首页 > 最新文献

Buffalo Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
The Gun Subsidy 枪支补贴
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2020-02-12 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3537278
C. Turner, Justin C. Van Orsdol
Despite thousands of gun deaths annually, the United States has failed to reach consensus on any means of addressing the public health crisis that is gun violence. The issue has become politically polarized, constitutionalized, and an object of pessimism and despair. We propose a regulatory system in which gun manufacturers would be strictly liable to a federal fund for deaths caused by their guns, paired with a subsidy that will serve to ensure the availability of guns sufficient to meet the rights the Supreme Court has found in the Second Amendment. While strict liability of this kind can indeed serve its traditional purposes of spreading costs and incentivizing better designs and processes, our primary goal is to alter the political economy around the issue of gun violence more generally. If manufacturers bear an increasing share of the costs created by their products, they will endeavor not only to produce products and advertise them in ways likely to reduce those costs but also to advocate for regulations that may do the same. While our proposal may not depolarize the issue entirely, it at least attempts to focus the minds and experience of those who know guns best on effective means of reducing guns’ social costs.
尽管每年有数千人死于枪支,但美国未能就解决枪支暴力引发的公共卫生危机达成任何共识。这个问题已经在政治上两极化,宪法化,成为悲观和绝望的对象。我们建议建立一个监管体系,在这个体系中,枪支制造商将严格地对由他们的枪支造成的死亡承担联邦基金的责任,并提供补贴,以确保枪支的可获得性足以满足最高法院在《第二修正案》中规定的权利。虽然这种严格责任确实可以达到分摊成本和激励更好的设计和流程的传统目的,但我们的主要目标是更广泛地改变围绕枪支暴力问题的政治经济学。如果制造商承担越来越多的产品成本,他们不仅会努力以可能降低成本的方式生产产品和宣传产品,而且还会倡导可能降低成本的法规。虽然我们的提议可能不会完全消除这个问题的两极化,但它至少试图将那些最了解枪支的人的思想和经验集中在减少枪支社会成本的有效手段上。
{"title":"The Gun Subsidy","authors":"C. Turner, Justin C. Van Orsdol","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3537278","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3537278","url":null,"abstract":"Despite thousands of gun deaths annually, the United States has failed to reach consensus on any means of addressing the public health crisis that is gun violence. The issue has become politically polarized, constitutionalized, and an object of pessimism and despair. We propose a regulatory system in which gun manufacturers would be strictly liable to a federal fund for deaths caused by their guns, paired with a subsidy that will serve to ensure the availability of guns sufficient to meet the rights the Supreme Court has found in the Second Amendment. While strict liability of this kind can indeed serve its traditional purposes of spreading costs and incentivizing better designs and processes, our primary goal is to alter the political economy around the issue of gun violence more generally. If manufacturers bear an increasing share of the costs created by their products, they will endeavor not only to produce products and advertise them in ways likely to reduce those costs but also to advocate for regulations that may do the same. While our proposal may not depolarize the issue entirely, it at least attempts to focus the minds and experience of those who know guns best on effective means of reducing guns’ social costs.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"68 1","pages":"1117"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-02-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41579976","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abandoning Realization and the Transition Tax: Toward a Comprehensive Tax Base 放弃变现与过渡税:走向综合税基
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2019-10-11 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3273098
Henry Ordower
The Tax Cuts and Jobs Act of 2017 imposed a tax, the “transition tax,” on as much as 31 years of undistributed, accumulated corporate income. This article focus on that transition tax as it evaluates the function and constitutionality of the tax and considers whether the transition tax might serve as a model for addressing the broader problem of deferred income in the United States. The article views the transition tax as joining the expatriation tax and other mark to market inclusion provisions in abandoning any pretext that there is continued vitality in the realization principle as something more compelling than any other longstanding and obsolescing tax principle. Recommending that Congress seize the Tax Cuts and Jobs Act moment and discard the general rule deferring the inclusion of gain in income through a realization requirement in favor of the annual marking to market of all the taxpayer’s property, the article models a general mark to market transition tax after the new transition tax on deferred foreign income. The proposal recommends inclusion of the net gain in taxpayers’ incomes at significantly reduced rates of tax, including one rate for liquid assets and a lower rate for illiquid assets and an opportunity to pay the tax in installments. Following the initial inclusion under this transition tax, gain and loss would be included annually consistent with comprehensive tax base definitions under an accrual system of taxation based on marking to market. Growth or decline in the value of taxpayers’ property would be taken into account income annually. In some instances permitting some taxpayers to defer payment of the tax until disposition of the property may be desirable but the continued deferral might incur an interest charge.
2017年的《减税和就业法案》(Tax Cuts and Jobs Act)对长达31年的未分配累积企业收入征收了一项税收,即“过渡税”。本文重点关注过渡税,因为它评估了税收的功能和合宪性,并考虑过渡税是否可以作为解决美国更广泛的递延收入问题的模型。本文认为,过渡税与移居税和其他按市场计价的规定一样,放弃了实现原则具有持续活力的任何借口,因为它比任何其他长期存在和过时的税收原则都更有说服力。建议国会抓住减税和就业法案的时机,放弃通过实现要求推迟纳入收入收益的一般规则,转而支持所有纳税人财产的年度市值计价,文章在递延外国收入的新过渡税之后建立了一般市值计价过渡税。该提案建议将净收益纳入纳税人收入,并大幅降低税率,包括对流动资产实行统一税率,对非流动资产实行较低税率,并提供分期纳税的机会。在最初纳入这种过渡税之后,利得和损失将按照以市场计价的权责发生制税制下的综合税基定义每年纳入。纳税人财产价值的增长或下降将被计入每年的收入。在某些情况下,允许一些纳税人推迟支付税款,直到财产处置可能是可取的,但继续推迟可能会产生利息费用。
{"title":"Abandoning Realization and the Transition Tax: Toward a Comprehensive Tax Base","authors":"Henry Ordower","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3273098","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3273098","url":null,"abstract":"The Tax Cuts and Jobs Act of 2017 imposed a tax, the “transition tax,” on as much as 31 years of undistributed, accumulated corporate income. This article focus on that transition tax as it evaluates the function and constitutionality of the tax and considers whether the transition tax might serve as a model for addressing the broader problem of deferred income in the United States. The article views the transition tax as joining the expatriation tax and other mark to market inclusion provisions in abandoning any pretext that there is continued vitality in the realization principle as something more compelling than any other longstanding and obsolescing tax principle. Recommending that Congress seize the Tax Cuts and Jobs Act moment and discard the general rule deferring the inclusion of gain in income through a realization requirement in favor of the annual marking to market of all the taxpayer’s property, the article models a general mark to market transition tax after the new transition tax on deferred foreign income. The proposal recommends inclusion of the net gain in taxpayers’ incomes at significantly reduced rates of tax, including one rate for liquid assets and a lower rate for illiquid assets and an opportunity to pay the tax in installments. Following the initial inclusion under this transition tax, gain and loss would be included annually consistent with comprehensive tax base definitions under an accrual system of taxation based on marking to market. Growth or decline in the value of taxpayers’ property would be taken into account income annually. In some instances permitting some taxpayers to defer payment of the tax until disposition of the property may be desirable but the continued deferral might incur an interest charge.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"67 1","pages":"1371"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2019-10-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42456954","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Rules, Standards, and Such 规则、标准等等
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2019-02-09 DOI: 10.31228/osf.io/n2kx3
K. Clermont
This Article aims to create a complete typology of the forms of decisional law. Distinguishing “rules” from “standards” is the most commonly attempted jurisprudential line, roughly drawn between nonvague and vague. But no agreement exists on the dimension along which the rule/standard terminology lies, or on where the dividing line on the continuum lies. Thus, classifying in terms of vagueness is itself vague. Ultimately it does not aid legal actors in formulating or applying the law. The classification works best as an evocative image. A clearer distinction would be useful in formulating or applying the law. For the law-applier, it would be more useful if expressly focused on whether the law-giver was trying to pin things down and thus narrow the room for discretion. It would be even more useful if it had helped that law-giver to think about how to pin things down.This better top-level distinction lies between binary and scalar directives. If the directive comprises a checklist of one or more yes/no conditions, then it is a binary directive. If instead the directive calls for consideration of multivalent factors, it is a scalar directive. Binary/scalar is a superior distinction for analysis. First, binary/scalar is a clean distinction. Second, it is a telling distinction that represents a significant difference between the components that compose the law. Third, it tells the law-applier much about whether the law-giver tried to pin things down. Fourth, it conveys a better sense of the tools at hand for the law-giver’s pinning down the law-applier, and thus enables the tools’ deployment in an optimal way. Fifth, it allows the drawing of meaningful subdivisions that bring to the fore the choices in shaping that law: for example, one such subtype of scalar directives is a true balancing test, which explicitly or implicitly presents an exhaustive listing of quantifiable and commensurable considerations to be scaled and weighed against one another—and offers a route to retrieving control in the application of any law that has to be expressed as a scalar directive.Parenthetically, a running example to illustrate the superiority of binary/scalar comes from injunctive relief. The test for a temporary restraining order was the supposedly binary condition of “irreparable harm,” but it has disintegrated in practice to the prevailing test for a preliminary injunction. The diversity among the tests for preliminary injunctions reveals the essential struggle between the necessary flexibility for infinitely variable situations and the need for appropriately corralling the judges’ discretion. From ancient roots of unrestrained discretion, the test for a preliminary injunction has evolved in recent decades from a sequential test of four supposedly binary conditions to the indefiniteness of a sliding-scale approach that balances the so-called four factors, back to a hopeless stab at crispness in the form of the alternatives test, which tries to state alternative c
本文旨在建立一个完整的决策法形式类型学。区分“规则”和“标准”是最常尝试的法理学界线,大致划分为非模糊和模糊。但是,对于规则/标准术语所在的维度,或者连续体的分界线在哪里,没有达成一致意见。因此,根据模糊性进行分类本身就是模糊的。最终,它不能帮助法律行为者制定或适用法律。这种分类最能唤起人们的共鸣。更明确的区分将有助于制定或适用法律。对于适用法律的人来说,如果明确地把重点放在立法者是否试图把事情确定下来,从而缩小自由裁量权的空间,将会更有用。如果它能帮助立法者思考如何把事情弄清楚,那就更有用了。这种更好的顶层区别在于二进制指令和标量指令之间的区别。如果指令包含一个或多个是/否条件的清单,那么它就是一个二进制指令。如果相反的指令要求考虑多价因素,它是一个标量指令。二元/标量是一种更好的分析区分。首先,二进制/标量是一个明确的区别。其次,这是一个明显的区别,代表了构成法律的各个组成部分之间的显著差异。第三,它告诉法律适用者,立法者是否试图把事情弄清楚。第四,它更好地传达了立法者对法律适用者的手头工具的感觉,从而使工具能够以最佳方式部署。第五,它允许绘制有意义的细分,将塑造法律的选择摆在前面:例如,标量指令的一个这样的子类型是一个真正的平衡测试,它明确或隐含地提出了一个可量化和可通约的考虑因素的详尽清单,以便彼此进行缩放和权衡,并提供了在任何必须表达为标量指令的法律的应用中检索控制的途径。附带地说,一个运行的例子来说明二进制/标量的优势来自禁令救济。临时限制令的检验标准是所谓的“不可弥补的损害”的二元条件,但在实践中,它已经瓦解了初步禁令的普遍检验标准。初步禁令检验标准的多样性揭示了在无限变化的情况下必要的灵活性与适当限制法官自由裁量权的需要之间的本质斗争。从不受限制的自由裁量权的古老根源出发,初步禁令的测试在最近几十年里已经从对四种所谓二元条件的连续测试演变为平衡所谓四种因素的滑动量表方法的不确定性,回到以替代测试的形式进行的无望的利落尝试,该测试试图陈述需要临时救济的情境事实的替代组合。最好的测试是一种系统化的标量指令——一种真正的平衡测试——它询问潜在的错误拒绝的预期成本是否超过潜在的错误授予初步禁令的预期成本。这种分析的现行规则/标准区分的不足之处在于,它很可能将所有相互竞争的初步禁令检验归为"标准"。总之,本文并不建议将规则/标准抛到一边作为对判决法进行分类的一种方式。相反,它建议采用二进制/标量作为定义规则和标准的方式。
{"title":"Rules, Standards, and Such","authors":"K. Clermont","doi":"10.31228/osf.io/n2kx3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31228/osf.io/n2kx3","url":null,"abstract":"This Article aims to create a complete typology of the forms of decisional law. Distinguishing “rules” from “standards” is the most commonly attempted jurisprudential line, roughly drawn between nonvague and vague. But no agreement exists on the dimension along which the rule/standard terminology lies, or on where the dividing line on the continuum lies. Thus, classifying in terms of vagueness is itself vague. Ultimately it does not aid legal actors in formulating or applying the law. The classification works best as an evocative image. A clearer distinction would be useful in formulating or applying the law. For the law-applier, it would be more useful if expressly focused on whether the law-giver was trying to pin things down and thus narrow the room for discretion. It would be even more useful if it had helped that law-giver to think about how to pin things down.This better top-level distinction lies between binary and scalar directives. If the directive comprises a checklist of one or more yes/no conditions, then it is a binary directive. If instead the directive calls for consideration of multivalent factors, it is a scalar directive. Binary/scalar is a superior distinction for analysis. First, binary/scalar is a clean distinction. Second, it is a telling distinction that represents a significant difference between the components that compose the law. Third, it tells the law-applier much about whether the law-giver tried to pin things down. Fourth, it conveys a better sense of the tools at hand for the law-giver’s pinning down the law-applier, and thus enables the tools’ deployment in an optimal way. Fifth, it allows the drawing of meaningful subdivisions that bring to the fore the choices in shaping that law: for example, one such subtype of scalar directives is a true balancing test, which explicitly or implicitly presents an exhaustive listing of quantifiable and commensurable considerations to be scaled and weighed against one another—and offers a route to retrieving control in the application of any law that has to be expressed as a scalar directive.Parenthetically, a running example to illustrate the superiority of binary/scalar comes from injunctive relief. The test for a temporary restraining order was the supposedly binary condition of “irreparable harm,” but it has disintegrated in practice to the prevailing test for a preliminary injunction. The diversity among the tests for preliminary injunctions reveals the essential struggle between the necessary flexibility for infinitely variable situations and the need for appropriately corralling the judges’ discretion. From ancient roots of unrestrained discretion, the test for a preliminary injunction has evolved in recent decades from a sequential test of four supposedly binary conditions to the indefiniteness of a sliding-scale approach that balances the so-called four factors, back to a hopeless stab at crispness in the form of the alternatives test, which tries to state alternative c","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"68 1","pages":"751"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2019-02-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42167819","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What the Judge Had for Breakfast: A Brief History of an Unpalatable Idea 法官早餐吃了什么:一个不愉快想法的简史
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2017-06-07 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2982716
Dan Priel
According to a familiar adage the legal realists equated law with what the judge had for breakfast. As this is sometimes used to ridicule the realists, prominent defenders of legal realism have countered that none of the realists ever entertained any such idea. In this short essay I show that this is inaccurate. References to this idea are found in the work of Karl Llewellyn and Jerome Frank, as well as in the works of their contemporaries, both friends and foes. However, the essay also shows that the idea is improperly attributed to the legal realists, as there are many references to it, in legal and non-legal sources, from long before the advent of legal realism. This suggests that the phrase has long reflected something of a received wisdom about adjudication. Tracing the question of the significance of digestion to one’s health, I argue that what we today take to be a humorous claim, may have been a much more serious one. For much of the nineteenth century it was widely believed that one’s health depended on one’s digestive health. Interestingly, this view is now once again taken seriously by scientists, which suggests that rather than scorn, the realists deserve credit for suggesting the question be studied seriously.
根据一个熟悉的格言,法律现实主义者将法律等同于法官早餐所吃的东西。由于这有时被用来嘲笑现实主义者,法律现实主义的著名捍卫者反驳说,没有一个现实主义者有过这样的想法。在这篇短文中,我指出这种说法是不准确的。在卡尔·卢埃林(Karl Llewellyn)和杰罗姆·弗兰克(Jerome Frank)的作品中,以及他们同时代人的作品中,无论是朋友还是敌人,都提到了这一观点。然而,这篇文章也表明,这一观点被不恰当地归因于法律现实主义者,因为在法律和非法律来源中,早在法律现实主义出现之前就有许多参考文献。这表明,这句话长期以来反映了某种关于裁决的公认智慧。追溯消化对健康的重要性这个问题,我认为,我们今天认为是幽默的说法,可能曾经是一个更严肃的问题。在19世纪的大部分时间里,人们普遍认为一个人的健康取决于他的消化系统健康。有趣的是,这种观点现在又一次被科学家们认真对待了,这表明,现实主义者建议认真研究这个问题,而不是蔑视,这值得赞扬。
{"title":"What the Judge Had for Breakfast: A Brief History of an Unpalatable Idea","authors":"Dan Priel","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2982716","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2982716","url":null,"abstract":"According to a familiar adage the legal realists equated law with what the judge had for breakfast. As this is sometimes used to ridicule the realists, prominent defenders of legal realism have countered that none of the realists ever entertained any such idea. In this short essay I show that this is inaccurate. References to this idea are found in the work of Karl Llewellyn and Jerome Frank, as well as in the works of their contemporaries, both friends and foes. However, the essay also shows that the idea is improperly attributed to the legal realists, as there are many references to it, in legal and non-legal sources, from long before the advent of legal realism. This suggests that the phrase has long reflected something of a received wisdom about adjudication. Tracing the question of the significance of digestion to one’s health, I argue that what we today take to be a humorous claim, may have been a much more serious one. For much of the nineteenth century it was widely believed that one’s health depended on one’s digestive health. Interestingly, this view is now once again taken seriously by scientists, which suggests that rather than scorn, the realists deserve credit for suggesting the question be studied seriously.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"68 1","pages":"899"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2017-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43095234","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Re-Reading Legal Realism and Tracing a Genealogy of Balancing 重新解读法律现实主义与平衡谱系的追溯
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2017-03-16 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2934539
Curtis Nyquist
The enclosed article offers a new understanding of the history of American legal thought. I developed this interpretation over twenty years as I read into the early twentieth century literature in jurisprudence. The conventional view holds that the Progressive Movement (1905-1923) and the Realist Movement (1923-1941) combined forces to attack and ultimately undermine Classical Legal Thought (1870-1920’s). Any differences between the progressives and the realists are seen as minor as compared with their joint effort to undermine Classical Thought. After reading the original literature I came to realize this standard approach is seriously flawed and a source of endless confusion in contemporary legal thought. Legal Realism was primarily a critique of progressive thought. Although the realists continued to assail the formalism of Classical Thought, their work is interesting and important because of their attack on the progressives. This attack was linked to a cognitive relativism in legal realism that parallels the profound changes in science and the arts in the 1920’s and 30’s. For example, an article from 1927 in an American Bar Association journal makes the following point: “[T]he old cosmic absolutes – absolute space, absolute time, absolute matter, absolute natural law, absolute truth – are gone. The reign of relativity . . . is destined to work a corresponding revolution, deep, noiseless it may be, but inevitable, in all the views and institutions of man.” This article also traces the genealogy of balancing. With the collapse of Classical Legal Thought, balancing became the predominant method of legal reasoning. The progressives and the realists held radically different views of balancing but, unfortunately, both used the same terms and it requires careful reading to untangle this history. The article distinguishes a teleological view of balancing, dominant in the progressive era and still the prevailing approach, and an attack on teleological balancing which the article calls “conflicting considerations.” One of the confusions in contemporary thought is the failure to recognize these two types of balancing. Many lawyers, judges, and scholars see only teleological balancing and fail to recognize the importance of the realists’ contribution to policy analysis.
随附的文章对美国法律思想史有了新的认识。20多年来,我在阅读20世纪初的法理学文献时,形成了这种解释。传统观点认为,进步运动(1905-1923)和现实主义运动(1923-1941)联手攻击并最终破坏了古典法律思想(1870-1920年代)。与他们共同破坏古典思想的努力相比,进步派和现实主义之间的任何分歧都被视为微不足道。在阅读了原始文献后,我意识到这种标准方法存在严重缺陷,是当代法律思想中无休止混乱的根源。法律现实主义主要是对进步思想的批判。尽管现实主义者继续抨击古典思想的形式主义,但他们的作品之所以有趣和重要,是因为他们攻击了进步主义者。这种攻击与法律现实主义中的认知相对主义有关,这种相对主义与20世纪20年代和30年代科学和艺术的深刻变化相似。例如1927年美国律师协会杂志上的一篇文章指出:“旧的宇宙绝对论——绝对空间、绝对时间、绝对物质、绝对自然法则、绝对真理——已经不复存在。相对论的统治……注定要进行一场相应的革命,在人类的所有观点和制度中,这可能是深刻的、无声的,但却是不可避免的。”也追溯了平衡的谱系。随着古典法律思想的崩溃,平衡成为法律推理的主要方法。进步派和现实主义者对平衡持截然不同的观点,但不幸的是,他们都使用了相同的术语,需要仔细阅读才能解开这段历史。文章区分了一种在进步时代占主导地位但仍然是主流的目的论平衡观,以及一种对目的论平衡的攻击,文章称之为“冲突的考虑”。当代思想的困惑之一是没有认识到这两种类型的平衡。许多律师、法官和学者只看到目的论的平衡,没有认识到现实主义者对政策分析的贡献的重要性。
{"title":"Re-Reading Legal Realism and Tracing a Genealogy of Balancing","authors":"Curtis Nyquist","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2934539","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2934539","url":null,"abstract":"The enclosed article offers a new understanding of the history of American legal thought. I developed this interpretation over twenty years as I read into the early twentieth century literature in jurisprudence. The conventional view holds that the Progressive Movement (1905-1923) and the Realist Movement (1923-1941) combined forces to attack and ultimately undermine Classical Legal Thought (1870-1920’s). Any differences between the progressives and the realists are seen as minor as compared with their joint effort to undermine Classical Thought. After reading the original literature I came to realize this standard approach is seriously flawed and a source of endless confusion in contemporary legal thought. \u0000Legal Realism was primarily a critique of progressive thought. Although the realists continued to assail the formalism of Classical Thought, their work is interesting and important because of their attack on the progressives. This attack was linked to a cognitive relativism in legal realism that parallels the profound changes in science and the arts in the 1920’s and 30’s. For example, an article from 1927 in an American Bar Association journal makes the following point: “[T]he old cosmic absolutes – absolute space, absolute time, absolute matter, absolute natural law, absolute truth – are gone. The reign of relativity . . . is destined to work a corresponding revolution, deep, noiseless it may be, but inevitable, in all the views and institutions of man.” \u0000This article also traces the genealogy of balancing. With the collapse of Classical Legal Thought, balancing became the predominant method of legal reasoning. The progressives and the realists held radically different views of balancing but, unfortunately, both used the same terms and it requires careful reading to untangle this history. The article distinguishes a teleological view of balancing, dominant in the progressive era and still the prevailing approach, and an attack on teleological balancing which the article calls “conflicting considerations.” One of the confusions in contemporary thought is the failure to recognize these two types of balancing. Many lawyers, judges, and scholars see only teleological balancing and fail to recognize the importance of the realists’ contribution to policy analysis.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"65 1","pages":"771"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2017-03-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44357293","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Causation, Legal History, and Legal Doctrine 因果关系、法律史和法律学说
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2016-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2714005
Charles L. Barzun
This short essay is my contribution to a conference on “opportunities for law’s intellectual history,” which took place at SUNY Buffalo Law School in the fall of 2014. The essay offers a friendly criticism of what I perceive to be a trend in legal history. In particular, it criticizes legal historians’ seemingly increasing reluctance to offer causal explanations of past events or current practices. While recognizing the empirical and conceptual difficulties that beset any effort to identify “causes” of historical events, I argue that legal history cannot effectively serve the critical function many historians hope for it without making controversial judgments about historical causation in particular cases. The bulk of the essay is devoted to identifying and analyzing four potentially critical types of history: Impeaching Accounts, Genealogies, Stories, and Restorative Projects. My aim in discussing each type is to show that critical histories that purport to remain agnostic as to the driving causal factors at work in the historical phenomena under examination are either insufficiently critical, insufficiently historical, or both.
这篇短文是我对2014年秋天在纽约州立大学布法罗法学院举行的“法律思想史机遇”会议的贡献。这篇文章对我所认为的法律史上的一种趋势提出了友好的批评。特别是,它批评了法律历史学家似乎越来越不愿意对过去的事件或当前的做法提供因果解释。虽然我认识到,任何试图确定历史事件“原因”的努力都存在经验和概念上的困难,但我认为,如果不对特定案例中的历史因果关系做出有争议的判断,法律史就无法有效地发挥许多历史学家所希望的批判功能。这篇文章的大部分都致力于识别和分析四种潜在的关键类型的历史:弹劾账户、家谱、故事和修复项目。我讨论每种类型的目的是为了表明,那些声称对所研究的历史现象中起作用的驱动因果因素保持不可知论的批判历史要么是不够批判性的,要么是不够历史性的,或者两者兼而有之。
{"title":"Causation, Legal History, and Legal Doctrine","authors":"Charles L. Barzun","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2714005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2714005","url":null,"abstract":"This short essay is my contribution to a conference on “opportunities for law’s intellectual history,” which took place at SUNY Buffalo Law School in the fall of 2014. The essay offers a friendly criticism of what I perceive to be a trend in legal history. In particular, it criticizes legal historians’ seemingly increasing reluctance to offer causal explanations of past events or current practices. While recognizing the empirical and conceptual difficulties that beset any effort to identify “causes” of historical events, I argue that legal history cannot effectively serve the critical function many historians hope for it without making controversial judgments about historical causation in particular cases. The bulk of the essay is devoted to identifying and analyzing four potentially critical types of history: Impeaching Accounts, Genealogies, Stories, and Restorative Projects. My aim in discussing each type is to show that critical histories that purport to remain agnostic as to the driving causal factors at work in the historical phenomena under examination are either insufficiently critical, insufficiently historical, or both.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"64 1","pages":"81"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68268010","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Decline of the Lawyer Politician 律师政治家的衰落
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2015-11-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2684731
N. Robinson
While the ubiquity of lawyers in U.S. electoral politics is well known, there has been almost no research on how their prevalence has changed over time, why these changes might have occurred, or the consequences of any such shift. This article helps address these gaps. Using a unique data set that extends over two hundred years of the occupational background of members of the U.S. Congress, it confirms widespread perceptions that lawyers have long dominated Congress. However, it also finds that this dominance is in slow, but steady, retreat. In the mid-19th century almost 80% of members were lawyers. By the 1960s this had dropped to under 60%, and by 2015 it was less than 40%. The article puts forward a set of arguments about why lawyers have traditionally had such success in U.S. electoral politics, including their affinity for lawmaking, the politicization of the U.S. justice system, and advantages in terms of career flexibility and access to resources. It claims lawyers’ electoral decline is largely the result of changes within the legal profession as well as new electoral competition, particularly from an emerging professionalized political class comprised of political aides and members of civil society that have made politics a career. The article argues lawyers’ prevalence in Congress has had at least three effects. First, it has impacted Congressional outcomes. While lawyer legislators generally have similar voting records as other members, evidence is presented here for the first time that members of the House of Representatives who are lawyers have been more likely to support the funding of civil legal aid, potentially pointing to a larger set of behavioral differences between lawyer and non-lawyer legislators, especially in their approach to policies related to the legal system. Second, law, as a “gateway” occupation into politics, has affected Congressional diversity. The article presents new evidence that lawyer members of Congress have historically been less likely to be women, indicating that the hurdles women have faced in law have possibly reduced their representation in Congress. Third, lawyers’ prevalence in Congress has impacted the legal profession and the larger legal system. Lawyers’ decline in Congress, and politics more generally, has likely reduced the number of politically oriented students who enter law and contributed to perceptions that the profession has become less civic-minded. The even more precipitous decline in Congress of former judges may be helping depoliticize the judiciary even more quickly than the bar. The article concludes by claiming that law schools and the profession need to more actively address diversity challenges as well as provide better training in leadership if they want lawyers to remain central to and be as positive a force as possible in electoral politics in the United States.
虽然律师在美国选举政治中的无处不在是众所周知的,但几乎没有研究表明,随着时间的推移,他们的普及程度是如何变化的,为什么会发生这些变化,或者任何这种变化的后果。本文有助于解决这些差距。该报告使用了一套独特的数据集,涵盖了美国国会议员200多年的职业背景,证实了律师长期以来主导国会的普遍看法。然而,它也发现这种主导地位正在缓慢但稳定地退却。在19世纪中期,几乎80%的会员是律师。到20世纪60年代,这一比例降至60%以下,到2015年,这一比例不到40%。这篇文章提出了一系列关于为什么律师传统上在美国选举政治中取得如此成功的论点,包括他们对立法的亲和力,美国司法系统的政治化,以及在职业灵活性和获取资源方面的优势。报告称,律师在选举中的下降主要是由于法律职业内部的变化以及新的选举竞争,特别是来自新兴的专业化政治阶层的竞争,这些政治阶层由政治助手和公民社会成员组成,他们把政治作为一种职业。文章认为律师在国会的盛行至少有三个影响。首先,它影响了国会的结果。虽然律师议员通常与其他议员有相似的投票记录,但这里首次提出的证据表明,律师出身的众议院议员更有可能支持为民事法律援助提供资金,这可能表明律师和非律师议员之间存在更大的行为差异,特别是在他们对法律制度相关政策的态度上。其次,法律作为进入政治的“门户”,影响了国会的多样性。这篇文章提出了新的证据,表明从历史上看,国会的律师成员中女性的可能性较小,这表明女性在法律上面临的障碍可能减少了她们在国会的代表性。第三,律师在国会的盛行影响了法律职业和更大的法律体系。律师在国会中的地位下降,更广泛地说,政治倾向的学生进入法律界的人数可能会减少,并导致人们认为这个职业变得不那么具有公民意识。国会中前法官人数的急剧下降可能比律师协会更快地帮助司法去政治化。文章最后声称,如果他们希望律师在美国的选举政治中保持核心地位,并尽可能成为积极的力量,法学院和律师行业需要更积极地应对多样性挑战,并提供更好的领导力培训。
{"title":"The Decline of the Lawyer Politician","authors":"N. Robinson","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2684731","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2684731","url":null,"abstract":"While the ubiquity of lawyers in U.S. electoral politics is well known, there has been almost no research on how their prevalence has changed over time, why these changes might have occurred, or the consequences of any such shift. This article helps address these gaps. Using a unique data set that extends over two hundred years of the occupational background of members of the U.S. Congress, it confirms widespread perceptions that lawyers have long dominated Congress. However, it also finds that this dominance is in slow, but steady, retreat. In the mid-19th century almost 80% of members were lawyers. By the 1960s this had dropped to under 60%, and by 2015 it was less than 40%. The article puts forward a set of arguments about why lawyers have traditionally had such success in U.S. electoral politics, including their affinity for lawmaking, the politicization of the U.S. justice system, and advantages in terms of career flexibility and access to resources. It claims lawyers’ electoral decline is largely the result of changes within the legal profession as well as new electoral competition, particularly from an emerging professionalized political class comprised of political aides and members of civil society that have made politics a career. The article argues lawyers’ prevalence in Congress has had at least three effects. First, it has impacted Congressional outcomes. While lawyer legislators generally have similar voting records as other members, evidence is presented here for the first time that members of the House of Representatives who are lawyers have been more likely to support the funding of civil legal aid, potentially pointing to a larger set of behavioral differences between lawyer and non-lawyer legislators, especially in their approach to policies related to the legal system. Second, law, as a “gateway” occupation into politics, has affected Congressional diversity. The article presents new evidence that lawyer members of Congress have historically been less likely to be women, indicating that the hurdles women have faced in law have possibly reduced their representation in Congress. Third, lawyers’ prevalence in Congress has impacted the legal profession and the larger legal system. Lawyers’ decline in Congress, and politics more generally, has likely reduced the number of politically oriented students who enter law and contributed to perceptions that the profession has become less civic-minded. The even more precipitous decline in Congress of former judges may be helping depoliticize the judiciary even more quickly than the bar. The article concludes by claiming that law schools and the profession need to more actively address diversity challenges as well as provide better training in leadership if they want lawyers to remain central to and be as positive a force as possible in electoral politics in the United States.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"65 1","pages":"657"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2015-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2684731","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68254393","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Remedial Discretion in Constitutional Adjudication 宪法裁决中的补救自由裁量权
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2014-02-17 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2305629
John M. Greabe
Courts frequently withhold remedies for meritorious assertions of constitutional right. The practice is often unobjectionable. Indeed, it is a systemic necessity if constitutional law is to remain vibrant. Without it, judges surely would be less inclined to engage in constitutional innovation. But just as surely, the practice is not available for all types of constitutional claim. For instance, the subject of a criminal indictment is always entitled to dismissal of the charges if the statute authorizing the prosecution is unconstitutional. The Supreme Court has experimented with various approaches to withholding constitutional remedies. The Warren Court embraced the practice of issuing non-retroactive constitutional rulings as it recognized new criminal constitutional rights. But the Burger and Rehnquist Courts rejected non-retroactivity. Instead, they enforced forfeiture rules and significantly broadened the reach of remedy-limiting doctrines such as qualified immunity, harmless error, and exceptions to the exclusionary rule. The Roberts Court has continued in the same vein. Unfortunately, however, the Court’s shift away from non-retroactivity has been unaccompanied by any trans-substantive account of when and how courts may withhold constitutional remedies. As a consequence, influential commentators have charged the Court with inconsistency; they say that it is incoherent to discard non-retroactivity while expanding doctrines that accomplish the same thing. These commentators have called for a revival of non-retroactivity doctrine to enable more constitutional innovation. This paper argues against reviving non-retroactivity doctrine and proposes a functional framework for evaluating when and how courts may withhold constitutional remedies. The proposal differentiates between substitutionary remedies addressed to wholly concluded constitutional wrongs, which courts sometimes may withhold, and specific remedies addressed to ongoing violations, which are obligatory. The proposal rationalizes the Court’s recent remedial practices in constitutional adjudication, permits a context-specific balancing of remedial interests in cases where such a balancing is appropriate, and accounts for separation-of-powers and federalism concerns. It thus provides concrete guidance on when courts may withhold constitutional remedies and when they may not. It also respects Article III limits on judicial power — limits that non-retroactivity doctrines exceed.
法院经常拒绝对值得称道的宪法权利主张进行救济。这种做法通常是无可非议的。事实上,如果宪法要保持活力,这是一个系统性的必要条件。没有它,法官们肯定不太愿意参与宪法改革。但同样可以肯定的是,这种做法并非适用于所有类型的宪法主张。例如,如果授权起诉的法规违反宪法,刑事起诉的主体总是有权撤销指控。最高法院已经尝试了各种方法来阻止宪法救济。沃伦法院接受了发布不溯及既往的宪法裁决的做法,因为它承认新的刑事宪法权利。但伯格和伦奎斯特法院驳回了不溯及力。相反,他们执行没收规则,并大大扩大了补救限制理论的范围,如有条件豁免、无害错误和排除规则的例外。罗伯茨法院继续以同样的方式行事。然而,不幸的是,法院在改变不溯及既往的原则时,并没有对法院何时以及如何拒绝宪法救济作出任何跨实质的说明。结果,有影响力的评论员指责法院前后不一;他们说,在扩大达到同样目的的学说的同时,抛弃非溯及性是不连贯的。这些评论家呼吁恢复非溯及性原则,以实现更多的宪法创新。本文反对恢复不溯及既往原则,并提出了一个评估法院何时以及如何保留宪法救济的功能框架。该提案区分了针对完全结案的宪法错误的替代补救措施,法院有时可能会拒绝这种补救措施,以及针对正在进行的违法行为的具体补救措施,这是强制性的。这项建议合理化了法院最近在宪法裁决中的补救做法,允许在适当的情况下根据具体情况平衡补救利益,并考虑到三权分立和联邦制问题。因此,它就法院何时可以不采取宪法补救措施以及何时可以不采取这种措施提供了具体指导。它也尊重第三条对司法权的限制——不溯及既往原则所超越的限制。
{"title":"Remedial Discretion in Constitutional Adjudication","authors":"John M. Greabe","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2305629","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2305629","url":null,"abstract":"Courts frequently withhold remedies for meritorious assertions of constitutional right. The practice is often unobjectionable. Indeed, it is a systemic necessity if constitutional law is to remain vibrant. Without it, judges surely would be less inclined to engage in constitutional innovation. But just as surely, the practice is not available for all types of constitutional claim. For instance, the subject of a criminal indictment is always entitled to dismissal of the charges if the statute authorizing the prosecution is unconstitutional. The Supreme Court has experimented with various approaches to withholding constitutional remedies. The Warren Court embraced the practice of issuing non-retroactive constitutional rulings as it recognized new criminal constitutional rights. But the Burger and Rehnquist Courts rejected non-retroactivity. Instead, they enforced forfeiture rules and significantly broadened the reach of remedy-limiting doctrines such as qualified immunity, harmless error, and exceptions to the exclusionary rule. The Roberts Court has continued in the same vein. Unfortunately, however, the Court’s shift away from non-retroactivity has been unaccompanied by any trans-substantive account of when and how courts may withhold constitutional remedies. As a consequence, influential commentators have charged the Court with inconsistency; they say that it is incoherent to discard non-retroactivity while expanding doctrines that accomplish the same thing. These commentators have called for a revival of non-retroactivity doctrine to enable more constitutional innovation. This paper argues against reviving non-retroactivity doctrine and proposes a functional framework for evaluating when and how courts may withhold constitutional remedies. The proposal differentiates between substitutionary remedies addressed to wholly concluded constitutional wrongs, which courts sometimes may withhold, and specific remedies addressed to ongoing violations, which are obligatory. The proposal rationalizes the Court’s recent remedial practices in constitutional adjudication, permits a context-specific balancing of remedial interests in cases where such a balancing is appropriate, and accounts for separation-of-powers and federalism concerns. It thus provides concrete guidance on when courts may withhold constitutional remedies and when they may not. It also respects Article III limits on judicial power — limits that non-retroactivity doctrines exceed.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"62 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2014-02-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2305629","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68081130","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Presidential Politics as a Safeguard of Federalism: The Case of Marijuana Legalization 总统政治作为联邦制的保障:以大麻合法化为例
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2013-09-16 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2326688
David S. Schwartz
The longstanding debate over the political versus judicial safeguards of federalism has paid insufficient attention to the role presidential politics might play in promoting state policy-making autonomy. In certain circumstances, the President may be better positioned than either the courts or Congress to be politically sensitive to state policy initiatives and to create the flexibilities in federal law necessary to accommodate them. A powerful example of this dynamic is presented by the problem of state marijuana legalization. A sharp policy conflict has arisen between the federal Controlled Substances Act, which purports to impose a zero-tolerance regime on marijuana distribution and use, and state laws permitting distribution and use of marijuana for medical and, more recently, recreational purposes. While the courts and Congress have played virtually no role in permitting such state policy experiments to go forward, the Obama administration's low key approach toward enforcing the CSA's marijuana ban in marijuana legalization states has created space for state level policy experiments. The article argues that the Obama administration's position reflects political sensitivity to the policy preferences of a small number of marijuana legalization states that play an outsized role in presidential "electoral math." The marijuana legalization example provides strong evidence that presidential politics can be a significant political safeguard of federalism where a grouping of "swing states" has a salient policy preference that is inconsistent with a well-supported national policy alternative in an era of close presidential elections.
关于联邦制的政治与司法保障的长期争论,对总统政治在促进国家决策自治方面可能发挥的作用关注不足。在某些情况下,总统可能比法院或国会更能在政治上敏感于州的政策举措,并在联邦法律中创造必要的灵活性来适应它们。这种动态的一个有力例子是各州大麻合法化的问题。联邦《管制物质法》(Controlled Substances Act)意在对大麻的分销和使用实行零容忍制度,而州法律则允许大麻的分销和使用用于医疗目的,最近还允许用于娱乐目的。虽然法院和国会在允许此类州政策试验向前推进方面几乎没有发挥任何作用,但奥巴马政府在大麻合法化州执行CSA大麻禁令方面的低调态度,为州一级的政策试验创造了空间。文章认为,奥巴马政府的立场反映了对少数大麻合法化州的政策偏好的政治敏感性,这些州在总统“选举数学”中发挥着巨大的作用。大麻合法化的例子提供了强有力的证据,证明总统政治可以成为联邦制的重要政治保障,因为在一个势不两立的总统选举时代,一群“摇摆州”有明显的政策偏好,这与得到广泛支持的国家政策选择不一致。
{"title":"Presidential Politics as a Safeguard of Federalism: The Case of Marijuana Legalization","authors":"David S. Schwartz","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2326688","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2326688","url":null,"abstract":"The longstanding debate over the political versus judicial safeguards of federalism has paid insufficient attention to the role presidential politics might play in promoting state policy-making autonomy. In certain circumstances, the President may be better positioned than either the courts or Congress to be politically sensitive to state policy initiatives and to create the flexibilities in federal law necessary to accommodate them. A powerful example of this dynamic is presented by the problem of state marijuana legalization. A sharp policy conflict has arisen between the federal Controlled Substances Act, which purports to impose a zero-tolerance regime on marijuana distribution and use, and state laws permitting distribution and use of marijuana for medical and, more recently, recreational purposes. While the courts and Congress have played virtually no role in permitting such state policy experiments to go forward, the Obama administration's low key approach toward enforcing the CSA's marijuana ban in marijuana legalization states has created space for state level policy experiments. The article argues that the Obama administration's position reflects political sensitivity to the policy preferences of a small number of marijuana legalization states that play an outsized role in presidential \"electoral math.\" The marijuana legalization example provides strong evidence that presidential politics can be a significant political safeguard of federalism where a grouping of \"swing states\" has a salient policy preference that is inconsistent with a well-supported national policy alternative in an era of close presidential elections.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"62 1","pages":"599"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2013-09-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2326688","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68106448","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Norm Supercompliance and the Status of Soft Law 规范超越性与软法的地位
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2013-09-02 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2319557
Brian Sheppard
Recent empirical research, including my own, has exposed a previously overlooked behavior: instances in which people constrain themselves from doing something that they want to do because they believe a norm obligates them to do so, even though the norm in question does not, on a straightforward reading, contain such an obligation. I label this phenomenon “Norm Supercompliance.” Simply put, Supercompliers treat soft norms as if they are hard norms. For example, one who grudgingly complies with an aspirational norm, such as “a lawyer should aspire to render at least 50 hours of pro bono service per year” on the belief that it states an obligation is a Supercomplier. There is a vast literature in which authors assert that norms in legal contexts that possess certain weak or soft qualities — “soft laws” — do not deserve legal status because such norms fail to make a practical difference to the deliberation of those subject to them. This assertion unduly ignores or undervalues Supercompliance; as those engaging in it experience considerable changes in their decision-making when they follow soft law. While it is easy to write off Supercompliance as a self-defeating or masochistic mistake, it has the capacity to benefit those engaging in it, allowing them to reap the same rewards that come from accepting legal obligation under ordinary circumstances. In this Article, I set forth the elements of Supercompliance in detail, provide examples from the empirical literature in which those elements have been satisfied, and discuss the theoretical and practical implications thereof. In particular, I focus on how the discovery of this behavior might weaken arguments in support of Exclusive Legal Positivism. Illuminating the value of Supercompliance and, in turn, soft law, will give legislators a better sense of the tools at their disposal that can bring about improved behavior. It will help them build better legal norms.
最近的实证研究,包括我自己的研究,揭示了一种以前被忽视的行为:人们约束自己不去做他们想做的事情,因为他们认为有一种规范要求他们这样做,尽管在简单的解读中,所讨论的规范并不包含这种义务。我把这种现象称为“规范超遵从性”。简单地说,超级编译者把软规范当作硬规范来对待。例如,一个不情愿地遵守一个理想规范的人,比如“律师应该立志每年提供至少50小时的无偿服务”,因为他认为这是一种义务,他就是一个超级编译者。在大量的文献中,作者断言,在法律环境中,具有某些软弱或软品质的规范——“软法律”——不值得拥有法律地位,因为这些规范不能对受其约束的人的审议产生实际的影响。这种说法不恰当地忽视或低估了“超规性”;当这些人遵循软法律时,他们的决策经历了相当大的变化。虽然人们很容易将“超级合规”视为一种自我挫败或自虐的错误,但它有能力让参与其中的人受益,让他们获得在普通情况下接受法律义务所带来的同样回报。在本文中,我详细阐述了超合规性的要素,从经验文献中提供了满足这些要素的例子,并讨论了其理论和实践意义。我特别关注这种行为的发现如何削弱支持排他性法律实证主义的论点。阐明Supercompliance的价值,进而阐明软法律的价值,将使立法者更好地了解他们可以使用的工具,这些工具可以改善行为。这将有助于他们建立更好的法律规范。
{"title":"Norm Supercompliance and the Status of Soft Law","authors":"Brian Sheppard","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2319557","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2319557","url":null,"abstract":"Recent empirical research, including my own, has exposed a previously overlooked behavior: instances in which people constrain themselves from doing something that they want to do because they believe a norm obligates them to do so, even though the norm in question does not, on a straightforward reading, contain such an obligation. I label this phenomenon “Norm Supercompliance.” Simply put, Supercompliers treat soft norms as if they are hard norms. For example, one who grudgingly complies with an aspirational norm, such as “a lawyer should aspire to render at least 50 hours of pro bono service per year” on the belief that it states an obligation is a Supercomplier. There is a vast literature in which authors assert that norms in legal contexts that possess certain weak or soft qualities — “soft laws” — do not deserve legal status because such norms fail to make a practical difference to the deliberation of those subject to them. This assertion unduly ignores or undervalues Supercompliance; as those engaging in it experience considerable changes in their decision-making when they follow soft law. While it is easy to write off Supercompliance as a self-defeating or masochistic mistake, it has the capacity to benefit those engaging in it, allowing them to reap the same rewards that come from accepting legal obligation under ordinary circumstances. In this Article, I set forth the elements of Supercompliance in detail, provide examples from the empirical literature in which those elements have been satisfied, and discuss the theoretical and practical implications thereof. In particular, I focus on how the discovery of this behavior might weaken arguments in support of Exclusive Legal Positivism. Illuminating the value of Supercompliance and, in turn, soft law, will give legislators a better sense of the tools at their disposal that can bring about improved behavior. It will help them build better legal norms.","PeriodicalId":51843,"journal":{"name":"Buffalo Law Review","volume":"62 1","pages":"787"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2013-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68100116","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
期刊
Buffalo Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1