论者认为基本的实在是纯粹经验的。此外,他们假设意识在基本层面上是形而上学的基础,并解释了物理学和人类意识的事实。我认为,如果唯心主义的泛心论是正确的,那么人类意识和意识在基本层面上将具有相同的格律结构。然而,正如我所展示的,人类意识并没有表现出与时空相同的韵律结构。因此,唯心主义泛心论者面临着她所假定的基本意识与时空之间的解释鸿沟。唯心主义的泛心论与这种解释缺口的存在是不相容的。因此,唯心主义泛心论者必须要么填补这一解释缺口(我认为他们缺乏这样做的资源),要么唯心主义泛心论是错误的。
{"title":"Idealist Panpsychism and Spacetime Structure","authors":"DAMIAN ALEKSIEV","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.17","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.17","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This paper presents a novel argument against one theoretically attractive form of panpsychism. I argue that ‘idealist panpsychism’ is false because it cannot account for spacetime's structure. Idealist panpsychists posit that fundamental reality is purely experiential. Moreover, they posit that consciousness at the fundamental level metaphysically grounds and explains both the facts of physics and the facts of human consciousness. I argue that if idealist panpsychism is true, human consciousness and consciousness at the fundamental level will have the same metrical structure. However, as I demonstrate, human consciousness does not exhibit the same metrical structure as spacetime. Consequently, the idealist panpsychist faces an explanatory gap between the fundamental consciousness she posits and spacetime. Idealist panpsychism is incompatible with the existence of such an explanatory gap. Thus, idealist panpsychists must either close this explanatory gap (which I argue they lack the resources to do), or idealist panpsychism is false.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":"274 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135044555","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An Epistemic Version of Pascal's Wager 帕斯卡赌注的认识论版本
2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-06 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.9
ELIZABETH JACKSON
Abstract Epistemic consequentialism is the view that epistemic goodness is more fundamental than epistemic rightness. In this article, I examine the relationship between epistemic consequentialism and theistic belief. I argue that in an epistemic consequentialist framework, there is an epistemic reason to believe in God. Imagine having an unlimited amount of time to ask an omniscient being anything you wanted. The potential epistemic benefits would be enormous. Considerations like these point to an epistemic version of Pascal's wager. I compare and contrast the epistemic wager with the traditional wager, and argue that the epistemic wager has several notable advantages.
摘要认识结果主义认为认识的善比认识的正确更为根本。在这篇文章中,我考察了认识论结果主义和有神论信仰之间的关系。我认为在认识论的结果主义框架中,有一个认识论的理由去相信上帝。想象一下,你有无限的时间向一个无所不知的人询问你想要的任何东西。潜在的认知效益将是巨大的。诸如此类的考虑指向帕斯卡赌注的认识论版本。我将认知投注与传统投注进行比较和对比,并认为认知投注有几个显著的优势。
{"title":"An Epistemic Version of Pascal's Wager","authors":"ELIZABETH JACKSON","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.9","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Epistemic consequentialism is the view that epistemic goodness is more fundamental than epistemic rightness. In this article, I examine the relationship between epistemic consequentialism and theistic belief. I argue that in an epistemic consequentialist framework, there is an epistemic reason to believe in God. Imagine having an unlimited amount of time to ask an omniscient being anything you wanted. The potential epistemic benefits would be enormous. Considerations like these point to an epistemic version of Pascal's wager. I compare and contrast the epistemic wager with the traditional wager, and argue that the epistemic wager has several notable advantages.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":"62 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135351647","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Inductive Reasoning Involving Social Kinds 涉及社会类型的归纳推理
2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-28 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.20
BARRETT EMERICK, TYLER HILDEBRAND
Abstract Most social policies cannot be defended without making inductive inferences. For example, consider certain arguments for racial profiling and affirmative action, respectively. They begin with statistics about crime or socioeconomic indicators. Next, there is an inductive step in which the statistic is projected from the past to the future. Finally, there is a normative step in which a policy is proposed as a response in the service of some goal—for example, to reduce crime or to correct socioeconomic imbalances. In comparison to the normative step, the inductive step of a policy defense may seem trivial. We argue that this is not so. Satisfying the demands of the inductive step is difficult, and doing so has important but underappreciated implications for the normative step. In this paper, we provide an account of induction in social contexts and explore its implications for policy. Our account helps to explain which normative principles we ought to accept, and as a result it can explain why it is acceptable to make inferences involving race in some contexts (e.g., in defense of affirmative action) but not in others (e.g., in defense of racial profiling).
大多数社会政策不进行归纳推理就无法为其辩护。例如,分别考虑种族定性和平权行动的某些论点。他们从有关犯罪或社会经济指标的统计数据开始。接下来是归纳步骤,将统计数据从过去预测到未来。最后,还有一个规范性步骤,在这个步骤中,一项政策被提议作为服务于某些目标的回应,例如,减少犯罪或纠正社会经济失衡。与规范步骤相比,策略辩护的归纳步骤可能显得微不足道。我们认为事实并非如此。满足归纳步骤的要求是困难的,这样做对规范步骤具有重要但未被重视的含义。在本文中,我们提供归纳在社会背景下的帐户,并探讨其对政策的影响。我们的解释有助于解释我们应该接受哪些规范原则,因此它可以解释为什么在某些情况下(例如,为平权行动辩护)可以接受涉及种族的推论,而在其他情况下(例如,为种族定性辩护)则不能接受。
{"title":"Inductive Reasoning Involving Social Kinds","authors":"BARRETT EMERICK, TYLER HILDEBRAND","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.20","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.20","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Most social policies cannot be defended without making inductive inferences. For example, consider certain arguments for racial profiling and affirmative action, respectively. They begin with statistics about crime or socioeconomic indicators. Next, there is an inductive step in which the statistic is projected from the past to the future. Finally, there is a normative step in which a policy is proposed as a response in the service of some goal—for example, to reduce crime or to correct socioeconomic imbalances. In comparison to the normative step, the inductive step of a policy defense may seem trivial. We argue that this is not so. Satisfying the demands of the inductive step is difficult, and doing so has important but underappreciated implications for the normative step. In this paper, we provide an account of induction in social contexts and explore its implications for policy. Our account helps to explain which normative principles we ought to accept, and as a result it can explain why it is acceptable to make inferences involving race in some contexts (e.g., in defense of affirmative action) but not in others (e.g., in defense of racial profiling).","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":"36 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135343960","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Considerateness Differentiated: Three Types of Virtuousness 体贴的分化:三种类型的美德
2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-25 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.22
KRISTJÁN KRISTJÁNSSON
Abstract Despite the prevalence of the virtue of considerateness in everyday moral discourse and the proliferation of philosophical studies of virtue language, considerateness hardly ever appears on philosophical agendas. When discussed in academia, its meaning seems fuzzy and unclear. This article makes amends for this gap by subjecting considerateness to conceptual scrutiny. The author argues that considerateness designates a cluster concept, encompassing three types of virtuousness that share a family resemblance only. One is a hybrid civic-moral social-glue virtue, extensionally equivalent to Aristotle's virtue of agreeableness. The second is an intellectual virtue of phronetic consideration (moral sensitivity and integration). The third is a full-fledged discrete moral virtue with standard Aristotelian features of a golden-mean structure and an emotional component as a motivator. The advantages of identifying these three types of virtuousness are elicited, as are some of the educational ramifications of analyzing the differentia of considerateness in this way.
尽管在日常道德话语中普遍存在着体贴的美德,并且对美德语言的哲学研究也在激增,但体贴几乎从未出现在哲学议程上。在学术界讨论时,其含义似乎模糊不清。本文通过对考虑性进行概念审查来弥补这一差距。作者认为,体贴指定一个集群概念,包括三种类型的美德,共享一个家庭的相似性。一种是混合的公民道德社会粘合美德,在外延上等同于亚里士多德的宜人性美德。第二是一种理性的思考能力(道德的敏感性和统一性)。第三种是一种成熟的离散道德美德,具有标准的亚里士多德式的中庸之道结构特征和作为激励因素的情感成分。识别这三种类型的美德的好处被引出,就像以这种方式分析体贴的差异的一些教育后果一样。
{"title":"Considerateness Differentiated: Three Types of Virtuousness","authors":"KRISTJÁN KRISTJÁNSSON","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.22","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.22","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Despite the prevalence of the virtue of considerateness in everyday moral discourse and the proliferation of philosophical studies of virtue language, considerateness hardly ever appears on philosophical agendas. When discussed in academia, its meaning seems fuzzy and unclear. This article makes amends for this gap by subjecting considerateness to conceptual scrutiny. The author argues that considerateness designates a cluster concept, encompassing three types of virtuousness that share a family resemblance only. One is a hybrid civic-moral social-glue virtue, extensionally equivalent to Aristotle's virtue of agreeableness. The second is an intellectual virtue of phronetic consideration (moral sensitivity and integration). The third is a full-fledged discrete moral virtue with standard Aristotelian features of a golden-mean structure and an emotional component as a motivator. The advantages of identifying these three types of virtuousness are elicited, as are some of the educational ramifications of analyzing the differentia of considerateness in this way.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":"66 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135815609","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Functional Analysis of Human Deception 人类欺骗的功能分析
2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-21 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.19
VLADIMIR KRSTIĆ
Abstract A satisfactory analysis of human deception must rule out cases where it is a mistake or an accident that person B was misled by person A's behavior. Therefore, most scholars think that deceivers must intend to deceive. This article argues that there is a better solution: rather than appealing to the deceiver's intentions, we should appeal to the function of their behavior. After all, animals and plants engage in deception, and most of them are not capable of forming intentions. Accordingly, certain human behavior is deceptive if and only if its function is to mislead. This solves our problem because if the function of A's behavior was to mislead, B's ending up misled was not an accident or a mere mistake even if A did not intend to deceive B.
要想对人的欺骗行为进行令人满意的分析,必须排除乙被甲的行为误导是错误或意外的情况。因此,大多数学者认为,骗子必须有意欺骗。本文认为,有一个更好的解决方案:我们应该诉诸于他们行为的功能,而不是诉诸于骗子的意图。毕竟,动物和植物都有欺骗行为,而且它们大多数都没有形成意图的能力。因此,当且仅当某些人类行为的功能是误导时,它就是欺骗性的。这就解决了我们的问题,因为如果A行为的功能是误导,那么即使A没有欺骗B的意图,B最终被误导也不是意外或单纯的错误。
{"title":"A Functional Analysis of Human Deception","authors":"VLADIMIR KRSTIĆ","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.19","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.19","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract A satisfactory analysis of human deception must rule out cases where it is a mistake or an accident that person B was misled by person A's behavior. Therefore, most scholars think that deceivers must intend to deceive. This article argues that there is a better solution: rather than appealing to the deceiver's intentions, we should appeal to the function of their behavior. After all, animals and plants engage in deception, and most of them are not capable of forming intentions. Accordingly, certain human behavior is deceptive if and only if its function is to mislead. This solves our problem because if the function of A's behavior was to mislead, B's ending up misled was not an accident or a mere mistake even if A did not intend to deceive B.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136155235","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What Do Beginning Students Think about Philosophy before Their First College Course? 初学的学生在上第一门大学课程之前对哲学有什么看法?
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-04 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.12
Bailie Peterson, David Agboola, Kelly Lundberg
In this article, we present the results of an original study identifying the perceptions of beginning philosophy students at the start of their first introductory course. We surveyed over 1,100 students representing over 40 universities and colleges in the United States regarding their initial perceptions of gender bias, inclusivity, value, understanding, similarities, and enjoyment of philosophy. We analyzed the results based on gender, first-generation status, and student of color status. This work represents the perspectives of a more diverse range of students, reflecting far more first-generation college students (40 percent) and students who identify as people of color (43 percent) than in previous work. Additionally, this study provides novel data as we were able to collect data on the first day of classes, in most cases before students were exposed to syllabi or content that could inform their views about philosophy. Understanding what beginning students think about philosophy before formal exposure to the field might help us to identify concerns, misconceptions, and areas for improvement. Many results are striking, and our project offers insight into the initial perspectives of philosophy students.
在这篇文章中,我们展示了一项原创研究的结果,该研究确定了哲学系学生在第一门入门课程开始时的看法。我们调查了来自美国40多所大学和学院的1100多名学生,了解他们对性别偏见、包容性、价值观、理解、相似性和哲学享受的最初看法。我们根据性别、第一代身份和有色人种学生身份对结果进行了分析。这项工作代表了更多元化的学生的观点,反映了比前一项工作多得多的第一代大学生(40%)和有色人种学生(43%)。此外,这项研究提供了新的数据,因为我们能够在上课的第一天收集数据,在大多数情况下,在学生接触到可以告知他们哲学观点的教学大纲或内容之前。在正式接触该领域之前,了解初学哲学的学生对哲学的看法可能有助于我们识别担忧、误解和需要改进的领域。许多结果是惊人的,我们的项目提供了对哲学学生最初观点的见解。
{"title":"What Do Beginning Students Think about Philosophy before Their First College Course?","authors":"Bailie Peterson, David Agboola, Kelly Lundberg","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.12","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.12","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In this article, we present the results of an original study identifying the perceptions of beginning philosophy students at the start of their first introductory course. We surveyed over 1,100 students representing over 40 universities and colleges in the United States regarding their initial perceptions of gender bias, inclusivity, value, understanding, similarities, and enjoyment of philosophy. We analyzed the results based on gender, first-generation status, and student of color status. This work represents the perspectives of a more diverse range of students, reflecting far more first-generation college students (40 percent) and students who identify as people of color (43 percent) than in previous work. Additionally, this study provides novel data as we were able to collect data on the first day of classes, in most cases before students were exposed to syllabi or content that could inform their views about philosophy. Understanding what beginning students think about philosophy before formal exposure to the field might help us to identify concerns, misconceptions, and areas for improvement. Many results are striking, and our project offers insight into the initial perspectives of philosophy students.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49243785","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Standpoint Epistemology and Epistemic Peerhood: A Defense of Epistemic Privilege 立场认识论与认识贵族:对认识特权的捍卫
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-08-30 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.6
Briana Toole
Standpoint epistemology is committed to the view that some epistemic advantage can be drawn from the position of powerlessness. Call this the epistemic privilege thesis. This thesis stands in need of explication and support. In providing that explication and support, I first distinguish between two readings of the thesis: the thesis that marginalized social locations confer some epistemic advantages (the epistemic advantage thesis) and the thesis that marginalized standpoints generate better, more accurate knowledge (the standpoint thesis). I then develop the former by appealing to the notion of epistemic peers available in the disagreement literature. I next turn to the latter thesis, arguing that consciousness-raising plays an analogous role in the achievement of a standpoint as training does in the achievement of expertise. The upshot of this analysis is that it clarifies that while marginalization is necessary (though not sufficient) for epistemic advantage, it is neither necessary nor sufficient for epistemic privilege.
立场认识论致力于这样一种观点,即无能为力的地位可以获得一些认识上的优势。称之为认知特权论。本文需要进一步的阐释和支持。在提供这种解释和支持时,我首先区分了这篇论文的两种解读:边缘化的社会位置赋予了一些认知优势的论文(认知优势论文)和边缘化的立场产生了更好、更准确的知识的论文(立场论文)。然后,我通过引用分歧文献中可用的认知同行的概念来发展前者。接下来,我转向后一篇论文,认为提高意识在实现立场方面发挥着类似于培训在实现专业知识方面的作用。这一分析的结果是,它澄清了边缘化对于认识优势是必要的(尽管不充分),但对于认识特权来说既不必要也不充分。
{"title":"Standpoint Epistemology and Epistemic Peerhood: A Defense of Epistemic Privilege","authors":"Briana Toole","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.6","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Standpoint epistemology is committed to the view that some epistemic advantage can be drawn from the position of powerlessness. Call this the epistemic privilege thesis. This thesis stands in need of explication and support. In providing that explication and support, I first distinguish between two readings of the thesis: the thesis that marginalized social locations confer some epistemic advantages (the epistemic advantage thesis) and the thesis that marginalized standpoints generate better, more accurate knowledge (the standpoint thesis). I then develop the former by appealing to the notion of epistemic peers available in the disagreement literature. I next turn to the latter thesis, arguing that consciousness-raising plays an analogous role in the achievement of a standpoint as training does in the achievement of expertise. The upshot of this analysis is that it clarifies that while marginalization is necessary (though not sufficient) for epistemic advantage, it is neither necessary nor sufficient for epistemic privilege.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44657382","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Journal of the American Philosophical Association
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1