首页 > 最新文献

Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie最新文献

英文 中文
Transformativism and Expressivity in Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind 黑格尔心灵哲学中的转换性与表现性
Pub Date : 2024-03-11 DOI: 10.1515/agph-2021-0082
Julia Peters
According to a major trend in Hegel scholarship, Hegel advocates a McDowell-style transformativist conception of the human mind. Central to this conception is a methodological dualism, according to which phenomena belonging to the rational mind, in contrast to those belonging to non-rational nature, must be accounted for from within the ‘space of reasons.’ In this paper I argue, by contrast, that Hegel rejects methodological dualism. For Hegel, a constitutive aspect of the rational mind is the activity of expression. I show how Hegel’s philosophy of mind adequately accounts for low-level forms of expressivity without appealing to capacities connected to conceptual thought and judgment, and that he does so by drawing on methods similar to those employed within the empirical sciences of his time. Thus, for Hegel, the sphere of the rational mind is broader than the McDowellian space of reasons.
根据黑格尔学术研究的主要趋势,黑格尔主张对人类心灵采用麦克道尔式的转换主义概念。这一概念的核心是方法论二元论,根据这一概念,属于理性思维的现象与属于非理性自然的现象相比,必须在'理性空间'内加以解释。而在本文中,我认为黑格尔反对方法论二元论。在黑格尔看来,理性思维的一个构成方面是表达活动。我将说明黑格尔的心灵哲学是如何在不诉诸与概念思维和判断相关的能力的情况下,充分解释低层次的表达形式的,而且他是通过借鉴与他那个时代的实证科学所使用的方法相类似的方法来做到这一点的。因此,对黑格尔来说,理性思维的范围比麦克道尔的理性空间更为广阔。
{"title":"Transformativism and Expressivity in Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind","authors":"Julia Peters","doi":"10.1515/agph-2021-0082","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2021-0082","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 According to a major trend in Hegel scholarship, Hegel advocates a McDowell-style transformativist conception of the human mind. Central to this conception is a methodological dualism, according to which phenomena belonging to the rational mind, in contrast to those belonging to non-rational nature, must be accounted for from within the ‘space of reasons.’ In this paper I argue, by contrast, that Hegel rejects methodological dualism. For Hegel, a constitutive aspect of the rational mind is the activity of expression. I show how Hegel’s philosophy of mind adequately accounts for low-level forms of expressivity without appealing to capacities connected to conceptual thought and judgment, and that he does so by drawing on methods similar to those employed within the empirical sciences of his time. Thus, for Hegel, the sphere of the rational mind is broader than the McDowellian space of reasons.","PeriodicalId":517350,"journal":{"name":"Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie","volume":"42 6","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140253449","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Aristotle on Non-substantial Particulars, Fundamentality, and Change 亚里士多德论非实体性细节、基本性和变化
Pub Date : 2024-02-07 DOI: 10.1515/agph-2023-0027
Keren Wilson Shatalov
There is a debate about whether particular properties are for Aristotle non-recurrent and trope-like individuals or recurrent universals. I argue that Physics I.7 provides evidence that he took non-substantial particulars to be neither; they are instead non-recurrent modes. Physics I.7 also helps show why this matters. Particular properties must be individual modes in order for Aristotle to preserve three key philosophical commitments: that objects of ordinary experience are primary substances, that primary substances undergo genuine change, and that primary substances are ontologically fundamental.
对于亚里士多德来说,特殊属性究竟是非重复性的特例个体,还是重复性的普遍性,存在着争论。我认为,《物理学》I.7 提供的证据表明,亚里士多德认为非实体的特殊性既不是,也不是;它们是非循环的模式。物理学》I.7 还有助于说明为什么这很重要。特殊属性必须是个别的模式,亚里士多德才能保留三个关键的哲学承诺:普通经验的对象是原初物质,原初物质经历真正的变化,以及原初物质在本体论上是基本的。
{"title":"Aristotle on Non-substantial Particulars, Fundamentality, and Change","authors":"Keren Wilson Shatalov","doi":"10.1515/agph-2023-0027","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2023-0027","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 There is a debate about whether particular properties are for Aristotle non-recurrent and trope-like individuals or recurrent universals. I argue that Physics I.7 provides evidence that he took non-substantial particulars to be neither; they are instead non-recurrent modes. Physics I.7 also helps show why this matters. Particular properties must be individual modes in order for Aristotle to preserve three key philosophical commitments: that objects of ordinary experience are primary substances, that primary substances undergo genuine change, and that primary substances are ontologically fundamental.","PeriodicalId":517350,"journal":{"name":"Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie","volume":"167 ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-02-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140460346","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Stoic Distinction between Syllogisms and Subsyllogisms 斯多葛派对论辩式和副论辩式的区分
Pub Date : 2024-02-07 DOI: 10.1515/agph-2022-0018
Fabian Ruge
This paper aims to explain the distinction between syllogisms and subsyllogisms in Stoic logic. Subsyllogisms replace at least one premise in a syllogism with a premise that is, according to Galen and Alexander, equipollent to the respective syllogistic premise. This equipollence is not synonymy of meaning between two linguistic expressions, but obtains between two propositions when they are true or false by the same standard. Subsyllogistic premises are simple propositions that are equipollent to the non-simple premises of the respective syllogisms. For subsyllogistic premises that replace syllogistic premises consist of predicates combining with cases rather than of connectives or negations governing propositions. Because of this difference in their premises, subsyllogisms have a different logical form than syllogisms and are not formally valid.
本文旨在解释斯多葛逻辑中的三段论与副三段论之间的区别。根据盖伦和亚历山大的观点,亚复句至少用一个前提取代了三段论中的一个前提,而这个前提与相应的三段论前提是等价的。这种等价性不是两个语言表达之间的同义性,而是两个命题之间的同义性,当它们以相同的标准来判断真假时,就会产生等价性。副逻辑前提是简单命题,与相应的三段论的非简单前提等价。因为取代三段论前提的子三段论前提是由谓词结合情况构成的,而不是由连接词或否定句构成的。由于它们的前提不同,子逻辑与三段论具有不同的逻辑形式,在形式上是无效的。
{"title":"The Stoic Distinction between Syllogisms and Subsyllogisms","authors":"Fabian Ruge","doi":"10.1515/agph-2022-0018","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2022-0018","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 This paper aims to explain the distinction between syllogisms and subsyllogisms in Stoic logic. Subsyllogisms replace at least one premise in a syllogism with a premise that is, according to Galen and Alexander, equipollent to the respective syllogistic premise. This equipollence is not synonymy of meaning between two linguistic expressions, but obtains between two propositions when they are true or false by the same standard. Subsyllogistic premises are simple propositions that are equipollent to the non-simple premises of the respective syllogisms. For subsyllogistic premises that replace syllogistic premises consist of predicates combining with cases rather than of connectives or negations governing propositions. Because of this difference in their premises, subsyllogisms have a different logical form than syllogisms and are not formally valid.","PeriodicalId":517350,"journal":{"name":"Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie","volume":"124 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-02-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140460673","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Natorp Saw and Burnyeat Missed 唯心主义与希腊哲学:纳托普所见与伯恩耶特所失
Pub Date : 2024-02-03 DOI: 10.1515/agph-2022-0098
Sylvain Delcomminette
In his paper “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Berkeley Missed and Descartes Saw,” Myles Burnyeat purports to show not only that idealism was not endorsed by any ancient philosopher, but also that it could not have been endorsed before Descartes; Greek philosophy was dominated by an “unquestioned, unquestioning assumption of realism.” By ‘idealism,’ Burnyeat means mainly Berkeley’s immaterialism, but he also extends his demonstration to something more akin to Kant’s transcendental idealism. After arguing that this last version has more historical credentials to the title of idealism than Berkeley’s doctrine, I compare Burnyeat’s reading to Natorp’s interpretation in Platos Ideenlehre, subtitled “An Introduction to Idealism.” Natorp argues that there is, on the contrary, a kind of underlying idealism in Greek philosophy, one that can be discerned on the basis of an interpretation of the meaning of the verb ‘to be’ which has found support in more recent research.
在他的论文《唯心主义与希腊哲学:迈尔斯-伯恩耶特(Myles Burnyeat)在他的论文《理想主义与希腊哲学:伯克利所忽略的和笛卡尔所看到的》中,不仅试图证明理想主义没有得到任何古代哲学家的认可,而且还试图证明在笛卡尔之前,理想主义不可能得到认可;希腊哲学被 "毫无疑问、不容置疑的现实主义假设 "所支配。伯恩耶特所说的 "唯心主义 "主要指的是伯克利的非物质主义,但他也将自己的论证扩展到更类似于康德的超验唯心主义。在论证了最后一个版本比伯克利的学说更具有理想主义称号的历史资质之后,我将伯恩耶特的解读与纳托普在《柏拉图的理想国》(Platos Ideenlehre)一书(副标题为 "理想主义导论")中的阐释进行了比较。纳托普认为,相反,希腊哲学中有一种潜在的唯心主义,这种唯心主义可以根据对动词 "存在 "含义的解释加以辨别,而这种解释在最近的研究中得到了支持。
{"title":"Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Natorp Saw and Burnyeat Missed","authors":"Sylvain Delcomminette","doi":"10.1515/agph-2022-0098","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2022-0098","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In his paper “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Berkeley Missed and Descartes Saw,” Myles Burnyeat purports to show not only that idealism was not endorsed by any ancient philosopher, but also that it could not have been endorsed before Descartes; Greek philosophy was dominated by an “unquestioned, unquestioning assumption of realism.” By ‘idealism,’ Burnyeat means mainly Berkeley’s immaterialism, but he also extends his demonstration to something more akin to Kant’s transcendental idealism. After arguing that this last version has more historical credentials to the title of idealism than Berkeley’s doctrine, I compare Burnyeat’s reading to Natorp’s interpretation in Platos Ideenlehre, subtitled “An Introduction to Idealism.” Natorp argues that there is, on the contrary, a kind of underlying idealism in Greek philosophy, one that can be discerned on the basis of an interpretation of the meaning of the verb ‘to be’ which has found support in more recent research.","PeriodicalId":517350,"journal":{"name":"Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie","volume":"10 3","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-02-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139896491","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Carl Stumpf and the Curious Incident of Music in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus 卡尔-斯通普夫与维特根斯坦《论语》中的音乐奇事
Pub Date : 2024-01-16 DOI: 10.1515/agph-2021-0141
Eran Guter
Abstract This essay explores Wittgenstein’s encounter with Stumpf’s work in Tone Psychology during a rarely studied period in Wittgenstein’s early career when he worked as a researcher in Myers’s laboratory for experimental psychology in Cambridge. I argue that Stumpf’s emphasis on the notion of musicality as the ability to characterize what is ‘musical’ about music troubled Wittgenstein’s initial formulation of his career-long adherence to the comparison between language and music. In the Tractatus the importance of internal projective relations far exceeds that of arbitrariness in language. This results in the curious elision of musicality in the Tractatus, as shown in his gramophone analogy. The acknowledgment of the enormous complexity pertaining to the facts of human life remained underdeveloped in Wittgenstein’s philosophy until the anthropological turn in his middle-period. Only then do we see the blooming of the language-as-music simile and its eventual impact on Wittgenstein’s later philosophy.
摘要 本文探讨了维特根斯坦在剑桥迈尔斯实验心理学实验室担任研究员期间,与斯通普夫在音调心理学方面的研究成果的相遇。我认为,斯通普夫强调音乐性的概念是描述音乐 "音乐性 "的能力,这对维特根斯坦在其职业生涯中坚持将语言与音乐进行比较的最初表述造成了困扰。在《理论篇》中,内部投射关系的重要性远远超过语言的任意性。这就导致了《论理学》中音乐性的奇特消失,正如他的留声机比喻所显示的那样。在维特根斯坦哲学的中期人类学转向之前,对人类生活事实的巨大复杂性的认识一直没有得到充分发展。只有在那时,我们才能看到语言即音乐的比喻的绽放及其对维特根斯坦后期哲学的最终影响。
{"title":"Carl Stumpf and the Curious Incident of Music in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus","authors":"Eran Guter","doi":"10.1515/agph-2021-0141","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2021-0141","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This essay explores Wittgenstein’s encounter with Stumpf’s work in Tone Psychology during a rarely studied period in Wittgenstein’s early career when he worked as a researcher in Myers’s laboratory for experimental psychology in Cambridge. I argue that Stumpf’s emphasis on the notion of musicality as the ability to characterize what is ‘musical’ about music troubled Wittgenstein’s initial formulation of his career-long adherence to the comparison between language and music. In the Tractatus the importance of internal projective relations far exceeds that of arbitrariness in language. This results in the curious elision of musicality in the Tractatus, as shown in his gramophone analogy. The acknowledgment of the enormous complexity pertaining to the facts of human life remained underdeveloped in Wittgenstein’s philosophy until the anthropological turn in his middle-period. Only then do we see the blooming of the language-as-music simile and its eventual impact on Wittgenstein’s later philosophy.","PeriodicalId":517350,"journal":{"name":"Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie","volume":"23 11","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140506060","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Emergence of Marx’s Concept of Subsumption 马克思 "亚消费 "概念的产生
Pub Date : 2024-01-16 DOI: 10.1515/agph-2022-0074
T. Giladi
Abstract In Marx’s posthumously published manuscripts from 1857–1863, we find a systematic exposition of his concept of subsumption. Though much has been written about it, significant interpretative gaps persist. In this article, I begin filling these gaps by examining the emergence of Marx’s concept of subsumption. I will argue that in the Grundrisse Marx brings together distinct but complementary elements from Hegel’s theories of judgment and teleology to coin two new and well delineated concepts of subsumption that prefigure his later concepts of formal and real subsumption. These two concepts may be defined as: (a) the process of acquiring the social relational property of being a means to an end; (b) the process by which changes in non-relational properties occur in something due to this acquisition – and occur to better suit said end.
摘要 在马克思于 1857 年至 1863 年期间追授出版的手稿中,我们发现了他对 "归并 "概念的系统阐述。尽管有关这一概念的论述已经很多,但在解释上仍然存在重大空白。在本文中,我将通过考察马克思 "子集 "概念的出现,开始填补这些空白。我将论证,在《基础理论》中,马克思从黑格尔的判断理论和目的论中汇集了不同但互补的元素,创造了两个新的、明确界定的子归属概念,这两个概念预示了他后来的形式子归属和实在子归属概念。这两个概念可以定义为(a) 获得作为达到目的的手段的社会关系属性的过程;(b) 由于这种获得,非关系属性在事物中发生变化的过程--这种变化的发生是为了更好地适应所述目的。
{"title":"The Emergence of Marx’s Concept of Subsumption","authors":"T. Giladi","doi":"10.1515/agph-2022-0074","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2022-0074","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In Marx’s posthumously published manuscripts from 1857–1863, we find a systematic exposition of his concept of subsumption. Though much has been written about it, significant interpretative gaps persist. In this article, I begin filling these gaps by examining the emergence of Marx’s concept of subsumption. I will argue that in the Grundrisse Marx brings together distinct but complementary elements from Hegel’s theories of judgment and teleology to coin two new and well delineated concepts of subsumption that prefigure his later concepts of formal and real subsumption. These two concepts may be defined as: (a) the process of acquiring the social relational property of being a means to an end; (b) the process by which changes in non-relational properties occur in something due to this acquisition – and occur to better suit said end.","PeriodicalId":517350,"journal":{"name":"Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie","volume":"6 3","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-01-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140505616","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1