首页 > 最新文献

Northwestern University Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
A Jurisprudence of Dangerousness 危险的法理学
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-11-17 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.305459
C. Slobogin
This article addresses the state's police power authority to deprive people of liberty based on predictions of antisocial behavior. Most conspicuously exercised against so-called "sexual predators," this authority purportedly justifies a wide array of other state interventions as well, ranging from police stops to executions. Yet there still is no general theory of preventive detention. This article is a preliminary effort in that regard. The article first surveys the various objections to preventive detention: the unreliability objection; the punishment-in-disguise objection; the legality objection; and the dehumanization objection. None of these objections justifies a complete prohibition on the state's power to detain people based on dangerousness. But they do suggest significant limitations on that power regarding acceptable methods of prediction, the nature and duration of preventive detention, the threshold conduct that can trigger such detention, and the extent to which it can replace punishment as the official response to antisocial behavior. On the latter issue, the central conclusion is that preventive detention which functions as a substitute for punishment, as in the case of sexual predator statutes, is only permissible if certain psychological and predictive criteria are met. The rest of the paper develops these criteria. It argues that the psychological criterion should be undeterrability, defined as the characteristic ignorance that one's criminal activity is criminal or a characteristic willingness to commit crime despite certain and significant punishment, a definition that differs from both the usual academic stance and the Supreme Court's inability-to-control formulation. The paper next argues that selection of a prediction criterion should be informed by two principles, the proportionality principle (which varies the legally requisite level of dangerousness with the nature and duration of the state's intervention) and the consistency principle (which takes as a reference point the implicit dangerousness assessments in the law of crimes). Finally, the paper explores some of the implications of the latter principle for the criminal law, including the possibility that some crimes - in particular various possession offenses, reckless endangerment and vagrancy - violate the fundamental norms of the police power authority.
本文论述了国家警察基于对反社会行为的预测而剥夺人们自由的权力。最明显的是针对所谓的“性侵犯者”,据称这种权力也为其他一系列国家干预提供了理由,从警察拦截到处决。然而,目前仍没有关于预防性拘留的一般理论。本文是这方面的初步努力。文章首先概述了对预防性拘留的各种异议:不可靠性异议;变相惩罚的反对;合法性异议;以及非人化的反对。所有这些反对意见都不能证明完全禁止国家以危险为由拘留人的权力是正当的。但它们确实表明,这种权力在可接受的预测方法、预防性拘留的性质和持续时间、可能引发这种拘留的阈值行为以及它可以在多大程度上取代惩罚作为对反社会行为的官方反应等方面存在重大限制。关于后一个问题,中心结论是,预防性拘留的作用是代替惩罚,例如关于性掠夺者的法规,只有在满足某些心理和预测标准的情况下才允许。本文的其余部分将进一步阐述这些标准。它认为,心理标准应该是不可震慑性,定义为对犯罪活动是犯罪行为的特征无知,或者尽管受到一定的和重大的惩罚,仍有犯罪的特征意愿,这一定义既不同于通常的学术立场,也不同于最高法院无法控制的表述。接下来,本文认为,预测标准的选择应遵循两个原则,即相称性原则(根据国家干预的性质和持续时间改变法律要求的危险程度)和一致性原则(以犯罪法中的隐性危险评估为参考点)。最后,本文探讨了后一原则对刑法的一些启示,包括某些犯罪——特别是各种占有罪、鲁莽危害罪和流浪罪——违反警察权力权威基本规范的可能性。
{"title":"A Jurisprudence of Dangerousness","authors":"C. Slobogin","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.305459","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.305459","url":null,"abstract":"This article addresses the state's police power authority to deprive people of liberty based on predictions of antisocial behavior. Most conspicuously exercised against so-called \"sexual predators,\" this authority purportedly justifies a wide array of other state interventions as well, ranging from police stops to executions. Yet there still is no general theory of preventive detention. This article is a preliminary effort in that regard. The article first surveys the various objections to preventive detention: the unreliability objection; the punishment-in-disguise objection; the legality objection; and the dehumanization objection. None of these objections justifies a complete prohibition on the state's power to detain people based on dangerousness. But they do suggest significant limitations on that power regarding acceptable methods of prediction, the nature and duration of preventive detention, the threshold conduct that can trigger such detention, and the extent to which it can replace punishment as the official response to antisocial behavior. On the latter issue, the central conclusion is that preventive detention which functions as a substitute for punishment, as in the case of sexual predator statutes, is only permissible if certain psychological and predictive criteria are met. The rest of the paper develops these criteria. It argues that the psychological criterion should be undeterrability, defined as the characteristic ignorance that one's criminal activity is criminal or a characteristic willingness to commit crime despite certain and significant punishment, a definition that differs from both the usual academic stance and the Supreme Court's inability-to-control formulation. The paper next argues that selection of a prediction criterion should be informed by two principles, the proportionality principle (which varies the legally requisite level of dangerousness with the nature and duration of the state's intervention) and the consistency principle (which takes as a reference point the implicit dangerousness assessments in the law of crimes). Finally, the paper explores some of the implications of the latter principle for the criminal law, including the possibility that some crimes - in particular various possession offenses, reckless endangerment and vagrancy - violate the fundamental norms of the police power authority.","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2003-11-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68518932","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 29
Making Sense of the Eleventh Amendment: International Law and State Sovereignty 解读第十一次修正案:国际法与国家主权
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-08-26 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.434380
Thomas H. Lee
The Judicial Power of the United States shall not be construed to extend to any suit in law or equity, commenced or prosecuted against one of the United States by Citizens of another State, or by Citizens or Subjects of any Foreign State. - Eleventh Amendment to the Constitution of the United States of America The thesis of this article is that the Eleventh Amendment, ratified in 1798, represented the incorporation into the American domestic constitutional law of federalism (specifically, the doctrine of state sovereign immunity) the late eighteenth-century international law rule that only states have rights against other states on the interstate plane.
合众国的司法权不得被解释为适用于由另一州的公民或任何外国公民或臣民对合众国一方提起或起诉的任何法律或衡平法诉讼。-美利坚合众国宪法第十一修正案本文的论点是,1798年批准的第十一修正案代表了18世纪晚期的国际法规则,即只有国家在州际层面上对其他国家拥有权利,并将联邦制(特别是国家主权豁免学说)纳入美国国内宪法。
{"title":"Making Sense of the Eleventh Amendment: International Law and State Sovereignty","authors":"Thomas H. Lee","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.434380","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.434380","url":null,"abstract":"The Judicial Power of the United States shall not be construed to extend to any suit in law or equity, commenced or prosecuted against one of the United States by Citizens of another State, or by Citizens or Subjects of any Foreign State. - Eleventh Amendment to the Constitution of the United States of America The thesis of this article is that the Eleventh Amendment, ratified in 1798, represented the incorporation into the American domestic constitutional law of federalism (specifically, the doctrine of state sovereign immunity) the late eighteenth-century international law rule that only states have rights against other states on the interstate plane.","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2003-08-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68778088","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The Utility of Desert 沙漠的效用
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-05-23 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.10195
P. Robinson, J. Darley
The article takes up the debate between utility and desert as distributive principles for criminal liability and punishment and concludes that a utilitarian analysis that takes account of all costs and benefits will support the distribution of liability and punishment according to desert, or at least according to the principles of desert as perceived by the community. It reaches this conclusion after an examination of a variety of recent social science data. On the one hand, it finds the traditional utilitarian theories of deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation to have little effect in many instances. It finds instead that the real power to gain compliance with society's rules of prescribed conduct lies not in the threat or reality of official criminal sanction, but in the power of the intertwined forces of social and individual moral control. The networks of interpersonal relationships in which people find themselves, the social norms and prohibitions shared among those relationships and transmitted through those social networks, and the internalized representations of those norms and moral precepts are what cause people to obey the law. The law is not irrelevant to these social and personal forces. Criminal law, in particular, plays a central role in creating and maintaining the social consensus necessary for sustaining moral norms. In fact, in a society as diverse as ours, the criminal law may be the only society-wide mechanism that transcends cultural and ethnic differences. Thus, the criminal law's most important real world effect may be its ability to assist in the building, shaping, and maintaining of these norms and moral principles. It can contribute to and harness the compliance-producing power of interpersonal relationships and personal morality. The criminal law can have a second effect in gaining compliance with its commands. If it earns a reputation as a reliable statement of what the community, given sufficient information and time to reflect, would perceive as condemnable, people are more likely to defer to its commands as morally authoritative and as appropriate to follow in those borderline cases where the propriety of certain conduct is unsettled or ambiguous in the mind of the actor. The extent of the criminal law's effectiveness in both these respects - in facilitating and communicating societal consensus on what is and is not condemnable, and in gaining compliance in borderline cases through deference to its moral authority - is to a great extent dependent on the degree of moral credibility that the criminal law has achieved in the minds of the citizens governed by it. Thus, the criminal law's moral credibility is essential to effective crime control, and is enhanced if the distribution of criminal liability is perceived as doing justice, that is, if it assigns liability and punishment in ways that the community perceives as consistent with the community's principles of appropriate liability and punishment. Conversel
这篇文章讨论了效用和沙漠作为刑事责任和惩罚的分配原则之间的争论,并得出结论认为,考虑到所有成本和收益的功利主义分析将支持根据沙漠分配责任和惩罚,或者至少根据社会所认为的沙漠原则。在对最近的各种社会科学数据进行研究后,它得出了这一结论。一方面,它发现传统的威慑、丧失行为能力和康复的功利主义理论在许多情况下收效甚微。相反,它发现,使人们遵守社会规定的行为规则的真正力量不在于官方刑事制裁的威胁或现实,而在于社会和个人道德控制相互交织的力量的力量。人们在其中找到自我的人际关系网络,在这些关系中共享并通过这些社会网络传播的社会规范和禁忌,以及这些规范和道德戒律的内化表征是导致人们遵守法律的原因。法律并非与这些社会和个人力量无关。特别是刑法在创造和维持维持道德规范所必需的社会共识方面发挥着核心作用。事实上,在我们这样一个多元化的社会中,刑法可能是唯一超越文化和种族差异的全社会机制。因此,刑法对现实世界最重要的影响可能是它帮助建立、塑造和维护这些规范和道德原则的能力。它可以促进和利用人际关系和个人道德的顺从生产能力。刑法在使人们服从它的命令方面还有另一种作用。如果它作为一个可靠的声明赢得了声誉,在有足够的信息和时间来反思的情况下,社会会认为它是应受谴责的,人们更有可能服从它的命令,认为它是道德权威的,在那些行为者心中不确定或模糊的边缘情况下,人们更有可能遵循它的命令。刑法在这两个方面的有效性程度——促进和沟通社会就什么是可谴责的和什么不是可谴责的达成共识,以及通过尊重其道德权威在边缘案件中获得遵守——在很大程度上取决于刑法在受其管辖的公民心目中所取得的道德信誉程度。因此,刑法的道德信誉对于有效控制犯罪至关重要,如果刑事责任的分配被认为是公正的,也就是说,如果它以符合社区适当责任和惩罚原则的方式分配责任和惩罚,那么刑法的道德信誉就会得到增强。相反,该体系的道德信誉,以及因此而产生的犯罪控制效果,由于责任分配偏离了社会对正义应得的看法而受到损害。
{"title":"The Utility of Desert","authors":"P. Robinson, J. Darley","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.10195","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.10195","url":null,"abstract":"The article takes up the debate between utility and desert as distributive principles for criminal liability and punishment and concludes that a utilitarian analysis that takes account of all costs and benefits will support the distribution of liability and punishment according to desert, or at least according to the principles of desert as perceived by the community. It reaches this conclusion after an examination of a variety of recent social science data. On the one hand, it finds the traditional utilitarian theories of deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation to have little effect in many instances. It finds instead that the real power to gain compliance with society's rules of prescribed conduct lies not in the threat or reality of official criminal sanction, but in the power of the intertwined forces of social and individual moral control. The networks of interpersonal relationships in which people find themselves, the social norms and prohibitions shared among those relationships and transmitted through those social networks, and the internalized representations of those norms and moral precepts are what cause people to obey the law. The law is not irrelevant to these social and personal forces. Criminal law, in particular, plays a central role in creating and maintaining the social consensus necessary for sustaining moral norms. In fact, in a society as diverse as ours, the criminal law may be the only society-wide mechanism that transcends cultural and ethnic differences. Thus, the criminal law's most important real world effect may be its ability to assist in the building, shaping, and maintaining of these norms and moral principles. It can contribute to and harness the compliance-producing power of interpersonal relationships and personal morality. The criminal law can have a second effect in gaining compliance with its commands. If it earns a reputation as a reliable statement of what the community, given sufficient information and time to reflect, would perceive as condemnable, people are more likely to defer to its commands as morally authoritative and as appropriate to follow in those borderline cases where the propriety of certain conduct is unsettled or ambiguous in the mind of the actor. The extent of the criminal law's effectiveness in both these respects - in facilitating and communicating societal consensus on what is and is not condemnable, and in gaining compliance in borderline cases through deference to its moral authority - is to a great extent dependent on the degree of moral credibility that the criminal law has achieved in the minds of the citizens governed by it. Thus, the criminal law's moral credibility is essential to effective crime control, and is enhanced if the distribution of criminal liability is perceived as doing justice, that is, if it assigns liability and punishment in ways that the community perceives as consistent with the community's principles of appropriate liability and punishment. Conversel","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2003-05-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68127971","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 155
One for You and One for Me: Is Title IX's Sex-Based Proportionality Requirement for College Varsity Athletic Positions Defensible? 一个给你,一个给我:教育法第九条对大学体育职位的性别比例要求是否站得住脚?
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-03-05 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.384960
K. Yuracko
This paper explores whether Title IX's proportionality requirement can be justified under any of three standard civil rights frameworks. The proportionality requirement has been widely criticized for failing to follow the "careers open to talents" model enforced by Title VII. The paper argues that the critics are correct that the proportionality requirement is inconsistent with the careers open to talents model but contends that the critics' own distribution proposals are also inconsistent with this model. The paper next considers whether the proportionality requirement can be justified by either of two other civil rights models: a utilitarian model (of the sort that underlies the Individuals with Disabilities Education Act) and what is referred to in the text as a tool-giving model (of the sort that underlies the school financing cases). Neither model provides an adequate justification for the proportionality requirement, however. Finally, the paper examines whether the proportionality requirement might best and most honestly be justified on the grounds that it encourages girls to participate in activities and develop traits and attributes that are widely socially valued. The paper concludes that the proportionality requirement is indeed best understood and justified as an openly "perfectionist" resocialization measure.
本文探讨了在三个标准的民权框架下,第九条的比例性要求是否合理。比例要求因未能遵循第七章所规定的“向人才开放的职业”模式而受到广泛批评。本文认为,批评者认为比例要求与人才职业开放模式不一致是正确的,但批评者自己的分配建议也与人才职业开放模式不一致。接下来,本文将考虑比例性要求是否可以通过另外两种民权模式中的任何一种来证明:一种是功利主义模式(即《残疾人教育法》的基础),另一种是文本中提到的工具提供模式(即学校融资案例的基础)。然而,这两种模式都没有为相称性要求提供充分的理由。最后,本文考察了比例要求是否可以最好和最诚实地证明是合理的,因为它鼓励女孩参加活动并发展被广泛社会重视的特征和属性。本文的结论是,比例要求作为一种公开的“完美主义”再社会化措施确实是最好的理解和合理的。
{"title":"One for You and One for Me: Is Title IX's Sex-Based Proportionality Requirement for College Varsity Athletic Positions Defensible?","authors":"K. Yuracko","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.384960","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.384960","url":null,"abstract":"This paper explores whether Title IX's proportionality requirement can be justified under any of three standard civil rights frameworks. The proportionality requirement has been widely criticized for failing to follow the \"careers open to talents\" model enforced by Title VII. The paper argues that the critics are correct that the proportionality requirement is inconsistent with the careers open to talents model but contends that the critics' own distribution proposals are also inconsistent with this model. The paper next considers whether the proportionality requirement can be justified by either of two other civil rights models: a utilitarian model (of the sort that underlies the Individuals with Disabilities Education Act) and what is referred to in the text as a tool-giving model (of the sort that underlies the school financing cases). Neither model provides an adequate justification for the proportionality requirement, however. Finally, the paper examines whether the proportionality requirement might best and most honestly be justified on the grounds that it encourages girls to participate in activities and develop traits and attributes that are widely socially valued. The paper concludes that the proportionality requirement is indeed best understood and justified as an openly \"perfectionist\" resocialization measure.","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2003-03-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68659593","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
The Five Worst (and Five Best) American Criminal Codes 美国五条最坏(和五条最好)的刑法
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-02-06 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.183290
P. Robinson, Michael T. Cahill, Usman Mohammad
This paper develops and attempts to justify criteria for judging the quality of a criminal code in performing its functions. It translates the abstract criteria into a workable code evaluation scheme, then applies the scheme to the fifty-two American criminal codes, ending with a ranking of those codes. Examples of good and bad code provisions are used in the discussion to illustrate the evaluation criteria.
本文发展并试图证明判断刑法在履行其职能时质量的标准。它将抽象的标准转化为一个可行的法典评估方案,然后将该方案应用于美国52部刑法,最后对这些法典进行排名。在讨论中使用了好的和坏的代码条款的例子来说明评估标准。
{"title":"The Five Worst (and Five Best) American Criminal Codes","authors":"P. Robinson, Michael T. Cahill, Usman Mohammad","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.183290","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.183290","url":null,"abstract":"This paper develops and attempts to justify criteria for judging the quality of a criminal code in performing its functions. It translates the abstract criteria into a workable code evaluation scheme, then applies the scheme to the fifty-two American criminal codes, ending with a ranking of those codes. Examples of good and bad code provisions are used in the discussion to illustrate the evaluation criteria.","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2003-02-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.183290","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67756602","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 15
Squandering the gain: gainsharing and the continuing dilemma of physician financial incentives. 浪费收益:收益分享和医生财务激励的持续困境。
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-01-01
Richard S Saver
{"title":"Squandering the gain: gainsharing and the continuing dilemma of physician financial incentives.","authors":"Richard S Saver","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2003-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"25645810","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Prospect Theory, Risk Preference, and the Law 前景理论、风险偏好与法律
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2002-10-31 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.344600
C. Guthrie
To understand how people behave in an uncertain world - and to make viable recommendations about how the law should try to shape that behavior - legal scholars must employ a model or theory of decision making. Only with an understanding of how people are likely to respond to legal rules can legal scholars, judges, legislators, and regulators craft rules that are likely to encourage desirable behavior and discourage undesirable behavior. Rather than rely on rational choice theory, behavioral law and economics scholars (or legal decision theorists) have turned to Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky's "prospect theory" to inform their analyses of law and legal behavior. Prospect theory contains several empirical propositions relevant to legal analysis, but this paper focuses primarily on prospect theory's insight that people often make risk-averse choices when selecting between "gains" and risk-seeking choices when selecting between "losses." The paper surveys efforts in the legal literature to use this insight to inform the way legal scholars think about law and behavior in several doctrinal areas. The paper acknowledges some limitations associated with this work (e.g., external validity, differences in individual decision making, differences in group vs. individual decision making), but it concludes that prospect theory is nonetheless a valuable tool for legal scholars and policy makers.
为了理解人们在一个不确定的世界中的行为,并就法律应该如何塑造这种行为提出可行的建议,法律学者必须采用一种决策模型或理论。只有了解了人们对法律规则的反应,法律学者、法官、立法者和监管者才能制定出可能鼓励可取行为和阻止不可取行为的规则。行为法和经济学学者(或法律决策理论家)不再依赖理性选择理论,而是转向丹尼尔·卡尼曼和阿莫斯·特沃斯基的“前景理论”,以指导他们对法律和法律行为的分析。前景理论包含了几个与法律分析相关的经验命题,但本文主要关注的是前景理论的洞见,即人们在选择“收益”时往往会做出风险厌恶的选择,在选择“损失”时往往会做出风险寻求的选择。本文调查了法律文献中使用这种见解来告知法律学者在几个理论领域思考法律和行为的方式的努力。本文承认与这项工作相关的一些局限性(例如,外部有效性,个人决策的差异,群体与个人决策的差异),但它得出的结论是,前景理论仍然是法律学者和政策制定者的宝贵工具。
{"title":"Prospect Theory, Risk Preference, and the Law","authors":"C. Guthrie","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.344600","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.344600","url":null,"abstract":"To understand how people behave in an uncertain world - and to make viable recommendations about how the law should try to shape that behavior - legal scholars must employ a model or theory of decision making. Only with an understanding of how people are likely to respond to legal rules can legal scholars, judges, legislators, and regulators craft rules that are likely to encourage desirable behavior and discourage undesirable behavior. Rather than rely on rational choice theory, behavioral law and economics scholars (or legal decision theorists) have turned to Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky's \"prospect theory\" to inform their analyses of law and legal behavior. Prospect theory contains several empirical propositions relevant to legal analysis, but this paper focuses primarily on prospect theory's insight that people often make risk-averse choices when selecting between \"gains\" and risk-seeking choices when selecting between \"losses.\" The paper surveys efforts in the legal literature to use this insight to inform the way legal scholars think about law and behavior in several doctrinal areas. The paper acknowledges some limitations associated with this work (e.g., external validity, differences in individual decision making, differences in group vs. individual decision making), but it concludes that prospect theory is nonetheless a valuable tool for legal scholars and policy makers.","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2002-10-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.344600","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68594124","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 65
The Endowment Effect and Legal Analysis 禀赋效应及其法律分析
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2002-09-29 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.326360
R. Korobkin
Most legal scholarship implicitly adopts the assumption of the Coase Theorem that the value an individual places on a legal entitlement is independent of whether or not the individual has physical possession of or a legal right to that entitlement. This is true of both traditional law and economics analysis concerned with the efficient allocation of resources and scholarship that is not self-consciously in the law and economics tradition but is concerned with law's effects on incentives. A robust body of social science scholarship, however, demonstrates that the assumption is incorrect, at least in many circumstances. The much studied "endowment effect" is that people tend to value goods more when they own them than when they do not. A consequence of the endowment effect is the "offer-asking gap", which is the empirically observed phenomenon that people will often demand a higher price to sell a good that they possess than they would pay for the same entitlement if they did not possess it at present. A third term - the "status quo bias" - is often used interchangeably with the other two, but actually has a slightly broader connotation: individuals tend to prefer the present state of the world to alternative states, all other things being equal. Whatever the label, this insight is the most significant finding from behavioral economics for legal analysis to date. This article reviews the empirical evidence of the endowment effect and considers a variety of possible causes of the effect. It then explores how the endowment effect can affect the positive and normative analysis of legal rules that (1) assign or transfer legal entitlements, (2) facilitate the private exchange of legal entitlements, and (3) enforce the rules of property and contract. The discussion demonstrates that the endowment effect is relevant to the analysis of virtually every field of law. It also shows that careful normative legal analysis based on the endowment effect must take into account the context-dependent nature of the effect and the causes of the effect, neither of which are fully understood. Thus, when the endowment effect is used as a basis for normative claims, these claims must often be qualified and contingent.
大多数法律学术隐含地采用科斯定理的假设,即个人对合法权利的价值与个人是否拥有该权利的物质占有或合法权利无关。传统的法律和经济学分析都是如此,这些分析关注的是资源的有效分配,而学术研究在法律和经济学传统中并不自觉,而是关注法律对激励的影响。然而,大量的社会科学研究表明,至少在许多情况下,这种假设是不正确的。被广泛研究的“禀赋效应”是,当人们拥有一件商品时,他们往往比不拥有一件商品时更看重它。禀赋效应的一个后果是“供需差距”,这是一种经验观察到的现象,即人们通常会要求更高的价格来出售他们拥有的商品,而不是他们目前没有拥有的相同权利。第三个术语——“现状偏见”——经常与前两个术语交替使用,但实际上有一个更广泛的含义:在其他条件相同的情况下,个人倾向于喜欢世界的现状,而不是其他状态。无论标签是什么,这是迄今为止行为经济学对法律分析最重要的发现。本文回顾了禀赋效应的经验证据,并考虑了产生禀赋效应的各种可能原因。然后,它探讨了禀赋效应如何影响对法律规则的积极和规范分析,这些法律规则包括:(1)转让或转移法律权利,(2)促进法律权利的私人交换,以及(3)执行财产和合同规则。讨论表明,禀赋效应与几乎所有法律领域的分析都有关。它还表明,基于禀赋效应的仔细的规范性法律分析必须考虑到该效应的上下文依赖性质和产生该效应的原因,而这两者都没有得到充分的理解。因此,当禀赋效应被用作规范性要求的基础时,这些要求往往必须是限定的和偶然的。
{"title":"The Endowment Effect and Legal Analysis","authors":"R. Korobkin","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.326360","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.326360","url":null,"abstract":"Most legal scholarship implicitly adopts the assumption of the Coase Theorem that the value an individual places on a legal entitlement is independent of whether or not the individual has physical possession of or a legal right to that entitlement. This is true of both traditional law and economics analysis concerned with the efficient allocation of resources and scholarship that is not self-consciously in the law and economics tradition but is concerned with law's effects on incentives. A robust body of social science scholarship, however, demonstrates that the assumption is incorrect, at least in many circumstances. The much studied \"endowment effect\" is that people tend to value goods more when they own them than when they do not. A consequence of the endowment effect is the \"offer-asking gap\", which is the empirically observed phenomenon that people will often demand a higher price to sell a good that they possess than they would pay for the same entitlement if they did not possess it at present. A third term - the \"status quo bias\" - is often used interchangeably with the other two, but actually has a slightly broader connotation: individuals tend to prefer the present state of the world to alternative states, all other things being equal. Whatever the label, this insight is the most significant finding from behavioral economics for legal analysis to date. This article reviews the empirical evidence of the endowment effect and considers a variety of possible causes of the effect. It then explores how the endowment effect can affect the positive and normative analysis of legal rules that (1) assign or transfer legal entitlements, (2) facilitate the private exchange of legal entitlements, and (3) enforce the rules of property and contract. The discussion demonstrates that the endowment effect is relevant to the analysis of virtually every field of law. It also shows that careful normative legal analysis based on the endowment effect must take into account the context-dependent nature of the effect and the causes of the effect, neither of which are fully understood. Thus, when the endowment effect is used as a basis for normative claims, these claims must often be qualified and contingent.","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2002-09-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.326360","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68579812","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 101
Is Corporate Law Trivial?: A Political and Economic Analysis 公司法无足轻重吗?政治与经济分析
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2002-09-11 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.329240
Bernard Black
On its face, state corporate law contains a mix of mandatory and default rules. I develop the "triviality hypothesis" that the appearance of a mandatory core to state corporate law is a mirage, and that state corporate law is trivial, in the sense that it lets companies -- managers and investors together -- establish any set of governance rules they would reasonably want. Rules that appear mandatory may be trivial for four reasons. First, some mandatory rules would be universally adopted if people thought about them ("market mimicking" rules). Second, some rules can be avoided by advance planning, including choice of capital structure and state of incorporation. Third, some mandatory rules are unimportant -- they cover situations that occur rarely or matter little. Finally, as circumstances change, some rules that used to be market mimicking, avoidable, or unimportant may matter, but precisely because these rules matter, they will soon be changed. The political forces that led to the trivialization of corporate law will see to that. Many apparently mandatory corporate law rules are trivial in one of these senses. Moreover, proving that nontrivial rules exist is hard. It is not trivial to disprove the extreme null hypothesis that all of state corporate law is trivial.
从表面上看,州公司法包含强制性和默认规则的混合。我提出了“琐碎性假设”(triviality hypothesis),认为州公司法强制性核心的表象是海市蜃楼,州公司法是琐碎的,因为它允许公司——管理者和投资者一起——建立他们合理想要的任何一套治理规则。看似强制性的规则可能微不足道,原因有四。首先,如果人们考虑到一些强制性规则(“市场模仿”规则),它们将被普遍采用。其次,一些规则可以通过提前规划来避免,包括资本结构的选择和公司注册状态。第三,一些强制性规则并不重要——它们涵盖了很少发生或无关紧要的情况。最后,随着环境的变化,一些曾经模仿市场、可以避免或不重要的规则可能会变得重要,但正是因为这些规则很重要,它们很快就会被改变。导致公司法庸俗化的政治力量将会看到这一点。从这些意义上讲,许多看似强制性的公司法规则都是微不足道的。此外,证明非平凡规则的存在是困难的。要证明极端的零假设,即所有州的公司法都是微不足道的,这不是微不足道的。
{"title":"Is Corporate Law Trivial?: A Political and Economic Analysis","authors":"Bernard Black","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.329240","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.329240","url":null,"abstract":"On its face, state corporate law contains a mix of mandatory and default rules. I develop the \"triviality hypothesis\" that the appearance of a mandatory core to state corporate law is a mirage, and that state corporate law is trivial, in the sense that it lets companies -- managers and investors together -- establish any set of governance rules they would reasonably want. Rules that appear mandatory may be trivial for four reasons. First, some mandatory rules would be universally adopted if people thought about them (\"market mimicking\" rules). Second, some rules can be avoided by advance planning, including choice of capital structure and state of incorporation. Third, some mandatory rules are unimportant -- they cover situations that occur rarely or matter little. Finally, as circumstances change, some rules that used to be market mimicking, avoidable, or unimportant may matter, but precisely because these rules matter, they will soon be changed. The political forces that led to the trivialization of corporate law will see to that. Many apparently mandatory corporate law rules are trivial in one of these senses. Moreover, proving that nontrivial rules exist is hard. It is not trivial to disprove the extreme null hypothesis that all of state corporate law is trivial.","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2002-09-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68582605","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 121
Internet Surveillance Law after the USA Patriot Act: The Big Brother that Isn't 《美国爱国者法案》之后的互联网监控法案:并非老大哥的法律
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2002-07-19 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.317501
Orin S. Kerr
This article argues that the common wisdom on the USA Patriot Act is wrong. Far from being a significant expansion of law enforcement powers online, the Patriot Act actually changed Internet surveillance law in only minor ways and added several key privacy protections. The article focuses on three specific provisions of the Patriot Act: the provision applying the pen register law to the Internet, the provisions relating to Carnivore, and the new computer trespasser exception to the Wiretap Act. By explaining the basic framework of surveillance law and applying it to the Patriot Act, the author shows how the Internet surveillance provisions of the Patriot Act updated the law in ways that both law enforcement and civil libertarians should appreciate.
本文认为,对《美国爱国者法案》的普遍认识是错误的。《爱国者法案》远不是对网络执法权力的重大扩张,它实际上只是在很小的方面改变了互联网监督法,并增加了几项关键的隐私保护。本文重点分析了爱国者法案的三个具体条款:将笔录法适用于互联网的条款、有关食肉动物的条款以及《窃听法》中新的计算机侵入者例外条款。通过解释监视法律的基本框架并将其应用于《爱国者法案》,作者展示了《爱国者法案》中的互联网监视条款如何以执法和公民自由主义者都应该欣赏的方式更新了法律。
{"title":"Internet Surveillance Law after the USA Patriot Act: The Big Brother that Isn't","authors":"Orin S. Kerr","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.317501","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.317501","url":null,"abstract":"This article argues that the common wisdom on the USA Patriot Act is wrong. Far from being a significant expansion of law enforcement powers online, the Patriot Act actually changed Internet surveillance law in only minor ways and added several key privacy protections. The article focuses on three specific provisions of the Patriot Act: the provision applying the pen register law to the Internet, the provisions relating to Carnivore, and the new computer trespasser exception to the Wiretap Act. By explaining the basic framework of surveillance law and applying it to the Patriot Act, the author shows how the Internet surveillance provisions of the Patriot Act updated the law in ways that both law enforcement and civil libertarians should appreciate.","PeriodicalId":47587,"journal":{"name":"Northwestern University Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2002-07-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.317501","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68569252","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 65
期刊
Northwestern University Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1