首页 > 最新文献

Journal of the American Philosophical Association最新文献

英文 中文
Fair Play Externalism and the Obligation to Relinquish 公平竞赛外部主义与放弃义务
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-04 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2024.4
JOSEPH FRIGAULT

This essay defends a new account of wrongful benefiting based on the principle of fair play. In particular, I argue that certain structurally-conferred group-based benefits or privileges can ground obligations on the part of innocent beneficiaries to relinquish specific gains for purposes of redistribution regardless of whether their receipt is sourced in wrongdoing or involves the imposition of harm upon relevant others. I call this approach to fair play reasoning externalist insofar as it turns on a novel conception of free-riding that eschews necessary appeal to beneficiaries’ mental states or volition. After presenting an empirical example to help illustrate the sort of benefiting at issue and distinguishing my account from arguments rooted in the notion of structural injustice, I defend it via what I call the extension argument, respond to two salient objections, and close by suggesting its potential political utility in the American context specifically.

本文以公平竞争原则为基础,对不正当受益进行了新的论证。具体而言,我认为某些结构上赋予的基于群体的利益或特权可以作为无辜受益人为再分配目的放弃特定收益的义务的基础,而不管他们的收益是否来源于不法行为或涉及对相关他人的伤害。我将这种公平游戏推理方法称为外部主义,因为它基于一种新颖的搭便车概念,避开了对受益人精神状态或意志的必要诉求。在提出了一个经验性的例子来帮助说明有争议的受益类型,并将我的论述与植根于结构性不公正概念的论证区分开来之后,我通过我称之为扩展论证的方法为其辩护,回应了两个突出的反对意见,最后提出了它在美国语境下的潜在政治效用。
{"title":"Fair Play Externalism and the Obligation to Relinquish","authors":"JOSEPH FRIGAULT","doi":"10.1017/apa.2024.4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2024.4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This essay defends a new account of wrongful benefiting based on the principle of fair play. In particular, I argue that certain structurally-conferred group-based benefits or privileges can ground obligations on the part of innocent beneficiaries to relinquish specific gains for purposes of redistribution regardless of whether their receipt is sourced in wrongdoing or involves the imposition of harm upon relevant others. I call this approach to fair play reasoning <span>externalist</span> insofar as it turns on a novel conception of free-riding that eschews necessary appeal to beneficiaries’ mental states or volition. After presenting an empirical example to help illustrate the sort of benefiting at issue and distinguishing my account from arguments rooted in the notion of structural injustice, I defend it via what I call the extension argument, respond to two salient objections, and close by suggesting its potential political utility in the American context specifically.</p>","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141255933","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Intellectual Virtue Signaling and (Non)Expert Credibility 知识美德信号与(非)专家可信度
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-22 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2024.3
K. Harris
In light of the complexity of some important matters, the best epistemic strategy for laypersons is often to rely heavily on the judgments of subject matter experts. However, given the contentiousness of some issues and the existence of fake experts, determining who to trust from the lay perspective is no simple matter. One proposed approach is for laypersons to attend to displays of intellectual virtue as indicators of expertise. I argue that this strategy is likely to fail, as non-experts often display apparent intellectual virtues while legitimate experts often display apparent intellectual vices. Then, I argue that this challenge is difficult to overcome, as experts who attempt to better exhibit apparent intellectual virtues would likely compromise their own reliability in the process. Finally, I discuss two conclusions—one more optimistic and one more pessimistic—that one might draw concerning the role of intellectual virtue in the identification of experts.
鉴于一些重要问题的复杂性,外行人最好的认识论策略往往是严重依赖主题专家的判断。然而,鉴于某些问题的争议性和假专家的存在,从外行的角度来确定该相信谁并不是一件简单的事情。一种建议的方法是让非专业人士关注知识美德的展示,将其作为专业知识的指标。我认为,这一策略很可能会失败,因为非专家往往表现出明显的知识美德,而合法专家则往往表现出明显的知识恶习。然后,我认为这一挑战难以克服,因为专家如果试图更好地表现出明显的知识美德,很可能会在这一过程中损害自身的可靠性。最后,我讨论了关于智力美德在专家识别中的作用可能得出的两个结论--一个比较乐观,一个比较悲观。
{"title":"Intellectual Virtue Signaling and (Non)Expert Credibility","authors":"K. Harris","doi":"10.1017/apa.2024.3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2024.3","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In light of the complexity of some important matters, the best epistemic strategy for laypersons is often to rely heavily on the judgments of subject matter experts. However, given the contentiousness of some issues and the existence of fake experts, determining who to trust from the lay perspective is no simple matter. One proposed approach is for laypersons to attend to displays of intellectual virtue as indicators of expertise. I argue that this strategy is likely to fail, as non-experts often display apparent intellectual virtues while legitimate experts often display apparent intellectual vices. Then, I argue that this challenge is difficult to overcome, as experts who attempt to better exhibit apparent intellectual virtues would likely compromise their own reliability in the process. Finally, I discuss two conclusions—one more optimistic and one more pessimistic—that one might draw concerning the role of intellectual virtue in the identification of experts.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141108704","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
“Spectator to One's Own Life” "自己生活的旁观者"
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-20 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2024.2
Mark Robert Taylor
Galen Strawson (2004) has championed an influential argument against the view that a life is, or ought to be, understood as a kind of story with temporal extension. The weight of his argument rests on his self-report of his experience of life as lacking the form or temporal extension necessary for narrative. And though this argument has been widely accepted, I argue that it ought to have been rejected. On one hand, the hypothetical non-diachronic life Strawson proposes would likely be psychologically fragmented. On the other, it would certainly be morally diminished, for it would necessarily lack the capacity for integrity.
盖伦-斯特劳森(Galen Strawson,2004 年)提出了一个颇具影响力的论点,反对将人生理解为或应该理解为一种具有时间延展性的故事。他的论点主要基于他的自我报告,即他的生命体验缺乏叙事所必需的形式或时间延展性。尽管这一论点已被广泛接受,但我认为它本应被摒弃。一方面,斯特劳森假设的非双时态生活很可能在心理上是支离破碎的。另一方面,它在道德上肯定会被削弱,因为它必然缺乏完整性的能力。
{"title":"“Spectator to One's Own Life”","authors":"Mark Robert Taylor","doi":"10.1017/apa.2024.2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2024.2","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Galen Strawson (2004) has championed an influential argument against the view that a life is, or ought to be, understood as a kind of story with temporal extension. The weight of his argument rests on his self-report of his experience of life as lacking the form or temporal extension necessary for narrative. And though this argument has been widely accepted, I argue that it ought to have been rejected. On one hand, the hypothetical non-diachronic life Strawson proposes would likely be psychologically fragmented. On the other, it would certainly be morally diminished, for it would necessarily lack the capacity for integrity.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141120363","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Joanna Baillie on Sympathetic Curiosity and Elizabeth Hamilton's Critique 乔安娜-贝利:同情好奇心与伊丽莎白-汉密尔顿的批评
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-18 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2024.1
DEBORAH BOYLE

Scholars working on recovering forgotten historical women philosophers have noted the importance of looking beyond traditional philosophical genres. This strategy is particularly important for finding Scottish women philosophers. By considering non-canonical genres, we can see the philosophical interest of the works of Scottish poet and playwright Joanna Baillie (1762–1851), who presents an account of “sympathetic curiosity” as one of the basic principles of the human mind. Baillie's work is also interesting for being a rare case of a woman's philosophical work that was discussed in print by another woman philosopher – in this case, by Elizabeth Hamilton (1758–1816), who argues for the importance of a feature of human nature that she calls the “selfish principle.” The article suggests that focusing on critical engagements between historical women philosophers can help integrate their texts into the history of philosophy without presenting them as “handmaidens” to male philosophers.

致力于找回被遗忘的历史女哲学家的学者们已经注意到,超越传统哲学流派的重要性。这一策略对于寻找苏格兰女哲学家尤为重要。通过考虑非经典体裁,我们可以看到苏格兰诗人兼剧作家乔安娜-贝利(Joanna Baillie,1762-1851 年)作品中的哲学趣味,她将 "同情的好奇心 "作为人类思想的基本原则之一进行了阐述。贝利的作品之所以有趣,还因为她的哲学著作罕见地由另一位女哲学家--伊丽莎白-汉密尔顿(Elizabeth Hamilton,1758-1816 年)--撰文论述,她认为人性的一个特征非常重要,她称之为 "自私原则"。文章认为,关注历史上女哲学家之间的批判性接触有助于将她们的文本纳入哲学史,而不会将她们视为男性哲学家的 "婢女"。
{"title":"Joanna Baillie on Sympathetic Curiosity and Elizabeth Hamilton's Critique","authors":"DEBORAH BOYLE","doi":"10.1017/apa.2024.1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2024.1","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Scholars working on recovering forgotten historical women philosophers have noted the importance of looking beyond traditional philosophical genres. This strategy is particularly important for finding Scottish women philosophers. By considering non-canonical genres, we can see the philosophical interest of the works of Scottish poet and playwright Joanna Baillie (1762–1851), who presents an account of “sympathetic curiosity” as one of the basic principles of the human mind. Baillie's work is also interesting for being a rare case of a woman's philosophical work that was discussed in print by another woman philosopher – in this case, by Elizabeth Hamilton (1758–1816), who argues for the importance of a feature of human nature that she calls the “selfish principle.” The article suggests that focusing on critical engagements between historical women philosophers can help integrate their texts into the history of philosophy without presenting them as “handmaidens” to male philosophers.</p>","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140155488","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Exploring Arbitrariness Objections to Time Biases 探讨时间偏差的任意性异议
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-07 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.14
ANDREW J. LATHAM, KRISTIE MILLER, JORDAN OH, SAM SHPALL, WEN YU

There are two kinds of time bias: near bias and future bias. While philosophers typically hold that near bias is rationally impermissible, many hold that future bias is rationally permissible. Call this normative hybridism. According to arbitrariness objections, certain patterns of preference are rationally impermissible because they are arbitrary. While arbitrariness objections have been leveled against both near bias and future bias, the kind of arbitrariness in question has been different. In this article we investigate whether there are forms of arbitrariness that are common to both kinds of preferences and, hence, whether there are versions of the arbitrariness objection that are objections to both near bias and future bias. If there are, then this might go some way toward undermining normative hybridism and to defending thoroughgoing time-neutralism.

时间偏差有两种:近期偏差和未来偏差。哲学家通常认为,近期偏差在理性上是不允许的,但许多哲学家认为,未来偏差在理性上是允许的。这就是规范混杂主义。根据任意性反对意见,某些偏好模式在理性上是不允许的,因为它们是任意的。虽然任意性反对既针对近期偏好,也针对未来偏好,但所涉及的任意性类型却有所不同。在本文中,我们将探究是否存在两种偏好所共有的任意性形式,因此,是否存在既反对近期偏好又反对未来偏好的任意性反对版本。如果有,那么这可能会在一定程度上削弱规范混合主义,并为彻底的时间中性主义辩护。
{"title":"Exploring Arbitrariness Objections to Time Biases","authors":"ANDREW J. LATHAM, KRISTIE MILLER, JORDAN OH, SAM SHPALL, WEN YU","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.14","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.14","url":null,"abstract":"<p>There are two kinds of time bias: near bias and future bias. While philosophers typically hold that near bias is rationally impermissible, many hold that future bias is rationally permissible. Call this <span>normative hybridism</span>. According to arbitrariness objections, certain patterns of preference are rationally impermissible because they are arbitrary. While arbitrariness objections have been leveled against both near bias and future bias, the kind of arbitrariness in question has been different. In this article we investigate whether there are forms of arbitrariness that are common to both kinds of preferences and, hence, whether there are versions of the arbitrariness objection that are objections to both near bias and future bias. If there are, then this might go some way toward undermining normative hybridism and to defending thoroughgoing time-neutralism.</p>","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140055048","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Does Studying Philosophy Make People Better Thinkers? 学习哲学会让人更善于思考吗?
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-07 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.30
MICHAEL PRINZING, MICHAEL VAZQUEZ

Philosophers often claim that doing philosophy makes people better thinkers. But what evidence is there for this empirical claim? This paper reviews extant evidence and presents some novel findings. We discuss standardized testing scores, review research on Philosophy for Children and critical thinking skills among college students, and present new empirical findings. On average, philosophers are better at logical reasoning, more reflective, and more open-minded than non-philosophers. However, there is an absence of evidence for the claim that studying philosophy led to these differences. We present some preliminary and suggestive evidence that although some of these differences may be attributable to philosophical training, others appear to be selection effects. The key takeaway is that more data are needed. We conclude by urging philosophers and interdisciplinary collaborators to gather more data to test the claim that studying philosophy makes people better thinkers.

哲学家们经常声称,从事哲学研究能使人成为更好的思想家。但这种实证性的说法有什么证据呢?本文回顾了现有的证据,并提出了一些新的发现。我们讨论了标准化测试的分数,回顾了关于儿童哲学和大学生批判性思维能力的研究,并提出了新的实证研究结果。平均而言,与非哲学家相比,哲学家的逻辑推理能力更强,更善于反思,思维更开阔。然而,学习哲学导致这些差异的说法缺乏证据。我们提出了一些初步的提示性证据,表明尽管这些差异中的一些可能归因于哲学训练,但另一些似乎是选择效应。我们得出的主要结论是,还需要更多的数据。最后,我们敦促哲学家和跨学科合作者收集更多数据,以验证 "学习哲学使人更善于思考 "这一说法。
{"title":"Does Studying Philosophy Make People Better Thinkers?","authors":"MICHAEL PRINZING, MICHAEL VAZQUEZ","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.30","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.30","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Philosophers often claim that doing philosophy makes people better thinkers. But what evidence is there for this empirical claim? This paper reviews extant evidence and presents some novel findings. We discuss standardized testing scores, review research on Philosophy for Children and critical thinking skills among college students, and present new empirical findings. On average, philosophers are better at logical reasoning, more reflective, and more open-minded than non-philosophers. However, there is an absence of evidence for the claim that studying philosophy led to these differences. We present some preliminary and suggestive evidence that although some of these differences may be attributable to philosophical training, others appear to be selection effects. The key takeaway is that more data are needed. We conclude by urging philosophers and interdisciplinary collaborators to gather more data to test the claim that studying philosophy makes people better thinkers.</p>","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140055045","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Call-Outs and Call-Ins 呼出和呼入
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-01 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.29
KELLY HERBISON, PAUL-MIKHAIL CATAPANG PODOSKY
The phenomena of call-outs and call-ins are fiercely debated. Are they mere instances of virtue signaling? Or can they actually perform social justice work? This paper gains purchase on these questions by focusing on how language users negotiate norms in speech. The authors contend that norm-enacting speech not only makes a norm salient in a context but also creates conversational conditions that motivate adherence to that norm. Recognizing this allows us to define call-outs and call-ins: the act of calling-out brings with it the presupposition that its target's behavior is norm-violating, whereas the act of calling-in simply presupposes its target's willingness to revise their belief. With these definitions at hand, we evaluate whether call-outs and call-ins are suitable tools for combating social injustice.
人们对 "呼出 "和 "呼入 "现象争论不休。它们仅仅是美德信号吗?还是它们真的能实现社会正义?本文通过关注语言使用者如何在言语中协商规范,对这些问题进行了探讨。作者认为,规范作用的言语不仅使规范在语境中变得突出,而且还创造了促使人们遵守规范的对话条件。认识到这一点,我们就可以对 "呼出 "和 "呼入 "进行定义:"呼出 "行为的前提是目标对象的行为违反了规范,而 "呼入 "行为的前提则是目标对象愿意修正自己的观念。有了这些定义,我们就可以评估 "呼出 "和 "呼入 "是否是打击社会不公的合适工具。
{"title":"Call-Outs and Call-Ins","authors":"KELLY HERBISON, PAUL-MIKHAIL CATAPANG PODOSKY","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.29","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.29","url":null,"abstract":"The phenomena of call-outs and call-ins are fiercely debated. Are they mere instances of virtue signaling? Or can they actually perform social justice work? This paper gains purchase on these questions by focusing on how language users negotiate norms in speech. The authors contend that norm-enacting speech not only makes a norm salient in a context but also creates conversational conditions that motivate adherence to that norm. Recognizing this allows us to define call-outs and call-ins: the act of calling-out brings with it the presupposition that its target's behavior is norm-violating, whereas the act of calling-in simply presupposes its target's willingness to revise their belief. With these definitions at hand, we evaluate whether call-outs and call-ins are suitable tools for combating social injustice.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140025790","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Courageous Love: K. C. Bhattacharyya on the Puzzle of Painful Beauty 勇敢的爱K. C. Bhattacharyya 论痛苦之美的谜题
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-29 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.28
EMILY LAWSON, DOMINIC MCIVER LOPES
In the 1930s, the Bengali philosopher K. C. Bhattacharyya proposed a new theory of rasa, or aesthetic emotion, according to which aesthetic emotions are feelings that have other feelings as their intentional objects. This paper articulates how Bhattacharyya's theory offers a novel solution to the puzzle of how it is both possible and rational to enjoy the kind of negative emotions that are inspired by tragic and sorrowful tales. The new solution is distinct from the conversion and compensation views that dominate the existing literature, and it derives its significance from how it ties aesthetic experience to self-awareness.
20 世纪 30 年代,孟加拉哲学家 K. C. Bhattacharyya 提出了一种新的 "拉萨"(rasa)或审美情感理论,认为审美情感是以其他情感为意向对象的情感。本文阐述了巴塔查里亚的理论是如何为享受悲剧和悲伤故事所激发的那种消极情绪的可能性和合理性这一难题提供新的解决方案的。新的解决方案有别于现有文献中占主导地位的转换和补偿观点,其意义在于它如何将审美体验与自我意识联系起来。
{"title":"Courageous Love: K. C. Bhattacharyya on the Puzzle of Painful Beauty","authors":"EMILY LAWSON, DOMINIC MCIVER LOPES","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.28","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.28","url":null,"abstract":"In the 1930s, the Bengali philosopher K. C. Bhattacharyya proposed a new theory of <jats:italic>rasa</jats:italic>, or aesthetic emotion, according to which aesthetic emotions are feelings that have other feelings as their intentional objects. This paper articulates how Bhattacharyya's theory offers a novel solution to the puzzle of how it is both possible and rational to enjoy the kind of negative emotions that are inspired by tragic and sorrowful tales. The new solution is distinct from the conversion and compensation views that dominate the existing literature, and it derives its significance from how it ties aesthetic experience to self-awareness.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-02-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140025788","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two kinds of requirements of justice 两种司法要求
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-06 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.31
N. Southwood, Robert E. Goodin
Claims about what justice “requires” and the “requirements” of justice are pervasive in political philosophy. However, there is a highly significant ambiguity in such claims that appears to have gone unnoticed. Such claims may pick out either one of two categorically distinct and noncoextensive kinds of requirement that we call 1) requirements-as-necessary-conditions for justice and 2) requirements-as-demands of justice. This is an especially compelling instance of an ambiguity that John Broome has famously observed in the context of claims about other requirements (notably the requirements of rationality and morality). But it appears to have been overlooked by political philosophers in the case of claims about the requirements of justice. The ambiguity is highly significant inasmuch as failing to notice it is liable to distort our normative thinking about politics and make us vulnerable to certain kinds of normatively consequential errors: both mistakenly drawing inferences about what justice demands of us from claims that certain states or societies are not just; and mistakenly drawing inferences about what states or societies are or would be just from claims that justice does not demand of states or societies that they do certain things. Paying greater attention to the distinction between these two different kinds of requirements and the ways in which they come apart is helpful, not merely in avoiding these distortions and errors, but also in resolving, or at least clarifying, a number of other notoriously murky meta-normative debates, especially various important debates about realism and idealism in political philosophy.
政治哲学中充斥着关于正义 "要求 "什么和正义 "要求 "什么的说法。然而,在这些主张中存在着一个似乎未被注意到的非常重要的模糊性。这种说法可能会挑出两种截然不同且非广义的要求中的一种,我们称之为:1)作为正义的必要条件的要求;2)作为正义的要求的要求。约翰-布鲁姆(John Broome)在论述其他要求(尤其是理性与道德的要求)时曾指出了一种模棱两可的情况,这是一个特别令人信服的例子。但在关于正义要求的主张中,政治哲学家们似乎忽略了这一点。这种模糊性是非常重要的,因为如果不注意到这一点,就有可能扭曲我们对政治的规范性思考,使我们容易犯某些规范性后果错误:既错误地从某些国家或社会不公正的主张中推论出正义对我们的要求;又错误地从正义不要求国家或社会做某些事情的主张中推论出哪些国家或社会是公正的或会是公正的。更多地关注这两种不同要求之间的区别以及它们的不同方式,不仅有助于避免这些歪曲和错误,而且有助于解决或至少澄清其他一些臭名昭著的元规范性争论,尤其是政治哲学中关于现实主义和理想主义的各种重要争论。
{"title":"Two kinds of requirements of justice","authors":"N. Southwood, Robert E. Goodin","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.31","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.31","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Claims about what justice “requires” and the “requirements” of justice are pervasive in political philosophy. However, there is a highly significant ambiguity in such claims that appears to have gone unnoticed. Such claims may pick out either one of two categorically distinct and noncoextensive kinds of requirement that we call 1) requirements-as-necessary-conditions for justice and 2) requirements-as-demands of justice. This is an especially compelling instance of an ambiguity that John Broome has famously observed in the context of claims about other requirements (notably the requirements of rationality and morality). But it appears to have been overlooked by political philosophers in the case of claims about the requirements of justice. The ambiguity is highly significant inasmuch as failing to notice it is liable to distort our normative thinking about politics and make us vulnerable to certain kinds of normatively consequential errors: both mistakenly drawing inferences about what justice demands of us from claims that certain states or societies are not just; and mistakenly drawing inferences about what states or societies are or would be just from claims that justice does not demand of states or societies that they do certain things. Paying greater attention to the distinction between these two different kinds of requirements and the ways in which they come apart is helpful, not merely in avoiding these distortions and errors, but also in resolving, or at least clarifying, a number of other notoriously murky meta-normative debates, especially various important debates about realism and idealism in political philosophy.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-02-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139799677","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two kinds of requirements of justice 两种司法要求
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-06 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2023.31
N. Southwood, Robert E. Goodin
Claims about what justice “requires” and the “requirements” of justice are pervasive in political philosophy. However, there is a highly significant ambiguity in such claims that appears to have gone unnoticed. Such claims may pick out either one of two categorically distinct and noncoextensive kinds of requirement that we call 1) requirements-as-necessary-conditions for justice and 2) requirements-as-demands of justice. This is an especially compelling instance of an ambiguity that John Broome has famously observed in the context of claims about other requirements (notably the requirements of rationality and morality). But it appears to have been overlooked by political philosophers in the case of claims about the requirements of justice. The ambiguity is highly significant inasmuch as failing to notice it is liable to distort our normative thinking about politics and make us vulnerable to certain kinds of normatively consequential errors: both mistakenly drawing inferences about what justice demands of us from claims that certain states or societies are not just; and mistakenly drawing inferences about what states or societies are or would be just from claims that justice does not demand of states or societies that they do certain things. Paying greater attention to the distinction between these two different kinds of requirements and the ways in which they come apart is helpful, not merely in avoiding these distortions and errors, but also in resolving, or at least clarifying, a number of other notoriously murky meta-normative debates, especially various important debates about realism and idealism in political philosophy.
政治哲学中充斥着关于正义 "要求 "什么和正义 "要求 "什么的说法。然而,在这些主张中存在着一个似乎未被注意到的非常重要的模糊性。这种说法可能会挑出两种截然不同且非广义的要求中的一种,我们称之为:1)作为正义的必要条件的要求;2)作为正义的要求的要求。约翰-布鲁姆(John Broome)在论述其他要求(尤其是理性与道德的要求)时曾指出了一种模棱两可的情况,这是一个特别令人信服的例子。但在关于正义要求的主张中,政治哲学家们似乎忽略了这一点。这种模糊性是非常重要的,因为如果不注意到这一点,就有可能扭曲我们对政治的规范性思考,使我们容易犯某些规范性后果错误:既错误地从某些国家或社会不公正的主张中推论出正义对我们的要求;又错误地从正义不要求国家或社会做某些事情的主张中推论出哪些国家或社会是公正的或会是公正的。更多地关注这两种不同要求之间的区别以及它们的不同方式,不仅有助于避免这些歪曲和错误,而且有助于解决或至少澄清其他一些臭名昭著的元规范性争论,尤其是政治哲学中关于现实主义和理想主义的各种重要争论。
{"title":"Two kinds of requirements of justice","authors":"N. Southwood, Robert E. Goodin","doi":"10.1017/apa.2023.31","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.31","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Claims about what justice “requires” and the “requirements” of justice are pervasive in political philosophy. However, there is a highly significant ambiguity in such claims that appears to have gone unnoticed. Such claims may pick out either one of two categorically distinct and noncoextensive kinds of requirement that we call 1) requirements-as-necessary-conditions for justice and 2) requirements-as-demands of justice. This is an especially compelling instance of an ambiguity that John Broome has famously observed in the context of claims about other requirements (notably the requirements of rationality and morality). But it appears to have been overlooked by political philosophers in the case of claims about the requirements of justice. The ambiguity is highly significant inasmuch as failing to notice it is liable to distort our normative thinking about politics and make us vulnerable to certain kinds of normatively consequential errors: both mistakenly drawing inferences about what justice demands of us from claims that certain states or societies are not just; and mistakenly drawing inferences about what states or societies are or would be just from claims that justice does not demand of states or societies that they do certain things. Paying greater attention to the distinction between these two different kinds of requirements and the ways in which they come apart is helpful, not merely in avoiding these distortions and errors, but also in resolving, or at least clarifying, a number of other notoriously murky meta-normative debates, especially various important debates about realism and idealism in political philosophy.","PeriodicalId":44879,"journal":{"name":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-02-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139859622","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of the American Philosophical Association
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1