Pub Date : 2016-12-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.004
Paul D. Thorn, Gerhard Schurz
In previous work, we studied four well known systems of qualitative probabilistic inference, and presented data from computer simulations in an attempt to illustrate the performance of the systems. These simulations evaluated the four systems in terms of their tendency to license inference to accurate and informative conclusions, given incomplete information about a randomly selected probability distribution. In our earlier work, the procedure used in generating the unknown probability distribution (representing the true stochastic state of the world) tended to yield probability distributions with moderately high entropy levels. In the present article, we present data charting the performance of the four systems when reasoning in environments of various entropy levels. The results illustrate variations in the performance of the respective reasoning systems that derive from the entropy of the environment, and allow for a more inclusive assessment of the reliability and robustness of the four systems.
{"title":"Qualitative probabilistic inference under varied entropy levels","authors":"Paul D. Thorn, Gerhard Schurz","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.004","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.004","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In previous work, we studied four well known systems of qualitative probabilistic inference, and presented data from computer simulations in an attempt to illustrate the performance of the systems. These simulations evaluated the four systems in terms of their tendency to license inference to accurate and informative conclusions, given incomplete information about a randomly selected probability distribution. In our earlier work, the procedure used in generating the unknown probability distribution (representing the true stochastic state of the world) tended to yield probability distributions with moderately high entropy levels. In the present article, we present data charting the performance of the four systems when reasoning in environments of various entropy levels. The results illustrate variations in the performance of the respective reasoning systems that derive from the entropy of the environment, and allow for a more inclusive assessment of the reliability and robustness of the four systems.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"19 ","pages":"Pages 87-101"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.004","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127506776","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2016-12-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.001
Christoph Beierle, Gabriele Kern-Isberner
{"title":"Dynamics of Knowledge and Belief","authors":"Christoph Beierle, Gabriele Kern-Isberner","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.001","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.001","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"19 ","pages":"Pages 51-53"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.001","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132243911","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2016-11-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.04.004
Gerhard Jäger, Michel Marti
Starting off from the usual language of modal logic for multi-agent systems dealing with the agents' knowledge/belief and common knowledge/belief we define so-called epistemic Kripke structures for intuitionistic (common) knowledge/belief. Then we introduce corresponding deductive systems and show that they are sound and complete with respect to these semantics.
{"title":"Intuitionistic common knowledge or belief","authors":"Gerhard Jäger, Michel Marti","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.04.004","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.04.004","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Starting off from the usual language of modal logic for multi-agent systems dealing with the agents' knowledge/belief and common knowledge/belief we define so-called epistemic Kripke structures for intuitionistic (common) knowledge/belief. Then we introduce corresponding deductive systems and show that they are sound and complete with respect to these semantics.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"18 ","pages":"Pages 150-163"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.04.004","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114948504","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2016-11-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.008
Fairouz Kamareddine , Jonathan P. Seldin , J.B. Wells
There are two versions of type assignment in the λ-calculus: Church-style, in which the type of each variable is fixed, and Curry-style (also called “domain free”), in which it is not. As an example, in Church-style typing, is the identity function on type A, and it has type but not for a type B different from A. In Curry-style typing, is a general identity function with type for every type C. In this paper, we will show how to interpret in a Curry-style system every Pure Type System (PTS) in the Church-style without losing any typing information. We will also prove a kind of conservative extension result for this interpretation, a result which implies that for most consistent PTSs of the Church-style, the corresponding Curry-style system is consistent. We will then show how to interpret in a system of the Church-style (a modified PTS, stronger than a PTS) every PTS-like system in the Curry style.
{"title":"Bridging Curry and Church's typing style","authors":"Fairouz Kamareddine , Jonathan P. Seldin , J.B. Wells","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.008","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>There are two versions of type assignment in the <em>λ</em>-calculus: Church-style, in which the type of each variable is fixed, and Curry-style (also called “domain free”), in which it is not. As an example, in Church-style typing, <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>λ</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>x</mi><mo>:</mo><mi>A</mi></mrow></msub><mo>.</mo><mi>x</mi></math></span> is the identity function on type <em>A</em>, and it has type <span><math><mi>A</mi><mo>→</mo><mi>A</mi></math></span> but not <span><math><mi>B</mi><mo>→</mo><mi>B</mi></math></span> for a type <em>B</em> different from <em>A</em>. In Curry-style typing, <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>λ</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>x</mi></mrow></msub><mo>.</mo><mi>x</mi></math></span> is a general identity function with type <span><math><mi>C</mi><mo>→</mo><mi>C</mi></math></span> for <em>every</em> type <em>C</em>. In this paper, we will show how to interpret in a Curry-style system every Pure Type System (PTS) in the Church-style without losing any typing information. We will also prove a kind of conservative extension result for this interpretation, a result which implies that for most consistent PTSs of the Church-style, the corresponding Curry-style system is consistent. We will then show how to interpret in a system of the Church-style (a modified PTS, stronger than a PTS) every PTS-like system in the Curry style.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"18 ","pages":"Pages 42-70"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.008","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72274381","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2016-11-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.006
Shokoofeh Ghorbani
In this paper, we introduce hoop twist-structure whose members are built as special squares of an arbitrary hoop. We show how our construction relates to eN4-lattices (N4-lattices) and implicative twist-structures. We prove that hoop twist-structures form a quasi-variety and characterize the AHT-congruences of each algebra in this quasi-variety in terms of the congruences of the associated hoop.
{"title":"Hoop twist-structures","authors":"Shokoofeh Ghorbani","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.006","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In this paper, we introduce hoop twist-structure whose members are built as special squares of an arbitrary hoop. We show how our construction relates to eN4-lattices (N4-lattices) and implicative twist-structures. We prove that hoop twist-structures form a quasi-variety and characterize the AHT-congruences of each algebra in this quasi-variety in terms of the congruences of the associated hoop.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"18 ","pages":"Pages 1-18"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.006","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72274383","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Reliability has become an integral component of the design intent of embedded cyber-physical systems. Safety-critical embedded systems are designed with specific reliability targets, and design practices include the appropriate allocation of both spatial and temporal redundancies in the implementation to meet such requirements. With increasing complexity of such systems and considering the large number of components in such systems, redundancy allocation requires a formal scientific basis. In this work, we profess the analysis of the redundancy requirement upfront with the objective of making it an integral part of the specification. The underlying problem is one of synthesizing a formal specification with built-in redundancy artifacts, from the formal properties of the error-free system, the error probabilities of the control components, and the reliability target. We believe that upfront formal analysis of redundancy requirements is important in budgeting the resource requirements from a cost versus reliability perspective. Several case-studies from the automotive domain highlight the efficacy of our proposal.
{"title":"Formal assessment of reliability specifications in embedded cyber-physical systems","authors":"Aritra Hazra , Pallab Dasgupta , Partha Pratim Chakrabarti","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.09.001","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.09.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Reliability has become an integral component of the design intent of embedded cyber-physical systems. Safety-critical embedded systems are designed with specific reliability targets, and design practices include the appropriate allocation of both spatial and temporal redundancies in the implementation to meet such requirements. With increasing complexity of such systems and considering the large number of components in such systems, redundancy allocation requires a formal scientific basis. In this work, we profess the analysis of the redundancy requirement upfront with the objective of making it an integral part of the specification. The underlying problem is one of synthesizing a formal specification with built-in redundancy artifacts, from the formal properties of the error-free system, the error probabilities of the control components, and the reliability target. We believe that upfront formal analysis of redundancy requirements is important in budgeting the resource requirements from a cost versus reliability perspective. Several case-studies from the automotive domain highlight the efficacy of our proposal.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"18 ","pages":"Pages 71-104"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.09.001","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128868575","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2016-11-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.06.001
A.J. Goodall , J. Nešetřil , P. Ossona de Mendez
A strongly polynomial sequence of graphs is a sequence of finite graphs such that, for every graph F, the number of homomorphisms from F to is a fixed polynomial function of n (depending on F). For example, is strongly polynomial since the number of homomorphisms from F to is the chromatic polynomial of F evaluated at n. In earlier work of de la Harpe and Jaeger, and more recently of Averbouch, Garijo, Godlin, Goodall, Makowsky, Nešetřil, Tittmann, Zilber and others, various examples of strongly polynomial sequences and constructions for families of such sequences have been found, leading to analogues of the chromatic polynomial for fractional colourings and acyclic colourings, to choose two interesting examples.
We give a new model-theoretic method of constructing strongly polynomial sequences of graphs that uses interpretation schemes of graphs in more general relational structures. This surprisingly easy yet general method encompasses all previous constructions and produces many more. We conjecture that, under mild assumptions, all strongly polynomial sequences of graphs can be produced by the general method of quantifier-free interpretation of graphs in certain basic relational structures (essentially disjoint unions of transitive tournaments with added unary relations). We verify this conjecture for strongly polynomial sequences of graphs with uniformly bounded degree.
{"title":"Strongly polynomial sequences as interpretations","authors":"A.J. Goodall , J. Nešetřil , P. Ossona de Mendez","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.06.001","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.06.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>A strongly polynomial sequence of graphs <span><math><mo>(</mo><msub><mrow><mi>G</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi></mrow></msub><mo>)</mo></math></span> is a sequence <span><math><msub><mrow><mo>(</mo><msub><mrow><mi>G</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi></mrow></msub><mo>)</mo></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi><mo>∈</mo><mi>N</mi></mrow></msub></math></span> of finite graphs such that, for every graph <em>F</em>, the number of homomorphisms from <em>F</em> to <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>G</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi></mrow></msub></math></span> is a fixed polynomial function of <em>n</em> (depending on <em>F</em>). For example, <span><math><mo>(</mo><msub><mrow><mi>K</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi></mrow></msub><mo>)</mo></math></span> is strongly polynomial since the number of homomorphisms from <em>F</em> to <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>K</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi></mrow></msub></math></span> is the chromatic polynomial of <em>F</em> evaluated at <em>n</em>. In earlier work of de la Harpe and Jaeger, and more recently of Averbouch, Garijo, Godlin, Goodall, Makowsky, Nešetřil, Tittmann, Zilber and others, various examples of strongly polynomial sequences and constructions for families of such sequences have been found, leading to analogues of the chromatic polynomial for fractional colourings and acyclic colourings, to choose two interesting examples.</p><p>We give a new model-theoretic method of constructing strongly polynomial sequences of graphs that uses interpretation schemes of graphs in more general relational structures. This surprisingly easy yet general method encompasses all previous constructions and produces many more. We conjecture that, under mild assumptions, all strongly polynomial sequences of graphs can be produced by the general method of quantifier-free interpretation of graphs in certain basic relational structures (essentially disjoint unions of transitive tournaments with added unary relations). We verify this conjecture for strongly polynomial sequences of graphs with uniformly bounded degree.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"18 ","pages":"Pages 129-149"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.06.001","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130060536","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2016-11-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.08.001
Justine Jacot , Emmanuel Genot , Frank Zenker
This article demonstrates that typical restrictions which are imposed in dialogical logic in order to recover first-order logical consequence from a fragment of natural language argumentation are also forthcoming from preference profiles of boundedly rational players, provided that these players instantiate a specific player type and compute partial strategies. We present two structural rules, which are formulated similarly to closure rules for tableaux proofs that restrict players' strategies to a mapping between games in extensive forms (i.e., game trees) and proof trees. Both rules are motivated from players' preferences and limitations; they can therefore be viewed as being player-self-imposable. First-order logical consequence is thus shown to result from playing a specific type of argumentation game. The alignment of such games with the normative model of the Pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation is positively evaluated. But explicit rules to guarantee that the argumentation game instantiates first-order logical consequence have now become gratuitous, since their normative content arises directly from players' preferences and limitations. A similar naturalization for non-classical logics is discussed.
{"title":"From reasonable preferences, via argumentation, to logic","authors":"Justine Jacot , Emmanuel Genot , Frank Zenker","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.08.001","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.08.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This article demonstrates that typical restrictions which are imposed in dialogical logic in order to recover first-order logical consequence from a fragment of natural language argumentation are also forthcoming from preference profiles of boundedly rational players, provided that these players instantiate a specific player type and compute partial strategies. We present two structural rules, which are formulated similarly to closure rules for tableaux proofs that restrict players' strategies to a mapping between games in extensive forms (i.e., game trees) and proof trees. Both rules are motivated from players' preferences and limitations; they can therefore be viewed as being player-self-imposable. First-order logical consequence is thus shown to result from playing a specific type of argumentation game. The alignment of such games with the normative model of the Pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation is positively evaluated. But explicit rules to guarantee that the argumentation game instantiates first-order logical consequence have now become gratuitous, since their normative content arises directly from players' preferences and limitations. A similar naturalization for non-classical logics is discussed.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"18 ","pages":"Pages 105-128"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.08.001","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133547618","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2016-11-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.007
Waqar Ahmed , Osman Hasan , Sofiène Tahar
Reliability Block Diagrams (RBDs) allow us to model the failure relationships of complex systems and their sub-components and are extensively used for system reliability, availability and maintainability analyses. Traditionally, these RBD-based analyses are done using paper-and-pencil proofs or computer simulations, which cannot ascertain absolute correctness due to their inaccuracy limitations. As a complementary approach, we propose to use the higher-order logic theorem prover HOL to conduct RBD-based analysis. For this purpose, we present a higher-order logic formalization of commonly used RBD configurations, such as series, parallel, parallel-series and series-parallel, and the formal verification of their equivalent mathematical expressions. A distinguishing feature of the proposed RBD formalization is the ability to model nested RBD configurations, which are RBDs having blocks that also represent RBD configurations. This generality allows us to formally analyze the reliability of many real-world systems. For illustration purposes, we formally analyze the reliability of a generic Virtual Data Center (VDC) in a cloud computing infrastructure exhibiting the nested series-parallel RBD configuration.
{"title":"Formalization of Reliability Block Diagrams in Higher-order Logic","authors":"Waqar Ahmed , Osman Hasan , Sofiène Tahar","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.007","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Reliability Block Diagrams (RBDs) allow us to model the failure relationships of complex systems and their sub-components and are extensively used for system reliability, availability and maintainability analyses. Traditionally, these RBD-based analyses are done using paper-and-pencil proofs or computer simulations, which cannot ascertain absolute correctness due to their inaccuracy limitations. As a complementary approach, we propose to use the higher-order logic theorem prover HOL to conduct RBD-based analysis. For this purpose, we present a higher-order logic formalization of commonly used RBD configurations, such as series, parallel, parallel-series and series-parallel, and the formal verification of their equivalent mathematical expressions. A distinguishing feature of the proposed RBD formalization is the ability to model nested RBD configurations, which are RBDs having blocks that also represent RBD configurations. This generality allows us to formally analyze the reliability of many real-world systems. For illustration purposes, we formally analyze the reliability of a generic Virtual Data Center (VDC) in a cloud computing infrastructure exhibiting the nested series-parallel RBD configuration.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"18 ","pages":"Pages 19-41"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2016.05.007","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72274384","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2016-09-01DOI: 10.1016/j.jal.2015.09.007
José Luis Casteleiro-Roca , Héctor Quintián , José Luis Calvo-Rolle , Emilio Corchado , María del Carmen Meizoso-López , Andrés Piñón-Pazos
The heat pump with geothermal exchanger is one of the best methods to heat up a building. The heat exchanger is an element with high probability of failure due to the fact that it is an outside construction and also due to its size. In the present study, a novel intelligent system was designed to detect faults on this type of heating equipment. The novel approach has been successfully empirically tested under a real dataset obtained during measurements of one year. It was based on classification techniques with the aim of detecting failures in real time. Then, the model was validated and verified over the building; it obtained good results in all the operating conditions ranges.
{"title":"An intelligent fault detection system for a heat pump installation based on a geothermal heat exchanger","authors":"José Luis Casteleiro-Roca , Héctor Quintián , José Luis Calvo-Rolle , Emilio Corchado , María del Carmen Meizoso-López , Andrés Piñón-Pazos","doi":"10.1016/j.jal.2015.09.007","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.jal.2015.09.007","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The heat pump with geothermal exchanger is one of the best methods to heat up a building. The heat exchanger is an element with high probability of failure due to the fact that it is an outside construction and also due to its size. In the present study, a novel intelligent system was designed to detect faults on this type of heating equipment. The novel approach has been successfully empirically tested under a real dataset obtained during measurements of one year. It was based on classification techniques with the aim of detecting failures in real time. Then, the model was validated and verified over the building; it obtained good results in all the operating conditions ranges.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":54881,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Logic","volume":"17 ","pages":"Pages 36-47"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1016/j.jal.2015.09.007","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114214440","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}