Pub Date : 2024-08-30DOI: 10.1007/s10988-023-09404-2
Osamu Sawada
This study investigates the meanings of the Japanese low-degree modifiers kasukani ‘faintly’ and honokani ‘approx. faintly’ and the English low-degree modifier faintly. I argue that, unlike typical low-degree modifiers such as sukoshi ‘a bit’ in Japanese and a bit in English, they are sense-based in that they not only semantically denote a small degree but also convey that the judge (typically the speaker) measures the degree of predicates based on their own sense (the senses of sight, smell, taste, etc.) at the level of conventional implicature (CI) (e.g., Grice (in: Cole, Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics iii: speech acts, Academic Press, New York, 1975), Potts (The logic of conventional implicatures, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2005), McCready (Semant Pragmat 3:1–57, 2010. https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.3.8, Sawada (Pragmatic aspects of scalar modifiers. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Chicago, 2010), Gutzmann (Empir Issues Syntax Semant 8:123–141, 2011)). I will also show that there are variations among the sense-based low-degree modifiers with regard to (i) the kind of sense, (ii) the presence/absence of positive evaluativity, and (iii) the possibility of direct measurement of emotion and will explain the variations in relation to the CI component. A unique feature of sense-based low-degree modifiers is that they can indirectly measure the degree of non-sense-based predicates (e.g., emotion) through sense (e.g., perception). I show that the proposed analysis can also explain the indirect measurement in a unified way. This paper shows that like predicates of personal taste such as tasty (e.g., Pearson (J Semant 30(1):103–154, 2013. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffs001), Ninan (Proc Semant Linguist Theory, 24:290–304, 2014. https://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v24i0.2413), Willer & Kennedy (Inquiry, 1–37, 2020. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2020.1850338)), sense-based low-degree modifiers trigger acquaintance inference. The difference between them is that, unlike predicates of personal taste, sense-based low-degree modifiers co-occur with gradable predicates and their experiential components signal the manner/way in which the degree of the predicate in question is measured.
本研究调查了日语低度修饰语 kasukani "微弱地 "和 honokani "大约微弱地 "以及英语低度修饰语 faintly 的含义。我认为,与典型的低度修饰词(如日语中的 sukoshi "一点 "和英语中的 a bit "有点")不同,它们是基于感觉的,因为它们不仅在语义上表示很小的程度,而且还传达出判断者(通常是说话者)根据自己的感觉(视觉、嗅觉、味觉等)在常规蕴涵(CI)的层面上衡量谓词的程度(例如,Grice (in., Cole, Morgan (Eds.):科尔、摩根(编),《语法和语义学 iii:言语行为》,学术出版社,纽约,1975 年),波茨(《常规蕴涵的逻辑》,牛津大学出版社,牛津,2005 年),麦克雷迪(《语义学语用》3:1-57,2010 年。https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.3.8,泽田(《标量修饰语的语用方面》。Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Chicago, 2010),Gutzmann(Empir Issues Syntax Semant 8:123-141, 2011)。我还将说明,基于感觉的低度修饰语在以下方面存在差异:(i) 感觉的种类,(ii) 有/无积极评价性,以及 (iii) 能否直接测量情感,并将结合 CI 成分解释这些差异。基于感性的低度修饰词的一个独特之处在于,它们可以通过感性(如知觉)间接测量非基于感性的谓词(如情感)的程度。我的研究表明,所提出的分析方法也能以统一的方式解释间接测量。本文表明,与tasty等个人品味谓词(如Pearson (J Semant 30(1):103-154, 2013. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffs001), Ninan (Proc Semant Linguist Theory, 24:290-304, 2014. https://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v24i0.2413), Willer & Kennedy (Inquiry, 1-37, 2020. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2020.1850338))一样,基于感官的低度修饰词也会触发熟人推理。它们之间的区别在于,与个人品味谓词不同,基于感官的低度修饰词与可分级谓词同时出现,其经验成分是衡量相关谓词程度的方式/途径的信号。
{"title":"Sense-based low-degree modifiers in Japanese and English: their relations to experience, evaluation, and emotions","authors":"Osamu Sawada","doi":"10.1007/s10988-023-09404-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09404-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This study investigates the meanings of the Japanese low-degree modifiers <i>kasukani</i> ‘faintly’ and <i>honokani</i> ‘approx. faintly’ and the English low-degree modifier <i>faintly</i>. I argue that, unlike typical low-degree modifiers such as <i>sukoshi</i> ‘a bit’ in Japanese and <i>a bit</i> in English, they are sense-based in that they not only semantically denote a small degree but also convey that the judge (typically the speaker) measures the degree of predicates based on their own sense (the senses of sight, smell, taste, etc.) at the level of conventional implicature (CI) (e.g., Grice (in: Cole, Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics iii: speech acts, Academic Press, New York, 1975), Potts (The logic of conventional implicatures, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2005), McCready (Semant Pragmat 3:1–57, 2010. https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.3.8, Sawada (Pragmatic aspects of scalar modifiers. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Chicago, 2010), Gutzmann (Empir Issues Syntax Semant 8:123–141, 2011)). I will also show that there are variations among the sense-based low-degree modifiers with regard to (i) the kind of sense, (ii) the presence/absence of positive evaluativity, and (iii) the possibility of direct measurement of emotion and will explain the variations in relation to the CI component. A unique feature of sense-based low-degree modifiers is that they can indirectly measure the degree of non-sense-based predicates (e.g., emotion) through sense (e.g., perception). I show that the proposed analysis can also explain the indirect measurement in a unified way. This paper shows that like predicates of personal taste such as <i>tasty</i> (e.g., Pearson (J Semant 30(1):103–154, 2013. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffs001), Ninan (Proc Semant Linguist Theory, 24:290–304, 2014. https://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v24i0.2413), Willer & Kennedy (Inquiry, 1–37, 2020. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2020.1850338)), sense-based low-degree modifiers trigger acquaintance inference. The difference between them is that, unlike predicates of personal taste, sense-based low-degree modifiers co-occur with gradable predicates and their experiential components signal the manner/way in which the degree of the predicate in question is measured.</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"6 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-08-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142217438","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-08-28DOI: 10.1007/s10988-024-09413-9
Craige Roberts, Mandy Simons
In this paper we articulate a pragmatic account of the projection behavior of three classes of non-anaphoric projective contents: the pre-states of change of state (CoS) predicates, the veridical entailments of factives, and the implication of satisfaction of selectional restrictions. Given evidence that the triggers of these implications are not anaphoric, hence do not impose presuppositional constraints on their local contexts, we argue that the projection behavior of these implications cannot be explained by the standard Karttunen/Heim/van der Sandt proposals. But we recognize that parallels between the projection behavior of these implications and the projection behavior of anaphorically-triggered implications must be explained. The current account offers a unified explanation of why the predicates in question give rise to projection at all; why projection of these implications is susceptible to contextual suppression; and why projection is systematically filtered in the standard Karttunen filtering environments, despite the absence of contextual constraints. We demonstrate that our account largely makes the same predictions for filtering of anaphoric and non-anaphoric presuppositions, and briefly support the claim that in the case of disjunction, filtering in the two cases is not fully parallel, as predicted by our account. We also briefly discuss how the well-documented variability in projection across predicates in the same semantic class can be understood within our approach.
在本文中,我们对三类非隐喻投射性内容的投射行为进行了语用解释:状态变化(CoS)谓词的前状态、事实蕴涵和满足选择限制的蕴涵。鉴于有证据表明这些蕴涵的触发器不是拟喻的,因此不会对其局部语境施加预设性限制,我们认为这些蕴涵的投射行为无法用标准的 Karttunen/Heim/van der Sandt 提议来解释。但我们承认,必须解释这些蕴涵的投射行为与隐喻触发蕴涵的投射行为之间的相似之处。目前的解释提供了一个统一的解释,说明了为什么有关谓词会产生投射;为什么这些蕴涵的投射容易受到语境的抑制;以及为什么在标准的卡图宁过滤环境中,尽管没有语境限制,投射还是会被系统地过滤掉。我们证明了我们的论述在很大程度上对拟喻预设和非拟喻预设的过滤做出了相同的预测,并简要地支持了这样一种说法,即在析取的情况下,两种情况下的过滤并不完全平行,正如我们的论述所预测的那样。我们还简要讨论了如何在我们的方法中理解有据可查的同一语义类别中不同谓词之间的投射差异。
{"title":"Preconditions and projection: Explaining non-anaphoric presupposition","authors":"Craige Roberts, Mandy Simons","doi":"10.1007/s10988-024-09413-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-024-09413-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p> In this paper we articulate a pragmatic account of the projection behavior of three classes of non-anaphoric projective contents: the pre-states of change of state (CoS) predicates, the veridical entailments of factives, and the implication of satisfaction of selectional restrictions. Given evidence that the triggers of these implications are not anaphoric, hence do not impose presuppositional constraints on their local contexts, we argue that the projection behavior of these implications cannot be explained by the standard Karttunen/Heim/van der Sandt proposals. But we recognize that parallels between the projection behavior of these implications and the projection behavior of anaphorically-triggered implications must be explained. The current account offers a unified explanation of why the predicates in question give rise to projection at all; why projection of these implications is susceptible to contextual suppression; and why projection is systematically filtered in the standard Karttunen filtering environments, despite the absence of contextual constraints. We demonstrate that our account largely makes the same predictions for filtering of anaphoric and non-anaphoric presuppositions, and briefly support the claim that in the case of disjunction, filtering in the two cases is not fully parallel, as predicted by our account. We also briefly discuss how the well-documented variability in projection across predicates in the same semantic class can be understood within our approach.</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"32 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142217439","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-08-23DOI: 10.1007/s10988-024-09420-w
Luka Crnič
The positive, non-exclusive inference of only has been famously elusive with respect to its projective status and its content: in some cases the positive inference behaves like a presupposition, while in others it does not; in some cases the inference is non-modal, corresponding to the prejacent of only or an existential counterpart of it, while in others it is modalized. This behavior, we argue, surfaces the exceptive nature of only (cf. von Fintel and Iatridou in Linguist Inq 38(3):445–483, 2007). More specifically, if the import of only is distributed between a minimality and a subtraction component, as has been argued for exceptives (esp. Gajewski in Nat Lang Semant 16(1):69–110, 2008), the apparently irreconcilable properties of only can be captured.
"唯一 "的正向非排他性推理在其投射性地位和内容方面一直是著名的难以捉摸的:在某些情况下,正向推理表现得像一个预设,而在另一些情况下则不是;在某些情况下,该推理是非模态的,与 "唯一 "的前置词或其存在性对应词相对应,而在另一些情况下则是模态化的。我们认为,这种行为揭示了 only 的例外性质(参见 von Fintel 和 Iatridou 在 Linguist Inq 38(3):445-483, 2007 中的论述)。更具体地说,如果 "唯一 "的意义分布在最小性和减法成分之间,就像对例外词的论证那样(特别是 Gajewski 在 Nat Lang Semant 16(1):69-110, 2008 中的论述),那么 "唯一 "看似不可调和的特性就可以被捕捉到。
{"title":"A distributed analysis of only","authors":"Luka Crnič","doi":"10.1007/s10988-024-09420-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-024-09420-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The positive, non-exclusive inference of <i>only</i> has been famously elusive with respect to its projective status and its content: in some cases the positive inference behaves like a presupposition, while in others it does not; in some cases the inference is non-modal, corresponding to the prejacent of <i>only</i> or an existential counterpart of it, while in others it is modalized. This behavior, we argue, surfaces the exceptive nature of <i>only</i> (cf. von Fintel and Iatridou in Linguist Inq 38(3):445–483, 2007). More specifically, if the import of <i>only</i> is distributed between a minimality and a subtraction component, as has been argued for exceptives (esp. Gajewski in Nat Lang Semant 16(1):69–110, 2008), the apparently irreconcilable properties of <i>only</i> can be captured.</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"20 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-08-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142217441","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-08-02DOI: 10.1007/s10988-023-09407-z
Lucas Champollion, Timothée Bernard
Fine (J Philos Logic 46(6):625–674, 2017) develops a unilateral and a bilateral truthmaker semantics for propositional logic. The unilateral approach trades off the primitive exact falsification relation of the bilateral approach for a primitive exclusion relation between states, thereby raising the question if exclusion serves any purpose other than to avoid exact falsification. We argue that exclusion is motivated independently of its use in avoiding exact falsification, namely as a foundation for the reconstruction of modal notions such as possibility and necessity. This reconstruction in turn motivates what we call emergent exclusion: an atomic state can exclude a sum of atomic states collectively without excluding any of these atomic states individually. Emergent exclusion is banned in Fine (2017a) in order to maintain exact equivalence in de Morgan’s law (lnot (P wedge Q) Leftrightarrow lnot P vee lnot Q); we argue that the two sides of this law are not exactly equivalent and discuss a variety of state spaces that feature emergent exclusion. This paper aims to be accessible to linguists without prior exposure to truthmaker semantics. We highlight points of contact with natural language semantics, such as event semantics and algebraic semantics of plurals and conjunction.
Fine (J Philos Logic 46(6):625-674, 2017)为命题逻辑建立了单边和双边的真值制造者语义学。单边方法将双边方法中的原始精确证伪关系换成了状态之间的原始排除关系,从而提出了排除除了避免精确证伪之外是否还有其他作用的问题。我们认为,排除的动机是独立于其避免精确证伪的用途之外的,即作为重构可能性和必然性等模态概念的基础。这种重构反过来又激发了我们所说的新兴排除:一个原子态可以集体地排除原子态的总和,而不单独排除这些原子态中的任何一个。Fine(2017a)禁止新兴排除,以保持德-摩根定律((lnot (P wedge Q) Leftrightarrow lnot P vee lnot Q)中的精确等价性;我们认为该定律的两边并不完全等价,并讨论了各种具有新兴排除特征的状态空间。本文的目标是让没有接触过造真语义学的语言学家也能理解。我们强调了与自然语言语义学的联系点,如事件语义学以及复数和连词的代数语义学。
{"title":"Negation and modality in unilateral truthmaker semantics","authors":"Lucas Champollion, Timothée Bernard","doi":"10.1007/s10988-023-09407-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09407-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Fine (J Philos Logic 46(6):625–674, 2017) develops a unilateral and a bilateral truthmaker semantics for propositional logic. The unilateral approach trades off the primitive exact falsification relation of the bilateral approach for a primitive exclusion relation between states, thereby raising the question if exclusion serves any purpose other than to avoid exact falsification. We argue that exclusion is motivated independently of its use in avoiding exact falsification, namely as a foundation for the reconstruction of modal notions such as possibility and necessity. This reconstruction in turn motivates what we call <i>emergent exclusion</i>: an atomic state can exclude a sum of atomic states collectively without excluding any of these atomic states individually. Emergent exclusion is banned in Fine (2017a) in order to maintain exact equivalence in de Morgan’s law <span>(lnot (P wedge Q) Leftrightarrow lnot P vee lnot Q)</span>; we argue that the two sides of this law are not exactly equivalent and discuss a variety of state spaces that feature emergent exclusion. This paper aims to be accessible to linguists without prior exposure to truthmaker semantics. We highlight points of contact with natural language semantics, such as event semantics and algebraic semantics of plurals and conjunction.</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"80 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-08-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141882484","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-07-18DOI: 10.1007/s10988-024-09409-5
Diti Bhadra
This paper explores the distribution and semantics of the reversative affix un- and the restitutive affix re-, and overall makes a new proposal about the lexical semantics of verbs. I argue that these affixes tell a story of derivational morphology that is based not on categorization of verbs into neat aspectual and decompositional classes, but on the result of the verb’s action on the object and whether or not such a result state permits reversal and restitution. The argument structure of these affixes shows us that morphology interacts with semantics in a true compositional sense, whereby the affectedness of the object is a crucial factor in determining compatibility and composition. I propose an approach to verb meaning that encodes this important information as outcomes: the lifespan properties of the object after the action occurs on it. I propose, formulating the Verb-Root-Outcomes framework, that all verb roots come equipped with sets of outcomes. A wide array of verbs that have been classified as ‘change-of-state’ are shown to have different sub-classes based on the shape of the outcome set, and this also allows a formal definition of what ‘potential’ change could mean. The affixes un- and re- are modeled as result-state modifiers, which are sensitive to the outcomes of the action of the verb stem they attach to, and only attach when their presuppositions about the state of the object are met. Apart from directly comparing reversal and restitution with the same formal notion of equivalence, this approach also allows a transparent representation of event decomposition, whereby change in the object is able to be tracked at a granular level and its importance in determining the success of morphological derivations highlighted. This theory argues for compositional semantic interpretation at a sub-lexical level, while also showing how sentential and pragmatic factors affect verb meaning and derivational affixation .
{"title":"Verb roots encode outcomes: argument structure and lexical semantics of reversal and restitution","authors":"Diti Bhadra","doi":"10.1007/s10988-024-09409-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-024-09409-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper explores the distribution and semantics of the reversative affix <i>un-</i> and the restitutive affix <i>re-</i>, and overall makes a new proposal about the lexical semantics of verbs. I argue that these affixes tell a story of derivational morphology that is based not on categorization of verbs into neat aspectual and decompositional classes, but on the result of the verb’s action on the object and whether or not such a result state permits reversal and restitution. The argument structure of these affixes shows us that morphology interacts with semantics in a true compositional sense, whereby the affectedness of the object is a crucial factor in determining compatibility and composition. I propose an approach to verb meaning that encodes this important information as outcomes: the lifespan properties of the object after the action occurs on it. I propose, formulating the Verb-Root-Outcomes framework, that all verb roots come equipped with sets of outcomes. A wide array of verbs that have been classified as ‘change-of-state’ are shown to have different sub-classes based on the shape of the outcome set, and this also allows a formal definition of what ‘potential’ change could mean. The affixes <i>un-</i> and <i>re-</i> are modeled as result-state modifiers, which are sensitive to the outcomes of the action of the verb stem they attach to, and only attach when their presuppositions about the state of the object are met. Apart from directly comparing reversal and restitution with the same formal notion of equivalence, this approach also allows a transparent representation of event decomposition, whereby change in the object is able to be tracked at a granular level and its importance in determining the success of morphological derivations highlighted. This theory argues for compositional semantic interpretation at a sub-lexical level, while also showing how sentential and pragmatic factors affect verb meaning and derivational affixation .\u0000</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"107 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-07-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141740775","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-06-22DOI: 10.1007/s10988-023-09403-3
Line Mikkelsen, Daniel Hardt
We propose an account of interpretive effects involving same and different, relying on two claims: the first is that same and different are able to take scope, and the second is that they are presuppositional. On this account, same and different are decomposed into two parts: an additive operator TOO and a (non-)identity predicate. We argue that this account provides a more parsimonious account of well-known properties of same and different, such as the distinction between internal and external readings, as well as the parallelism effects discovered by Hardt and Mikkelsen (Linguist Philos 38:289–314, 2015). We also present a solution to a previously unexplained puzzle involving comparatives.
{"title":"Same and different are additive presupposition triggers","authors":"Line Mikkelsen, Daniel Hardt","doi":"10.1007/s10988-023-09403-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09403-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We propose an account of interpretive effects involving <i>same</i> and <i>different</i>, relying on two claims: the first is that <i>same</i> and <i>different</i> are able to take scope, and the second is that they are presuppositional. On this account, <i>same</i> and <i>different</i> are decomposed into two parts: an additive operator TOO and a (non-)identity predicate. We argue that this account provides a more parsimonious account of well-known properties of <i>same</i> and <i>different</i>, such as the distinction between internal and external readings, as well as the parallelism effects discovered by Hardt and Mikkelsen (Linguist Philos 38:289–314, 2015). We also present a solution to a previously unexplained puzzle involving comparatives.</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"19 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141511137","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-05-31DOI: 10.1007/s10988-023-09408-y
Peter Hawke, Levin Hornischer, Francesco Berto
When do two sentences say the same thing, that is, express the same content? We defend two-component (2C) semantics: the view that propositional contents comprise (at least) two irreducibly distinct constituents: (1) truth-conditions and (2) subject-matter. We contrast 2C with one-component (1C) semantics, focusing on the view that subject-matter is reducible to truth-conditions. We identify exponents of this view and argue in favor of 2C. An appendix proposes a general formal template for propositional 2C semantics.
{"title":"Truth, topicality, and transparency: one-component versus two-component semantics","authors":"Peter Hawke, Levin Hornischer, Francesco Berto","doi":"10.1007/s10988-023-09408-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09408-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p>When do two sentences say the same thing, that is, express the same content? We defend two-component (2C) semantics: the view that propositional contents comprise (at least) two irreducibly distinct constituents: (1) truth-conditions and (2) subject-matter. We contrast 2C with one-component (1C) semantics, focusing on the view that subject-matter is reducible to truth-conditions. We identify exponents of this view and argue in favor of 2C. An appendix proposes a general formal template for propositional 2C semantics.\u0000</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"22 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-05-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141195103","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-05-21DOI: 10.1007/s10988-023-09406-0
Daniel Asherov, Danny Fox, Roni Katzir
The literature in semantics and pragmatics provides extensive evidence for the strengthening of linguistic expressions, both in matrix positions and when embedded under various operators. We study the properties of such strengthening using a very simple setting. Specifically, we look at when the expression “crate with a banana” can be understood as a unique crate even though two different crates have a banana in them. By varying the scenarios in which an expression such as “Pick the crate with a banana” is evaluated, we show that the strengthening of “crate with a banana” within the scope of the definite article parallels the entailments of “crate with only a banana” (with an overt exhaustivity operator, ‘only’). We use this observation to argue that strengthening in embedded positions follows the logic of an exhaustivity operator rather than that of rational inference. We then note that a similar pattern obtains in matrix positions.
{"title":"Strengthening, exhaustification, and rational inference","authors":"Daniel Asherov, Danny Fox, Roni Katzir","doi":"10.1007/s10988-023-09406-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09406-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p> The literature in semantics and pragmatics provides extensive evidence for the strengthening of linguistic expressions, both in matrix positions and when embedded under various operators. We study the properties of such strengthening using a very simple setting. Specifically, we look at when the expression “crate with a banana” can be understood as a unique crate even though two different crates have a banana in them. By varying the scenarios in which an expression such as “Pick the crate with a banana” is evaluated, we show that the strengthening of “crate with a banana” within the scope of the definite article parallels the entailments of “crate with only a banana” (with an overt exhaustivity operator, ‘only’). We use this observation to argue that strengthening in embedded positions follows the logic of an exhaustivity operator rather than that of rational inference. We then note that a similar pattern obtains in matrix positions.</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"172 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-05-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141867580","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-05-18DOI: 10.1007/s10988-023-09400-6
Yi-Hsun Chen
Superlative modifiers (SMs) are known to demonstrate an ambiguity between an epistemic reading (EPI) conveying speaker ignorance and a concessive reading (CON) conveying speaker concession. Such EPI-CON ambiguity has often been taken, implicitly or explicitly, to be a lexical coincidence. While there may be some justification for such a position when a single language is considered, we argue for an intrinsic connection between the two readings based on cross-linguistic considerations. This paper focuses on English at least and Mandarin zhi-shao as representative of superlative modifiers across a wide range of languages to propose a unified account of the two readings. The proposal builds on Biezma (2013) in relying on the role of focus and scalarity in developing a unified semantics for the two readings, but differs in capitalizing on the fact that cross-linguistically superlative modifiers use the same morphological formants as quantity superlatives. It also follows Biezma (2013) in taking pragmatic factors as crucial in deriving the variation between EPI and CON readings. Elaborating on her account, it offers a more nuanced picture of the ways in which EPI is sensitive to the question of informativity while CON relates to issues of evaluativity. The paper shows how the proposed semantics and pragmatics account for several well-known properties of superlative modifiers. It ends by noting several open issues in the literature on this topic that the current proposal sheds new light on.
众所周知,高级修饰语(SMs)在表示说话人无知的认识性读法(EPI)和表示说话人让步的让步性读法(CON)之间表现出一种模糊性。这种 EPI-CON 的模糊性常常被或明或暗地认为是词汇上的巧合。虽然在考虑单一语言时,这种立场可能有一定的道理,但我们基于跨语言的考虑,认为这两种读法之间存在内在联系。本文以英语的 "至少 "和普通话的 "之少 "为研究对象,将其作为多种语言中超格修饰语的代表,提出了两种读法的统一解释。该建议以 Biezma(2013)为基础,依靠焦点和标度的作用为两种读法建立统一的语义,但不同之处在于利用了跨语言的超修饰语与数量超修饰语使用相同的形态构式这一事实。该研究还遵循 Biezma(2013 年)的观点,将语用因素作为得出 EPI 和 CON 读法之间差异的关键因素。在 Biezma 的论述基础上,本文对 EPI 对信息性问题的敏感性和 CON 对评价性问题的敏感性进行了更细致的描述。论文展示了所提出的语义学和语用学是如何解释超褒义修饰语的几个众所周知的特性的。最后,论文指出了有关这一主题的文献中存在的几个未决问题,而当前的提议为这些问题提供了新的思路。
{"title":"Ignorance and concession with superlative modifiers: a cross-linguistic perspective","authors":"Yi-Hsun Chen","doi":"10.1007/s10988-023-09400-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09400-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Superlative modifiers (SMs) are known to demonstrate an ambiguity between an epistemic reading (EPI) conveying speaker ignorance and a concessive reading (CON) conveying speaker concession. Such EPI-CON ambiguity has often been taken, implicitly or explicitly, to be a lexical coincidence. While there may be some justification for such a position when a single language is considered, we argue for an intrinsic connection between the two readings based on cross-linguistic considerations. This paper focuses on English <i>at least</i> and Mandarin <i>zhi-shao</i> as representative of superlative modifiers across a wide range of languages to propose a unified account of the two readings. The proposal builds on Biezma (2013) in relying on the role of focus and scalarity in developing a unified semantics for the two readings, but differs in capitalizing on the fact that cross-linguistically superlative modifiers use the same morphological formants as quantity superlatives. It also follows Biezma (2013) in taking pragmatic factors as crucial in deriving the variation between EPI and CON readings. Elaborating on her account, it offers a more nuanced picture of the ways in which EPI is sensitive to the question of informativity while CON relates to issues of evaluativity. The paper shows how the proposed semantics and pragmatics account for several well-known properties of superlative modifiers. It ends by noting several open issues in the literature on this topic that the current proposal sheds new light on.</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"67 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-05-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141063836","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-03-04DOI: 10.1007/s10988-023-09397-y
Thomas Grano
Recent work on mood choice considers fine-grained semantic differences among desire predicates (notably, ‘want’ and ‘hope’) and their consequences for the distribution of indicative and subjunctive complement clauses. In that vein, this paper takes a close look at ‘intend’. I show that cross-linguistically, ‘intend’ accepts nonfinite and subjunctive complements and rejects indicative complements. This fact poses difficulties for recent approaches to mood choice. Toward a solution, a broad aim of this paper is to argue that—while ‘intend’ is loosely in the family of desire predicates—it differs from ‘want’ and ‘hope’ in that it has a causative component, and this is relevant to its mood choice behavior, given that causative predicates also systematically reject indicative complements. More concretely, my analysis has three ingredients: (i) following related proposals in philosophy, intention reports have causally self-referential content; (ii) encoding causal self-reference requires abstraction over the complement clause’s eventuality argument; and (iii) nonfinite and subjunctive clauses enable such abstraction but indicative clauses do not. Aside from causative predicates, independent support for the proposal comes from the syntax of belief-/intention-hybrid attitude predicates like ‘decide’ and ‘convince’, anankastic conditional antecedents, aspectual predicates, and memory and perception reports. Synthesizing this result with that of previous literature, the emergent generalization is that subjunctive mood occurs in attitude reports that involve either comparison or eventuality abstraction. Toward a unified theory of mood choice, I suggest that both comparison and eventuality abstraction represent departures from the clausal semantics of unembedded assertions and consequently that subjunctive mood signals such a departure.
{"title":"Intention reports and eventuality abstraction in a theory of mood choice","authors":"Thomas Grano","doi":"10.1007/s10988-023-09397-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09397-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Recent work on mood choice considers fine-grained semantic differences among desire predicates (notably, ‘want’ and ‘hope’) and their consequences for the distribution of indicative and subjunctive complement clauses. In that vein, this paper takes a close look at ‘intend’. I show that cross-linguistically, ‘intend’ accepts nonfinite and subjunctive complements and rejects indicative complements. This fact poses difficulties for recent approaches to mood choice. Toward a solution, a broad aim of this paper is to argue that—while ‘intend’ is loosely in the family of desire predicates—it differs from ‘want’ and ‘hope’ in that it has a causative component, and this is relevant to its mood choice behavior, given that causative predicates also systematically reject indicative complements. More concretely, my analysis has three ingredients: (i) following related proposals in philosophy, intention reports have causally self-referential content; (ii) encoding causal self-reference requires abstraction over the complement clause’s eventuality argument; and (iii) nonfinite and subjunctive clauses enable such abstraction but indicative clauses do not. Aside from causative predicates, independent support for the proposal comes from the syntax of belief-/intention-hybrid attitude predicates like ‘decide’ and ‘convince’, anankastic conditional antecedents, aspectual predicates, and memory and perception reports. Synthesizing this result with that of previous literature, the emergent generalization is that subjunctive mood occurs in attitude reports that involve either comparison or eventuality abstraction. Toward a unified theory of mood choice, I suggest that both comparison and eventuality abstraction represent departures from the clausal semantics of unembedded assertions and consequently that subjunctive mood signals such a departure.</p>","PeriodicalId":47748,"journal":{"name":"Linguistics and Philosophy","volume":"55 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-03-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140034436","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}