首页 > 最新文献

JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
Ethical Causality and Rebirth in the Pātañjalayogaśāstra and Abhidharmakośabhās A3B2 tvs=1mm h-1.7 . h0.7 A3B2 tvs ya: A Mirrored Argument Pātañjalayogaśāstra 和 Abhidharmakośabhās A3B2 tvs=1mm h-1.7 .h0.7 A3B2 tvs ya:镜像论证
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-09-17 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09574-8
Karen O’Brien-Kop

This paper focuses on Sāṃkhya-Yoga and Buddhist Abhidharma ontologies and their engagement. A close reading of two hitherto uncompared passages from Pātañjalayogaśāstra 2.13 and Vasubandhu’s Abhidharmakośabhāṣya 4.94 suggests that they are intertextual or interdiscursive. A mirrored argument form in the texts explains ethical causality (karma) in relation to rebirth (punarjanman). The arguments in both texts are similar in form, sequence, and even conclusion, although not in terms of the doctrinal basis of reasoning. On first examination, both arguments analyse how action (karma) sustains patterns of moral repercussion across life and beyond death in terms of singular and plural causes and effects. But a close reading shows that the level of conceptual engagement on this issue is more nuanced – centred on ‘projecting’ and ‘completing’ mechanisms of karmic retribution (ākṣepaka karman and paripūraka karman) as well as determinate or indeterminate (niyata and aniyata) maturation of karmic effects. The paper suggests that the function of Patañjali’s passage was to serve as a structured engagement with Buddhist Sarvāstivāda karma theory.

本文重点探讨萨迦瑜伽与佛教阿毗达磨本体论及其联系。通过细读 Pātañjalayogaśāstra 2.13 和 Vasubandhu 的 Abhidharmakośabhāṣya 4.94 这两段迄今为止尚未对比过的经文,我们发现它们是互文或互涉的。文本中的一个镜像论证形式解释了与重生(punarjanman)相关的伦理因果关系(业力)。两个文本中的论证在形式、顺序甚至结论上都很相似,但在推理的教义基础上却不尽相同。初看之下,这两个论点都从单数和复数因果关系的角度分析了行为(业力)如何在生前和死后维持道德反响的模式。但仔细阅读后会发现,在这一问题上,概念层面的参与更为细微--集中于业力报应的 "投射 "和 "完成 "机制(ākṣepaka karman 和 paripūraka karman),以及业力效应的确定或不确定(niyata 和 aniyata)成熟。本文认为,帕绷伽利这段话的作用是作为对佛教 Sarvāstivāda 因果报应理论的结构性参与。
{"title":"Ethical Causality and Rebirth in the Pātañjalayogaśāstra and Abhidharmakośabhās A3B2 tvs=1mm h-1.7 . h0.7 A3B2 tvs ya: A Mirrored Argument","authors":"Karen O’Brien-Kop","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09574-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09574-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper focuses on Sāṃkhya-Yoga and Buddhist Abhidharma ontologies and their engagement. A close reading of two hitherto uncompared passages from <i>Pātañjalayogaśāstra</i> 2.13 and Vasubandhu’s <i>Abhidharmakośabhāṣya</i> 4.94 suggests that they are intertextual or interdiscursive. A mirrored argument form in the texts explains ethical causality (karma) in relation to rebirth (<i>punarjanman</i>). The arguments in both texts are similar in form, sequence, and even conclusion, although not in terms of the doctrinal basis of reasoning. On first examination, both arguments analyse how action (karma) sustains patterns of moral repercussion across life and beyond death in terms of singular and plural causes and effects. But a close reading shows that the level of conceptual engagement on this issue is more nuanced – centred on ‘projecting’ and ‘completing’ mechanisms of karmic retribution (<i>ākṣepaka karman</i> and <i>paripūraka karman</i>) as well as determinate or indeterminate (<i>niyata</i> and <i>aniyata</i>) maturation of karmic effects. The paper suggests that the function of Patañjali’s passage was to serve as a structured engagement with Buddhist Sarvāstivāda karma theory.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-09-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142252219","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Divine Favour and Human Gratitude: A Study of Vedānta Deśikaṉ’s Upakārasaṅgraham 神的恩惠与人的感恩:吠檀多-德希卡(Vedānta Deśikaṉ)的《乌帕卡拉萨(Upakārasaṅgraham)》研究
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-09-13 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09580-w
Suganya Anandakichenin

Among the many works that Vedānta Deśikaṉ—(traditional dates: 1268-1369), a most eminent theologian of all times—composed in his lifetime, his minor works—thirty in number and collectively known as the Cillaṟai rahasyam (‘miscellaneous esoterica’)—stand out like guides meant to help those eager Śrīvaiṣṇavas who lack time to deepen their knowledge of Viśiṣṭādvaita by the study of longer and deeper texts. One such rahasyam is the Upakārasaṅgraham, in which Deśikaṉ deals (almost exhaustively) with the theme of God’s countless acts of upakāra (‘aid, help, favour’) upon the individual souls. This beneficence of God’s forms the very basis of Viśiṣṭādvaita, as it involves a discussion of one the three tattvas (‘realities’), namely, God, (and by extension, the sentient entity), as well as on mokṣa (‘liberation’), which is the ultimate aim of the Śrīvaiṣṇava Ācāryas. In this article, which is ultimately meant to introduce to the reader an important but little-known text, I shall explore the topic of infinite divine upakāra as elaborated upon by Vedānta Deśikaṉ in his Upakārasaṅgraham, which, according to this text, ought to inspire human gratitude. And in the process, we shall also examine the nature and object(s) of God’s acts of upakāra, and the means through which He proceeds to bestow them.

吠檀多-德希卡(Vedānta Deśikaṉ,传统写作年代:1268-1369 年)是古代最杰出的神学家,在他一生创作的众多作品中,他的次要作品有 30 部,统称为《西拉ṟ艾拉赫》:1268-1369 年)--一位最杰出的神学家-- 在他的一生中创作了许多作品,其中有 30 部次要作品,统称为 "杂密"(Cillaṟai rahasyam),它们就像指南一样,可以帮助那些没有时间通过研究更长、更深的文本来加深对唯识知识的了解的渴望者。乌帕卡拉萨》(Upakārasaṅgraham)就是这样一部经书,在这部经书中,德希卡(Deśikaṉ)(几乎详尽无遗地)论述了上帝对个体灵魂的无数乌帕卡拉("援助、帮助、恩惠")行为。神的这种恩惠构成了唯识学的基础,因为它涉及到对三塔瓦("实相")之一,即神(以及有情实体)和 mokṣa("解脱")的讨论,而 mokṣa 是圣十字会的终极目标。本文的最终目的是向读者介绍一篇重要但鲜为人知的文章,我将探讨吠檀多-德希卡在其《乌帕卡拉萨ṅ格拉哈姆》中阐述的无限神圣的乌帕卡拉(upakāra)这一主题,根据这篇文章,乌帕卡拉应该激发人类的感激之情。在此过程中,我们还将研究神的乌帕卡拉行为的性质和目的,以及神赐予这些行为的手段。
{"title":"Divine Favour and Human Gratitude: A Study of Vedānta Deśikaṉ’s Upakārasaṅgraham","authors":"Suganya Anandakichenin","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09580-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09580-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Among the many works that Vedānta Deśikaṉ—(traditional dates: 1268-1369), a most eminent theologian of all times—composed in his lifetime, his minor works—thirty in number and collectively known as the <i>Cillaṟai rahasyam</i> (‘miscellaneous esoterica’)—stand out like guides meant to help those eager Śrīvaiṣṇavas who lack time to deepen their knowledge of Viśiṣṭādvaita by the study of longer and deeper texts. One such <i>rahasyam</i> is the <i>Upakārasaṅgraham</i>, in which Deśikaṉ deals (almost exhaustively) with the theme of God’s countless acts of <i>upakāra</i> (‘aid, help, favour’) upon the individual souls. This beneficence of God’s forms the very basis of Viśiṣṭādvaita, as it involves a discussion of one the three <i>tattvas</i> (‘realities’), namely, God, (and by extension, the sentient entity), as well as on <i>mokṣa</i> (‘liberation’), which is the ultimate aim of the Śrīvaiṣṇava Ācāryas. In this article, which is ultimately meant to introduce to the reader an important but little-known text, I shall explore the topic of infinite divine <i>upakāra</i> as elaborated upon by Vedānta Deśikaṉ in his <i>Upakārasaṅgraham</i>, which, according to this text, ought to inspire human gratitude. And in the process, we shall also examine the nature and object(s) of God’s acts of <i>upakāra</i>, and the means through which He proceeds to bestow them.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-09-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142193878","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Māyājāla-sūtra: A Canonical Proto-Yogācāra Sūtra? Māyājāla-sūtra: A Canonical Proto-Yogācāra Sūtra?
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-08-16 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09567-7
Gleb Sharygin

In our study of the development of Buddhist ideas over time, one of the major problems is the absence of the links, connecting different strata, strands or schools of the Buddhist thought. Perhaps, the most extreme example of this is the origin of the Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda tradition, a complex teaching that emerged almost “full-grown” in the Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra. Our knowledge of the historical antecedents of Yogācāra is very scarce and, what concerns the school Sautrāntika/Dārṣṭāntika, contradictory. The Māyājāla-sūtra very likely reveals important details regarding the very origin of the Yogācāra tradition and is, therefore, a long-sought-for source. Māyājāla-sūtra is a sūtra in the recently recovered Sanskrit Dīrgha-āgama. It stands out from the other Dīrgha-āgama sūtras by its diction and unique compositional and doctrinal features. One of its unique features is that its core terminology, its passages and similes are used extensively in the Sautrāntika-Dārṣṭāntika-Yogācāra sources, especially in the Yogācārabhūmi and the Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra. In the article, I summarize the sūtra, overview these features and show that the central message of the sūtra is the so-called darśana-mārga, a path of seeing, which is accompanied by supramundane insight (lokottara-prajñā), which enables a Buddhist adept to directly perceive the true reality and become an ārya, noble person. I argue that this central idea of the sūtra is textually and doctrinally (or philosophically) interwoven with the specifically Yogācāra understanding of the darśana-mārga. Moreover, I show that one of the main ideas of the sūtra, the ambivalence of the sense objects, realized at the darśana-mārga, is likely an antecedent of the specifically Yogācāra teaching on the possibility of the same object to cause opposite types of experience, and, as such, an antecedent of the cornerstone Yogācāra principle of vijñaptimātratā (the teaching that the objects of perception are mere representations of/in the mind). Another important aspect explored in this paper is the intertextuality of the Māyājāla-sūtra, its parallels and the first chapters of the Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra, which sheds important light on the origin of the latter text. I argue that these parallels to the Yogācāra teachings are, at the very least, their earlier precedents, and, because of that the Māyājāla-sūtra may be called a proto-Yogācāra sūtra.

在我们研究佛教思想的长期发展过程中,一个主要问题是缺乏将佛教思想的不同阶层、分支或流派联系起来的纽带。也许,最极端的例子就是《瑜伽师地论》-《维摩诘所说经》(Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda)传统的起源,这一复杂的教义在《萨迦耶跋摩经论》中几乎 "完全成熟"。我们对瑜伽行派历史前身的了解非常有限,而且与 "菩提流支"(Sautrāntika/Dārṣṭāntika)学派有关的知识也相互矛盾。Māyājāla-sūtra 很有可能揭示了有关瑜伽行派传统起源的重要细节,因此是人们长期以来一直在寻找的资料来源。Māyājāla-sūtra 是最近修复的梵文 Dīrgha-āgama 中的一部经文。与其他 Dīrgha-āgama 经不同的是,它的用词和独特的构成与教义特征。其独特之处之一是,其核心术语、段落和譬喻被广泛用于 Sautrāntika-Dārṣāntika-Yogācāra 资料中,尤其是在《瑜伽师地论》和《萨ṃdhinirmocana-sūtra》中。在这篇文章中,我总结了经文,概述了这些特点,并说明经文的中心思想是所谓的 darśana-mārga(见道),它伴随着超世俗的洞察力(lokottara-prajñā),使佛教信徒能够直接感知真实的实相,成为高尚的人(ārya)。我认为,《瑜伽师地论》的这一核心思想在文本和教义(或哲学)上与《瑜伽师地论》对 "达磨"(darśana-mārga)的具体理解交织在一起。此外,我还指出,在达希那摩迦(darśana-mārga)悟到的《瑜伽师地论》的主要思想之一--感官对象的矛盾性--很可能是专门的瑜伽教义的前身,即同一对象有可能引起相反类型的体验,因此也是瑜伽教义的基石--"知觉对象只是心的表象"(vijñaptimātratā)原则的前身。本文探讨的另一个重要方面是《摩耶迦罗经》、其相似之处以及《萨迦毗尼摩柯那经》前几章的互文性,这为后一文本的起源提供了重要的启示。我认为,这些与《瑜伽师地论》相似的教义至少是其早期的先例,正因为如此,《摩耶迦罗经》可被称为原《瑜伽师地论》。
{"title":"Māyājāla-sūtra: A Canonical Proto-Yogācāra Sūtra?","authors":"Gleb Sharygin","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09567-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09567-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In our study of the development of Buddhist ideas over time, one of the major problems is the absence of the links, connecting different strata, strands or schools of the Buddhist thought. Perhaps, the most extreme example of this is the origin of the Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda tradition, a complex teaching that emerged almost “full-grown” in the <i>Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra</i>. Our knowledge of the historical antecedents of Yogācāra is very scarce and, what concerns the school Sautrāntika/Dārṣṭāntika, contradictory. The <i>Māyājāla-sūtra</i> very likely reveals important details regarding the very origin of the Yogācāra tradition and is, therefore, a long-sought-for source. <i>Māyājāla-sūtra</i> is a <i>sūtra</i> in the recently recovered Sanskrit <i>Dīrgha-āgama</i>. It stands out from the other <i>Dīrgha-āgama sūtras</i> by its diction and unique compositional and doctrinal features. One of its unique features is that its core terminology, its passages and similes are used extensively in the Sautrāntika-Dārṣṭāntika-Yogācāra sources, especially in the <i>Yogācārabhūmi</i> and the <i>Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra</i>. In the article, I summarize the <i>sūtra</i>, overview these features and show that the central message of the <i>sūtra</i> is the so-called <i>darśana-mārga</i>, a path of seeing, which is accompanied by supramundane insight (lokottara-prajñā), which enables a Buddhist adept to directly perceive the true reality and become an <i>ārya</i>, noble person. I argue that this central idea of the <i>sūtra</i> is textually and doctrinally (or philosophically) interwoven with the specifically Yogācāra understanding of the <i>darśana-mārga</i>. Moreover, I show that one of the main ideas of the <i>sūtra</i>, the ambivalence of the sense objects, realized at the <i>darśana-mārga</i>, is likely an antecedent of the specifically Yogācāra teaching on the possibility of the same object to cause opposite types of experience, and, as such, an antecedent of the cornerstone Yogācāra principle of <i>vijñaptimātratā</i> (the teaching that the objects of perception are mere representations of/in the mind). Another important aspect explored in this paper is the intertextuality of the <i>Māyājāla-sūtra</i>, its parallels and the first chapters of the <i>Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra</i>, which sheds important light on the origin of the latter text. I argue that these parallels to the Yogācāra teachings are, at the very least, their earlier precedents, and, because of that the <i>Māyājāla-sūtra</i> may be called a proto-Yogācāra <i>sūtra</i>.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142193879","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dialogues About Death in Milindapañha and Carakasaṃhitā Milindapañha 和 Carakasaṃhitā 中关于死亡的对话
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-08-12 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09578-4
Yukio Yamanaka, Tsutomu Yamashita

This paper deals with the debates over kālamṛtyu (“timely death” or human death at the end of the life span) and akālamṛtyu (“untimely death” or premature death that occurs when the life span still remains). In cultural areas like ancient India, where the karman doctrine or the law of karman is firmly rooted, such “timely death” and “untimely death” have seemed to be the catalysts for the philosophical and ethical debates. Assuming that a person’s life itself would be affected by the person’s past karmans, each life span and death of individual persons would have been predetermined by their past karmans, and consequently, any efforts for preserving or prolonging life span in this world would have no meaning. If it were so, in the first place, does the karman doctrine leave room for “untimely death”? This paper discusses how Buddhist literature, especially the Questions of King Milinda (Milindapañha), and the Āyurvedic literature approach the above issues.

本文论述的是关于 kālamṛtyu("及时死亡 "或人在寿命结束时的死亡)和 akālamṛtyu("非及时死亡 "或在寿命尚存时发生的过早死亡)的争论。在古印度等羯磨论或羯磨法根深蒂固的文化地区,这种 "适时死亡 "和 "非适时死亡 "似乎是哲学和伦理争论的催化剂。假设一个人的生命本身会受到其过去业力的影响,那么每个人的寿命和死亡都是由其过去的业力所注定的,因此,在这个世界上为保存或延长寿命所做的任何努力都没有意义。既然如此,那么业力说是否为 "早死 "留下了余地呢?本文讨论佛教文献,尤其是《弥林达王问经》(Milindapañha)和阿育吠陀文献是如何处理上述问题的。
{"title":"Dialogues About Death in Milindapañha and Carakasaṃhitā","authors":"Yukio Yamanaka, Tsutomu Yamashita","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09578-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09578-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p> This paper deals with the debates over <i>kālamṛtyu</i> (“timely death” or human death at the end of the life span) and <i>akālamṛtyu</i> (“untimely death” or premature death that occurs when the life span still remains). In cultural areas like ancient India, where the <i>karman</i> doctrine or the law of <i>karman</i> is firmly rooted, such “timely death” and “untimely death” have seemed to be the catalysts for the philosophical and ethical debates. Assuming that a person’s life itself would be affected by the person’s past <i>karman</i>s, each life span and death of individual persons would have been predetermined by their past <i>karman</i>s, and consequently, any efforts for preserving or prolonging life span in this world would have no meaning. If it were so, in the first place, does the <i>karman</i> doctrine leave room for “untimely death”? This paper discusses how Buddhist literature, especially the <i>Questions of King Milinda</i> (<i>Milindapañha</i>), and the Āyurvedic literature approach the above issues.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142193922","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
In Some Ways: Syādvāda as the Synthesis of Anekāntavāda and Nayavāda in Akalaṅka’s Philosophical Treatises 某种程度上:阿卡拉卡哲学论著中作为阿内卡文塔达和纳雅文塔达综合体的萨达瓦达(Syādvāda
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-07-31 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09575-7
Shree Nahata

This paper investigates the relationship between the theory of many-sidedness (anekāntavāda), the theory of viewpoints (nayavāda), and the theory of sevenfold conditional predication (syādvāda) in the philosophical monographs of the Jaina philosopher Akalaṅka (c. 720-780 CE). Despite being celebrated as novel Jaina contributions to Indian philosophy, the mutual relationship between these three theories is poorly understood. Do these three theories represent three distinct frameworks with distinct purposes? Or do these three theories ultimately synthesise to form a single unified framework? Through a careful study of the Laghīyastraya and the Nyāyaviniścaya, this paper shows how Akalaṅka understands syādvāda as the central organising framework for integrating the theory of many-sidedness and the theory of viewpoints. On the one hand, syādvāda is analysed as the synthesis of multiple viewpoints because each of the seven conditional predications, when taken individually, represents a genuine viewpoint. On the other hand, the seven conditional predications of syādvāda, when taken collectively and iterated with respect to different characteristics, represent the linguistic formalisation of many-sided (anekānta) Jaina ontology. This paper shows how syādvāda as the grand synthesis of the theory of many-sidedness and the theory of viewpoints creates new possibilities as well as new problems within Akalaṅka’s philosophical system.

本文研究了耆那教哲学家阿卡拉卡(Akalaṅka,约公元 720-780 年)哲学专著中的多面性理论(anekāntavāda)、观点理论(nayavāda)和七重条件谓词理论(syādvāda)之间的关系。尽管这三种理论被誉为耆那教对印度哲学的新贡献,但人们对它们之间的相互关系却知之甚少。这三种理论是否代表了具有不同目的的三种不同框架?还是这三种理论最终会综合形成一个统一的框架?本文通过对《大智度论》(Laghīyastraya)和《瑜伽师地论》(Nyāyaviniścaya)的仔细研究,说明了阿卡拉卡是如何将 "多面性理论"(syādvāda)理解为整合 "多面性理论 "和 "观点理论 "的核心组织框架的。一方面,syādvāda 被分析为多种观点的综合,因为七个条件谓词中的每一个单独来看都代表一种真正的观点。另一方面,"syādvāda "的七个条件谓词如果合在一起并根据不同的特征反复使用,则代表了多面(anekānta)耆那教本体论的语言形式化。本文展示了 syādvāda 作为多面性理论和观点理论的大综合如何在阿卡拉卡的哲学体系中创造了新的可能性和新的问题。
{"title":"In Some Ways: Syādvāda as the Synthesis of Anekāntavāda and Nayavāda in Akalaṅka’s Philosophical Treatises","authors":"Shree Nahata","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09575-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09575-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper investigates the relationship between the theory of many-sidedness (<i>anekāntavāda</i>), the theory of viewpoints (<i>nayavāda</i>), and the theory of sevenfold conditional predication (<i>syādvāda</i>) in the philosophical monographs of the Jaina philosopher Akalaṅka (c. 720-780 CE). Despite being celebrated as novel Jaina contributions to Indian philosophy, the mutual relationship between these three theories is poorly understood. Do these three theories represent three distinct frameworks with distinct purposes? Or do these three theories ultimately synthesise to form a single unified framework? Through a careful study of the <i>Laghīyastraya</i> and the <i>Nyāyaviniścaya</i>, this paper shows how Akalaṅka understands <i>syādvāda</i> as the central organising framework for integrating the theory of many-sidedness and the theory of viewpoints. On the one hand, <i>syādvāda</i> is analysed as the synthesis of multiple viewpoints because each of the seven conditional predications, when taken individually, represents a genuine viewpoint. On the other hand, the seven conditional predications of <i>syādvāda</i>, when taken collectively and iterated with respect to different characteristics, represent the linguistic formalisation of many-sided (<i>anekānta</i>) Jaina ontology. This paper shows how <i>syādvāda</i> as the grand synthesis of the theory of many-sidedness and the theory of viewpoints creates new possibilities as well as new problems within Akalaṅka’s philosophical system.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141868419","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Should a Yogi Be Healthy? Health Concepts in Early Haṭhayoga Texts 瑜伽士应该健康吗?早期哈他瑜伽文本中的健康概念
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-07-31 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09573-9
Hagar Shalev

Haṭhayoga texts, influential in the development of modern posture-based yoga, offer a conceptual framework intertwining physical cultivation, health, and soteriological aims. This article explores two interconnected inquiries regarding early Haṭhayoga texts: How do they conceptualize health, and how do they perceive the relationship between health and soteriology? These investigations illuminate the place of health in early yoga texts within Hindu traditions prior to its global recognition.

This article reveals that early haṭha texts present a holistic approach to health, highlighting the interconnectedness of curing the mind and healing the body. This process entails not only eradicating physical diseases but also the transcendence of all forms of suffering. The transformative process of eliminating the misleading self-identity (ahaṁkāra) is pivotal, leading directly to health. This relationship extends beyond metaphorical comparisons of healing ignorance and suffering. This ontological framework proposes a harmonious integration between the material and soteriological realms, viewing the healthy body as a physical manifestation of the divine essence. Thus, the emergence of the biomedical discourse surrounding yoga in modern times did not occur autonomously. Haṭhayoga, with its roots dating back to the beginning of the second millennium CE, played a crucial role in shaping this historical transformation.

Haṭhayoga(下塔瑜伽)经文对现代姿势瑜伽的发展具有重要影响,它提供了一个将身体修炼、健康和神学目标交织在一起的概念框架。本文探讨了有关早期 Haṭhayoga 经文的两个相互关联的问题:它们如何看待健康的概念,以及它们如何看待健康与神学之间的关系?本文揭示了早期 Haṭhayoga 经文提出的整体健康方法,强调了治愈心灵与治愈身体之间的相互联系。这一过程不仅包括消除身体疾病,还包括超越一切形式的痛苦。消除误导性自我认同(ahaṁkāra)的转变过程至关重要,直接导致健康。这种关系超越了治疗无知和痛苦的隐喻比较。这一本体论框架提出了物质领域与神学领域的和谐统一,将健康的身体视为神性本质的物质体现。因此,现代围绕瑜伽的生物医学论述的出现并不是独立发生的。起源于公元二千年初的哈他瑜伽在这一历史转变中发挥了至关重要的作用。
{"title":"Should a Yogi Be Healthy? Health Concepts in Early Haṭhayoga Texts","authors":"Hagar Shalev","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09573-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09573-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Haṭhayoga texts, influential in the development of modern posture-based yoga, offer a conceptual framework intertwining physical cultivation, health, and soteriological aims. This article explores two interconnected inquiries regarding early Haṭhayoga texts: How do they conceptualize health, and how do they perceive the relationship between health and soteriology? These investigations illuminate the place of health in early yoga texts within Hindu traditions prior to its global recognition.</p><p>This article reveals that early <i>haṭha</i> texts present a holistic approach to health, highlighting the interconnectedness of curing the mind and healing the body. This process entails not only eradicating physical diseases but also the transcendence of all forms of suffering. The transformative process of eliminating the misleading self-identity (<i>ahaṁkāra</i>) is pivotal, leading directly to health. This relationship extends beyond metaphorical comparisons of healing ignorance and suffering. This ontological framework proposes a harmonious integration between the material and soteriological realms, viewing the healthy body as a physical manifestation of the divine essence. Thus, the emergence of the biomedical discourse surrounding yoga in modern times did not occur autonomously. Haṭhayoga, with its roots dating back to the beginning of the second millennium CE, played a crucial role in shaping this historical transformation.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141868628","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two Uses of Anekāntavāda 阿内坎塔瓦达的两种用途
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-07-27 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09577-5
Johannes Bronkhorst

The thesis I will present is that, whatever its exact origins, the anekāntavāda was primarily (though not exclusively) used for two purposes: (1) to solve the “paradox of causality”, and (2) to classify non-Jaina systems of thought. The earliest texts in which the doctrine occurs present it as a solution to the paradox of causality. Only later do we find its use to classify non-Jaina philosophies.

我将提出的论点是,无论其确切起源如何,anekāntavāda 主要(尽管不是唯一)用于两个目的:(1) 解决 "因果性悖论",(2) 对非耆那教思想体系进行分类。出现该学说的最早文本将其作为因果悖论的解决方案。后来,我们才发现它被用来对非耆那教哲学进行分类。
{"title":"Two Uses of Anekāntavāda","authors":"Johannes Bronkhorst","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09577-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09577-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The thesis I will present is that, whatever its exact origins, the <i>anekāntavāda</i> was primarily (though not exclusively) used for two purposes: (1) to solve the “paradox of causality”, and (2) to classify non-Jaina systems of thought. The earliest texts in which the doctrine occurs present it as a solution to the paradox of causality. Only later do we find its use to classify non-Jaina philosophies.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141773849","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On Hearing a Yogi’s Talk: Āgamapramāṇa, Language, and Mind in the Pātañjalayoga 聆听瑜伽士的谈话:帕他伽罗瑜伽中的阿伽马普拉那、语言和心智
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-07-25 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09571-x
Rocco Cestola

The current study aims to clarify the meaning, the epistemic construction, and the pragmatics of the term āgama occurring in Pātañjalayogaśāstra I.7 and its commentaries. Since āgama is a linguistic construction, this paper is also a contribution to the inquiry into the philosophy of language of the Pātañjalayogaśāstra. The inclusion of linguistic-philosophical arguments corroborates the Pātañjalayoga system of philosophy as a śāstra text and its logical and epistemological paradigm. The structure of the present work is as follows: a first part strictly dealing with textual sources, and a second where the content of textual sources is discussed. Relying on the early literature ranging from the Pātañjalayogaśāstra (c. 400 CE) to the Pātañjalayogasūtravṛtti of Nāgeśa Bhaṭṭa (PYV, half of 17th—half of 18th cent. CE), to āgama can be accorded two principal meanings: as a generic verbal testimony, and as authoritative verbal teachings. Grounded on the evaluated textual material, the second part of this essay presents a hypothesis aiming at the understanding of verbal testimony: in the Pātañjalayogaśāstra, āgama exhibits an epistemological, linguistic and psychological construction. In fact, as an epistemic theory of verbal testimony āgama functions following three main vectors being: (a) epistemological source and instance of valid cognition, namely a pramāṇa, (b) linguistically structured, āgama exhibits a propositional structure (vākya); and (c) a mental episode, placing āgama as one among the different mental events (cittavṛtti) described in the Pātañjalayogaśāstra.

本研究旨在厘清出现在《帕绷亚罗耶瑜伽经》(Pātañjalayogaśāstra)I.7 及其注释中的āgama 一词的含义、认识论构造和语用学。由于 āgama 是一种语言建构,本文也是对《帕绷亚拉约伽śāstra》语言哲学探究的贡献。语言哲学论证的加入,证实了 Pātañjalayoga 哲学系统作为一个希斯拉文本及其逻辑和认识论范式。本著作的结构如下:第一部分严格论述文本来源,第二部分讨论文本来源的内容。根据早期文献,从《帕塔雅拉耶瑜伽经》(Pātañjalayogaśāstra,约公元 400 年)到《那伽婆多》(Nāgeśa Bhaṭṭa,PYV,公元 17 世纪下半叶至 18 世纪下半叶),āgama 可被赋予两种主要含义:通用的口头证言和权威的口头教义。根据所评估的文本材料,本文的第二部分提出了一个旨在理解口头证言的假设:在《帕绷亚罗亚瑜伽经》中,āgama 展示了一种认识论、语言学和心理学构造。事实上,作为言语证言的认识论理论,āgama 遵循三个主要载体发挥作用:(a) 有效认知的认识论来源和实例,即 pramāṇa;(b) 语言结构,āgama 展示了命题结构(vākya);(c) 心理事件,将āgama 作为《帕塔纳贾拉约伽śāstra》中描述的不同心理事件(cittavṛtti)之一。
{"title":"On Hearing a Yogi’s Talk: Āgamapramāṇa, Language, and Mind in the Pātañjalayoga","authors":"Rocco Cestola","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09571-x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09571-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The current study aims to clarify the meaning, the epistemic construction, and the pragmatics of the term <i>āgama</i> occurring in <i>Pātañjalayogaśāstra</i> I.7 and its commentaries. Since <i>āgama</i> is a linguistic construction, this paper is also a contribution to the inquiry into the philosophy of language of the <i>Pātañjalayogaśāstra</i>. The inclusion of linguistic-philosophical arguments corroborates the Pātañjalayoga system of philosophy as a <i>śāstra</i> text and its logical and epistemological paradigm. The structure of the present work is as follows: a first part strictly dealing with textual sources, and a second where the content of textual sources is discussed. Relying on the early literature ranging from the <i>Pātañjalayogaśāstra</i> (c. 400 CE) to the <i>Pātañjalayogasūtravṛtti</i> of Nāgeśa Bhaṭṭa (PYV, half of 17th—half of 18th cent. CE), to <i>āgama</i> can be accorded two principal meanings: as a generic verbal testimony, and as authoritative verbal teachings. Grounded on the evaluated textual material, the second part of this essay presents a hypothesis aiming at the understanding of verbal testimony: in the <i>Pātañjalayogaśāstra</i>, <i>āgama</i> exhibits an epistemological, linguistic and psychological construction. In fact, as an epistemic theory of verbal testimony <i>āgama</i> functions following three main vectors being: (a) epistemological source and instance of valid cognition, namely a <i>pramāṇa</i>, (b) linguistically structured, <i>āgama</i> exhibits a propositional structure (<i>vākya</i>); and (c) a mental episode, placing <i>āgama</i> as one among the different mental events (<i>cittavṛtti</i>) described in the <i>Pātañjalayogaśāstra</i>.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141773678","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Status of the Householder in the Dharmasūtras 户主在《达摩经》中的地位
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-07-25 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09576-6
Christopher G. Framarin

Vasiṣṭha claims both that all four āśramas are equal and that the householder is the best of the four āśramas. This apparent contradiction would be resolved if either of these claims could be dismissed. Vasiṣṭha's claim that the four āśramas are equal seems entailed, however, by his endorsement of the original formulation of the āśrama system. His claim that the householder is superior, in turn, seems supported by the surplus of arguments that he offers in favor of the householder. Patrick Olivelle takes Vasiṣṭha to advance this surplus of arguments for the householder only to bolster the more modest claim that the householder is equal—and therefore not inferior—to the celibate āśramas. If this right, then Vasiṣṭha's claim that the householder is superior might be understood in the same way. If the balance of evidence weighs in favor of one claim or the other, however, it seems to weigh in favor of the superiority of the householder, rather than the equality of the āśramas. An alternative interpretation takes Vasiṣṭha to evaluate the householder in relation to two distinct metrics. The four āśramas are equal, he says, in their ability to attain the highest heaven. The householder is superior to the other three āśramas, however, in his unmatched contributions to the general welfare.

瓦西ṭṭha 既声称四禅平等,又声称居士是四禅中最好的。如果这两种说法中的任何一种都能被否定,那么这个明显的矛盾就会迎刃而解。然而,瓦西ṭṭha 宣称四种禅是平等的,这似乎是由于他赞同最初的禅系统。反过来,他认为家庭主妇更优越的说法似乎也得到了他提供的大量支持家庭主妇的论据的支持。帕特里克-奥利维尔认为,瓦西ṣṭha 为居家者提出的大量论据只是为了支持一种更为温和的说法,即居家者与独身的āśramas 是平等的,因此并不低人一等。如果这种说法是正确的,那么瓦西藏(Vasiṣṭha)关于户主优越的说法也可以用同样的方式来理解。然而,如果证据的天平倾向于其中一种说法,那么似乎是倾向于居家者的优越性,而不是 āśramas 的平等性。另一种解释认为瓦西藏是根据两个不同的标准来评价户主的。他说,在达到最高天堂的能力方面,四个āśramas 是平等的。然而,居家者在为大众福利做出无与伦比的贡献方面优于其他三位常住。
{"title":"The Status of the Householder in the Dharmasūtras","authors":"Christopher G. Framarin","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09576-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09576-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Vasiṣṭha claims both that all four <i>āśramas</i> are equal and that the householder is the best of the four <i>āśramas</i>. This apparent contradiction would be resolved if either of these claims could be dismissed. Vasiṣṭha's claim that the four <i>āśramas</i> are equal seems entailed, however, by his endorsement of the original formulation of the <i>āśrama</i> system. His claim that the householder is superior, in turn, seems supported by the surplus of arguments that he offers in favor of the householder. Patrick Olivelle takes Vasiṣṭha to advance this surplus of arguments for the householder only to bolster the more modest claim that the householder is <i>equal</i>—and therefore not inferior—to the celibate <i>āśramas</i>. If this right, then Vasiṣṭha's claim that the householder is superior might be understood in the same way. If the balance of evidence weighs in favor of one claim or the other, however, it seems to weigh in favor of the superiority of the householder, rather than the equality of the <i>āśramas</i>. An alternative interpretation takes Vasiṣṭha to evaluate the householder in relation to two distinct metrics. The four <i>āśramas</i> are equal, he says, in their ability to attain the highest heaven. The householder is superior to the other three <i>āśramas</i>, however, in his unmatched contributions to the general welfare.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141773850","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Smoke and Fire. Sign Inference in Greek and in Indian Epistemology 烟与火。希腊和印度认识论中的符号推理
IF 0.3 2区 哲学 N/A ASIAN STUDIES Pub Date : 2024-07-15 DOI: 10.1007/s10781-024-09572-w
A. K. Aklan

“Wherever there is smoke there must be fire.” In 1957, Aram M. Frenkian noticed that both ancient Greek and Indian philosophy makes use of the smoke-fire analogy as a model for inferential reasoning. He postulated that Greek use of the example reflected Indian influence on Greek philosophy which was mediated through the works of Pyrrho, the founder of Sceptisicm, who had accompanied Alexander the Great on his Indian campaign (327-5 BCE) and learnt from Indian sages (‘gymnosophists’ as the Greeks called them). More recent scholarship mainly shares his views. In the present paper, I argue that the smoke-fire example formed part of a complex theory of sign inference, and that not only the isolated analogy, but the theory as a whole which it illustrates is present in both cultures. Furthermore, the variants of this theory comprise such close and extended similarities that they must be the result of direct contact between Indian and Greek thinkers, although it is impossible to decide whether they stem from a common origin, or are the result of influence from one culture to the other.

"哪里有烟,哪里就有火"。1957 年,Aram M. Frenkian 注意到古希腊和印度哲学都使用烟火类比作为推理的模式。他推测,希腊哲学使用烟火类比反映了印度哲学对希腊哲学的影响,而这种影响是通过怀疑论创始人皮尔洛的著作传播的,皮尔洛曾随亚历山大大帝征战印度(公元前 327-5 年),并向印度圣人(希腊人称之为 "体操师")学习。最近的学术研究主要赞同他的观点。在本文中,我认为烟火的例子构成了复杂的符号推理理论的一部分,而且不仅是孤立的类比,它所说明的整个理论在两种文化中都存在。此外,这一理论的变体包含了如此紧密和广泛的相似性,以至于它们一定是印度和希腊思想家直接接触的结果,尽管我们无法确定它们是源于一个共同的起源,还是一种文化对另一种文化影响的结果。
{"title":"Smoke and Fire. Sign Inference in Greek and in Indian Epistemology","authors":"A. K. Aklan","doi":"10.1007/s10781-024-09572-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-024-09572-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>“Wherever there is smoke there must be fire.” In 1957, Aram M. Frenkian noticed that both ancient Greek and Indian philosophy makes use of the smoke-fire analogy as a model for inferential reasoning. He postulated that Greek use of the example reflected Indian influence on Greek philosophy which was mediated through the works of Pyrrho, the founder of Sceptisicm, who had accompanied Alexander the Great on his Indian campaign (327-5 BCE) and learnt from Indian sages (‘gymnosophists’ as the Greeks called them). More recent scholarship mainly shares his views. In the present paper, I argue that the smoke-fire example formed part of a complex theory of sign inference, and that not only the isolated analogy, but the theory as a whole which it illustrates is present in both cultures. Furthermore, the variants of this theory comprise such close and extended similarities that they must be the result of direct contact between Indian and Greek thinkers, although it is impossible to decide whether they stem from a common origin, or are the result of influence from one culture to the other.</p>","PeriodicalId":51854,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141773679","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
JOURNAL OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1