首页 > 最新文献

Nigeria and the classics最新文献

英文 中文
Plato’s Philebus
Pub Date : 2018-11-29 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0326
Sylvain Delcomminette, Dee L. Clayman
The Philebus is almost unanimously considered as one of Plato’s last dialogues, probably written around the same time as the Timaeus. Unlike other late dialogues, however, it takes the more conventional form of a conversation between Socrates and two interlocutors: Philebus and Protarchus. Philebus in fact refuses to discuss and remains silent for most of the dialogue, leaving to Protarchus the task of defending hedonism against the attacks of intellectualism championed by Socrates. The Philebus is a particularly rich and difficult work, which has often been viewed as messy. Although it has received the subtitle “On pleasure” since Antiquity, it contains, besides a lengthy examination of pleasure that notably argues for the possibility of false pleasures, a reflection on the relations between unity and plurality, an exposition of dialectic presented as a “god-given” and “heavenly” method, a fourfold classification of “all there is,” a cosmological argument purported to show that the world is governed by intelligence, and a hierarchical classification of the different kinds of knowledge. All these elements are integrated in a quest for “the good,” which at the beginning of the dialogue is identified to the best human life, but at the end seems to gain greater generality and concern not only human beings but also the whole or the universe. Are all these themes supposed to connect somehow, and if they are, in what manner? This question was already debated by the Neoplatonist commentators and was taken over by modern scholarship since the 19th century. Another question that has provoked scholars is the relation between the “metaphysics” exposed in the dialogue and Plato’s “unwritten doctrines” referred to by Aristotle. However, the greatest part of scholarship on the Philebus is currently devoted to scrutinize a theme or a portion of the text itself. After a relative neglect, this dialogue has indeed become the focus of much scholarly work during the last decades. The present bibliography had consequently to be highly selective and favors the most useful starting-points for further explorations of the wealthy literature devoted to this fascinating text.
《菲利伯斯篇》几乎被一致认为是柏拉图最后的对话之一,可能与《蒂迈奥篇》同时写成。然而,与其他后期的对话不同,它采用了苏格拉底与两个对话者:菲利伯斯和普罗塔克之间的对话的更传统的形式。菲利伯斯实际上拒绝讨论,在大部分对话中保持沉默,把捍卫享乐主义的任务留给普罗塔克,反对苏格拉底所倡导的理智主义的攻击。《菲勒伯斯》是一部内容特别丰富、难度特别大的作品,经常被认为是凌乱的。尽管从古代起它就有了“论快乐”的副标题,但它除了对快乐进行了冗长的考察,特别是论证了虚假快乐的可能性之外,还包含了对统一与多元之间关系的反思,对辩证法的阐述,即“上帝赋予”和“天堂”的方法,“一切都有”的四重分类,一种宇宙学论证声称,世界是由智力和不同种类的知识的等级分类所统治的。所有这些因素都被整合在对“善”的追求中,在对话的开始被确定为最好的人类生活,但在最后似乎获得了更大的普遍性和关注,不仅是人类,而且是整个宇宙。所有这些主题都应该以某种方式联系在一起吗?如果是的话,是以什么方式联系在一起的?这个问题已经被新柏拉图主义评论家讨论过,并且自19世纪以来被现代学术所接管。另一个让学者们感到不安的问题是,对话中暴露的“形而上学”与亚里士多德提到的柏拉图的“不成文学说”之间的关系。然而,目前关于《菲勒伯斯》的大部分学术研究都致力于研究一个主题或文本本身的一部分。在相对被忽视之后,这一对话在过去几十年中确实成为许多学术工作的焦点。因此,目前的参考书目必须是高度选择性的,有利于最有用的起点,以进一步探索丰富的文献,致力于这个迷人的文本。
{"title":"Plato’s Philebus","authors":"Sylvain Delcomminette, Dee L. Clayman","doi":"10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0326","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0326","url":null,"abstract":"The Philebus is almost unanimously considered as one of Plato’s last dialogues, probably written around the same time as the Timaeus. Unlike other late dialogues, however, it takes the more conventional form of a conversation between Socrates and two interlocutors: Philebus and Protarchus. Philebus in fact refuses to discuss and remains silent for most of the dialogue, leaving to Protarchus the task of defending hedonism against the attacks of intellectualism championed by Socrates. The Philebus is a particularly rich and difficult work, which has often been viewed as messy. Although it has received the subtitle “On pleasure” since Antiquity, it contains, besides a lengthy examination of pleasure that notably argues for the possibility of false pleasures, a reflection on the relations between unity and plurality, an exposition of dialectic presented as a “god-given” and “heavenly” method, a fourfold classification of “all there is,” a cosmological argument purported to show that the world is governed by intelligence, and a hierarchical classification of the different kinds of knowledge. All these elements are integrated in a quest for “the good,” which at the beginning of the dialogue is identified to the best human life, but at the end seems to gain greater generality and concern not only human beings but also the whole or the universe. Are all these themes supposed to connect somehow, and if they are, in what manner? This question was already debated by the Neoplatonist commentators and was taken over by modern scholarship since the 19th century. Another question that has provoked scholars is the relation between the “metaphysics” exposed in the dialogue and Plato’s “unwritten doctrines” referred to by Aristotle. However, the greatest part of scholarship on the Philebus is currently devoted to scrutinize a theme or a portion of the text itself. After a relative neglect, this dialogue has indeed become the focus of much scholarly work during the last decades. The present bibliography had consequently to be highly selective and favors the most useful starting-points for further explorations of the wealthy literature devoted to this fascinating text.","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"31 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90827265","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Eratosthenes of Cyrene 昔兰尼的埃拉托色尼
Pub Date : 2018-10-11 DOI: 10.1007/springerreference_58424
P. Finglass
{"title":"Eratosthenes of Cyrene","authors":"P. Finglass","doi":"10.1007/springerreference_58424","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/springerreference_58424","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"19 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-10-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90691938","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Optimates/Populares
Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0323
C. Rosillo-López
Populares and optimates are two political denominations, especially used in ancient Roman politics during the 1st century bce during the Late Roman Republic (although the sources apply them sometimes to the 2nd century bce). The basis of such differentiation is Marcus Tullius Cicero (106–43 bce), Pro Sestio 96, which defined populares and optimates as two distinct political categories. Popularis (adjective, singular of the plural populares in Latin) is an ambiguous term: it could connote “pleasing to the people” or “in the interest of the people”; the term to define the opposite of the senatorial majority, a combination of a certain political strategy and a certain type of political eloquence (eloquentia popularis) or, finally, a certain political tradition. Many politicians termed populares were tribunes of the plebs and some of them died or were murdered in violent confrontations with the Senate. The term optimates, or boni (a similar term, not exactly a synonym), rarely occur in the sources. People ascribed to this group in modern scholarship are those who believed in senatorial authority and/or those supporting the interests of the wealthy. However, identification can be also problematic. Some of the main sources are Cicero, Pro Sestio 96 (takes a negative view; main locus of the confrontation optimates-populares); Sallust, Bellum Catilinae 20; Bellum Iugurthinum 31 (Memmius’s speech) and 85 (Marius’s speech); Historiae 1.55 (Lepidus’s speech) and 3.48 (Macer’s speech). Sallust’s Epistulae ad Caesarem have been considered to be both fake and authentic (latest edition Antonio Duplá, Guillermo Fatás, and Francisco Pina Polo, Rem publicam restituere: una propuesta popularis para la crisis republicana: las Epistulae ad Caesarem de Salustio [Zaragoza, Spain: Departamento de ciencias de la antigüedad Universidad de Zaragoza, 1994] considers them authentic). Best introductions in English: Zvi Yavetz, Plebs and princeps (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 1988); Nicola Mackie, Popularis ideology and popular politics at Rome in the first century B. C. Rheinisches Museum für Philologie 135 (1992): 49–73; Margaret Robb, Beyond « populares » and « optimates »: political language in the late Republic (Stuttgart: Steiner, 2010); Antonio Duplá, “Consules populares,” in Consuls and res publica: holding high office in the Roman Republic, edited by Hans Beck, Antonio Duplá, Martin Jehne and Francisco Pina Polo (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2011), pp. 279–298; Claudia Tiersch, “Political Communication in the Late Roman Republic: Semantic Battles between Optimates and Populares?” in Institutions and Ideology in Republican Rome. Speech, Audience and Decision, edited by H. van der Blom, C. Gray and C. Steel (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2018), pp. 35–68.
Populares和optimates是两个政治名称,特别是在公元前1世纪罗马共和国晚期的古罗马政治中使用(尽管资料来源有时将它们应用于公元前2世纪)。这种区分的基础是马库斯·图利乌斯·西塞罗(公元前106-43)的《96年论纲》(Pro Sestio 96),其中将平民和优选者定义为两个不同的政治类别。Popularis(形容词,拉丁语中复数populares的单数)是一个模棱两可的术语:它可能意味着“取悦人民”或“为了人民的利益”;这个术语用来定义参议院多数派的对立面,是某种政治策略和某种政治口才(eloquentia popularis)的结合,或者最后是某种政治传统的结合。许多被称为populares的政治家是平民的保民官,他们中的一些人在与元老院的暴力冲突中死亡或被谋杀。术语优化或boni(一个类似的术语,不完全是同义词)很少出现在源代码中。在现代学术界,属于这一群体的人是那些相信元老院权威和/或支持富人利益的人。然而,识别也是有问题的。一些主要的来源是西塞罗的《论文集》第96章(持否定观点;对抗的主要地点是最优者(populares);萨勒斯特,羽扇叶20;Bellum Iugurthinum 31 (Memmius的演讲)和85 (Marius的演讲);历史1.55(雷必达的演讲)和3.48(梅瑟的演讲)。萨勒斯特的《凯撒书信》被认为既假又真(最新版安东尼奥·杜普、吉列尔莫Fatás和弗朗西斯科·皮纳·波罗,《共和危机下的大众书信》:《凯撒书信》认为它们是真品[西班牙萨拉戈萨:萨拉戈萨大学科学学院,1994年])。最佳英文介绍:Zvi Yavetz, Plebs and princeps (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 1988);尼古拉·麦基:《公元前一世纪罗马的大众意识形态与大众政治》,《莱茵博物馆》,《语言学》135 (1992):49-73;玛格丽特·罗伯:《超越“大众”和“最优者”:《共和国》晚期的政治语言》(斯图加特:施泰纳出版社,2010);安东尼奥·迪普勒,“平民执政官”,载于《执政官与共和政府:在罗马共和国担任高官》,由汉斯·贝克、安东尼奥·迪普勒、马丁·杰内和弗朗西斯科·皮纳·波罗编辑(英国剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2011),第279-298页;克劳迪娅·蒂尔施(Claudia Tiersch):《罗马共和国晚期的政治传播:最优者与大众之间的语义之争?》摘自《共和罗马的制度与意识形态》。《演讲、听众与决策》,H. van der Blom、C. Gray和C. Steel主编(剑桥,英国:剑桥大学出版社,2018),第35-68页。
{"title":"Optimates/Populares","authors":"C. Rosillo-López","doi":"10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0323","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0323","url":null,"abstract":"Populares and optimates are two political denominations, especially used in ancient Roman politics during the 1st century bce during the Late Roman Republic (although the sources apply them sometimes to the 2nd century bce). The basis of such differentiation is Marcus Tullius Cicero (106–43 bce), Pro Sestio 96, which defined populares and optimates as two distinct political categories. Popularis (adjective, singular of the plural populares in Latin) is an ambiguous term: it could connote “pleasing to the people” or “in the interest of the people”; the term to define the opposite of the senatorial majority, a combination of a certain political strategy and a certain type of political eloquence (eloquentia popularis) or, finally, a certain political tradition. Many politicians termed populares were tribunes of the plebs and some of them died or were murdered in violent confrontations with the Senate. The term optimates, or boni (a similar term, not exactly a synonym), rarely occur in the sources. People ascribed to this group in modern scholarship are those who believed in senatorial authority and/or those supporting the interests of the wealthy. However, identification can be also problematic. Some of the main sources are Cicero, Pro Sestio 96 (takes a negative view; main locus of the confrontation optimates-populares); Sallust, Bellum Catilinae 20; Bellum Iugurthinum 31 (Memmius’s speech) and 85 (Marius’s speech); Historiae 1.55 (Lepidus’s speech) and 3.48 (Macer’s speech). Sallust’s Epistulae ad Caesarem have been considered to be both fake and authentic (latest edition Antonio Duplá, Guillermo Fatás, and Francisco Pina Polo, Rem publicam restituere: una propuesta popularis para la crisis republicana: las Epistulae ad Caesarem de Salustio [Zaragoza, Spain: Departamento de ciencias de la antigüedad Universidad de Zaragoza, 1994] considers them authentic). Best introductions in English: Zvi Yavetz, Plebs and princeps (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 1988); Nicola Mackie, Popularis ideology and popular politics at Rome in the first century B. C. Rheinisches Museum für Philologie 135 (1992): 49–73; Margaret Robb, Beyond « populares » and « optimates »: political language in the late Republic (Stuttgart: Steiner, 2010); Antonio Duplá, “Consules populares,” in Consuls and res publica: holding high office in the Roman Republic, edited by Hans Beck, Antonio Duplá, Martin Jehne and Francisco Pina Polo (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2011), pp. 279–298; Claudia Tiersch, “Political Communication in the Late Roman Republic: Semantic Battles between Optimates and Populares?” in Institutions and Ideology in Republican Rome. Speech, Audience and Decision, edited by H. van der Blom, C. Gray and C. Steel (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2018), pp. 35–68.","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"10 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78163168","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Pythagoreanism 毕达哥拉斯主义
Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0319
L. Zhmud
Pythagoreanism is a modern term referring to a multifaceted phenomenon that covered different aspects of the ancient world such as political life, religion, philosophy, and science and existed in only partly overlapping forms. Its originator, Pythagoras of Samos, moved c. 530 bce to Italian Croton, where his followers, the Pythagoreans, organized a political society, whose participants were at the same time encouraged to undertake various intellectual pursuits. Pythagoras’s best attested doctrine is transmigration of the soul, whereas philosophical theories and scientific discoveries ascribed to him are highly disputed. Often he is regarded as a purely religious thinker, though not a single religious figure is known of among his followers. All known ancient Pythagoreans belong to five overlapping categories: politicians, athletes, doctors, natural philosophers, and mathematical scientists. After Pythagoras’s death the Pythagorean societies politically dominated in Croton, Metapontum, Tarentum, and other cities of Southern Italy until the anti-Pythagorean uprising (c. 450), when many Pythagoreans were killed or forced to flee to mainland Greece. The last center of Pythagoreanism in Italy remained in Tarentum, led in 367–361 by Archytas, a successful general and brilliant mathematician. The Pythagorean school created theoretical arithmetic and mathematical harmonics and greatly contributed to natural philosophy, geometry, and astronomy. Its disappearance after 350 bce marked the end of ancient Pythagoreanism. A new form of Pythagoreanism without the Pythagoreans were the pseudo-Pythagorean writings ascribed to Pythagoras and his fictitious family members. The first wave of Pseudo-Pythagorica (late 4th to late 2nd centuries bce) was neither numerous nor popular but since the early 1st century bce it was superseded by the second, more successful wave that was part of the emerging Neopythagoreanism. These treatises written under the names of historical and fictional Pythagoreans and containing Stoic, Platonic, and Aristotelian doctrines aimed to present Pythagoras and his followers as the precursors of Plato and Aristotle. The first Neopythagoreans writing under their own names appeared in the mid-1st century ce and doctrinally belonged to Middle Platonism. The most important representatives of late antique Pythagoreanism were the Neoplatonists Porphyry and especially Iamblichus, who secured its existence until the end of Antiquity.
毕达哥拉斯主义是一个现代术语,指的是一种多面现象,它涵盖了古代世界的不同方面,如政治生活、宗教、哲学和科学,只是部分重叠的形式存在。它的创始人,萨摩斯的毕达哥拉斯,公元前530年搬到意大利的克罗顿,在那里他的追随者,毕达哥拉斯派,组织了一个政治社会,其参与者同时被鼓励从事各种知识追求。毕达哥拉斯最被证实的学说是灵魂的轮回,而他的哲学理论和科学发现却备受争议。他经常被认为是一个纯粹的宗教思想家,尽管在他的追随者中没有一个宗教人物。所有已知的古代毕达哥拉斯学派都属于五个相互重叠的类别:政治家、运动员、医生、自然哲学家和数学科学家。毕达哥拉斯死后,毕达哥拉斯社会在政治上主导了克罗顿、梅塔波顿、塔伦托姆和意大利南部的其他城市,直到反毕达哥拉斯起义(约450年),当时许多毕达哥拉斯教徒被杀害或被迫逃往希腊大陆。毕达哥拉斯主义在意大利的最后一个中心仍在塔伦托姆,在367-361年由阿奇塔斯领导,他是一位成功的将军和杰出的数学家。毕达哥拉斯学派创造了理论算术和数学谐波,并对自然哲学、几何和天文学做出了巨大贡献。它在公元前350年之后的消失标志着古代毕达哥拉斯主义的终结。没有毕达哥拉斯学派的一种新形式是伪毕达哥拉斯的著作,这些著作被认为是毕达哥拉斯和他虚构的家庭成员写的。伪毕达哥拉斯学派的第一波浪潮(公元前4世纪末至公元前2世纪末)既不多也不流行,但自公元前1世纪初以来,它被第二波更成功的浪潮所取代,这是新兴的新毕达哥拉斯主义的一部分。这些论文以历史和虚构的毕达哥拉斯学派的名义撰写,包含斯多葛学派、柏拉图学派和亚里士多德学派的教义,旨在将毕达哥拉斯及其追随者视为柏拉图和亚里士多德的先驱。新毕达哥拉斯学派的第一批署名作品出现在公元1世纪中期,理论上属于中柏拉图主义。古代晚期毕达哥拉斯主义最重要的代表人物是新柏拉图主义者斑菲利,尤其是伊姆布利克斯,他们使毕达哥拉斯主义一直存在到古代末期。
{"title":"Pythagoreanism","authors":"L. Zhmud","doi":"10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0319","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0319","url":null,"abstract":"Pythagoreanism is a modern term referring to a multifaceted phenomenon that covered different aspects of the ancient world such as political life, religion, philosophy, and science and existed in only partly overlapping forms. Its originator, Pythagoras of Samos, moved c. 530 bce to Italian Croton, where his followers, the Pythagoreans, organized a political society, whose participants were at the same time encouraged to undertake various intellectual pursuits. Pythagoras’s best attested doctrine is transmigration of the soul, whereas philosophical theories and scientific discoveries ascribed to him are highly disputed. Often he is regarded as a purely religious thinker, though not a single religious figure is known of among his followers. All known ancient Pythagoreans belong to five overlapping categories: politicians, athletes, doctors, natural philosophers, and mathematical scientists. After Pythagoras’s death the Pythagorean societies politically dominated in Croton, Metapontum, Tarentum, and other cities of Southern Italy until the anti-Pythagorean uprising (c. 450), when many Pythagoreans were killed or forced to flee to mainland Greece. The last center of Pythagoreanism in Italy remained in Tarentum, led in 367–361 by Archytas, a successful general and brilliant mathematician. The Pythagorean school created theoretical arithmetic and mathematical harmonics and greatly contributed to natural philosophy, geometry, and astronomy. Its disappearance after 350 bce marked the end of ancient Pythagoreanism. A new form of Pythagoreanism without the Pythagoreans were the pseudo-Pythagorean writings ascribed to Pythagoras and his fictitious family members. The first wave of Pseudo-Pythagorica (late 4th to late 2nd centuries bce) was neither numerous nor popular but since the early 1st century bce it was superseded by the second, more successful wave that was part of the emerging Neopythagoreanism. These treatises written under the names of historical and fictional Pythagoreans and containing Stoic, Platonic, and Aristotelian doctrines aimed to present Pythagoras and his followers as the precursors of Plato and Aristotle. The first Neopythagoreans writing under their own names appeared in the mid-1st century ce and doctrinally belonged to Middle Platonism. The most important representatives of late antique Pythagoreanism were the Neoplatonists Porphyry and especially Iamblichus, who secured its existence until the end of Antiquity.","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"19 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81205228","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Classical Architecture in Europe and North America since 1700 欧洲和北美自1700年以来的古典建筑
Pub Date : 2018-07-24 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0318
E. Macaulay-Lewis
Since the Western Roman Empire collapsed, classical, or Greco-Roman, architecture has served as a model to articulate the cultural, artistic, political, and ideological goals of later civilizations, empires, nations, and individuals. The Renaissance marked the first major, widespread re-engagement with classical antiquity in art, literature, and architecture. Debates over classical antiquity and its relation to the modern world continued ever since. One such important debate was that of the quarrel between the Ancients and Moderns, which resulted when Charles Perrault published his Parallèles des anciens et des modernes in 1688. This dispute focused on whether the modern age could surpass antiquity, especially in literature. The Greco-Roman controversy (1750s and 1760s) was another example of Europeans engaging with the classical past; this debate focused on whether Greek or Roman art was of greater historical value; an argument has continued unabated to this day. Figures like Johann Joachim Winckelmann argued (in publications such as Winckelmann 1764, cited under Early Archaeological Publications on Greece and Classical Ruins in the Roman East, on Greek art) for the supremacy of Greek forms, while others like Giovanni Battista Piranesi (whose 1748–1778 views of Rome are reproduced in Ficacci 2011, cited under Early Archaeological Publications on Italy) advocated for Rome’s preeminence. Such debates demonstrate how classical antiquity was an essential part of the intellectual and artistic milieu of 18th-century Europe. This bibliography focuses on the appropriation of classical architecture in the creation of built forms from 1700 to the present in Europe and North America, which is typically called neoclassical or neo-classical, both of which are acceptable. Scholars often define the neoclassical period as lasting from c. 1750 to 1830, when European art and architecture predominantly appropriated classical forms and ideas. The influence of classical architecture continued in popularity throughout the 19th century and early 20th century in the United States. The early 19th century saw the flourishing of the Greek Revival, where Greek forms dominated artistic and architectural production, both in Europe and the United States. The ascendance of Queen Victoria in 1837 marked a shift toward a preference for the Gothic and Medieval forms. Neoclassical forms saw a resurgence in the second half of the 19th century, as Roman architectural forms became increasingly popular as an expression of empire. The term “Neo-classical” was coined as early as January 1872 by Robert Kerr, who used the term positively. It later took on certain negative overtones, when it was used as a derogatory epithet by an unknown writer in the Times of London in 1892. Neoclassical architecture has fared no better with the rise of modernism in the early 20th century onward and since then it has been seen as old-fashioned and derivative. Neoclassical architecture was not a mindless i
自西罗马帝国崩溃以来,古典或希腊罗马建筑一直是表达后来文明、帝国、国家和个人的文化、艺术、政治和意识形态目标的典范。文艺复兴标志着第一次在艺术、文学和建筑方面与古代古典的广泛重新接触。关于古典古代及其与现代世界关系的争论一直持续至今。其中一个重要的争论就是古今之争,查尔斯·佩诺特在1688年出版了他的《古今之平行》。这场争论的焦点是现代能否超越古代,尤其是在文学方面。希腊罗马之争(1750年代和1760年代)是欧洲人参与古典历史的另一个例子;争论的焦点是希腊艺术和罗马艺术哪个具有更大的历史价值;争论一直持续到今天。像约翰·约阿希姆·温克尔曼这样的人物(在温克尔曼1764年等出版物中,引用于《关于希腊的早期考古出版物》和《罗马东部的古典废墟》,关于希腊艺术)主张希腊形式的至高无上,而乔瓦尼·巴蒂斯塔·皮拉内西(其1748年至1778年对罗马的看法被菲卡奇2011年转载,引用于《关于意大利的早期考古出版物》)则主张罗马的卓越地位。这样的辩论表明,古典古代是18世纪欧洲知识和艺术环境的重要组成部分。本参考书目着重于1700年至今在欧洲和北美建造形式中对古典建筑的挪用,这通常被称为新古典主义或新古典主义,两者都是可以接受的。学者们通常将新古典主义时期定义为从1750年到1830年,当时欧洲的艺术和建筑主要采用了古典主义的形式和思想。古典建筑的影响在整个19世纪和20世纪初的美国继续流行。19世纪初见证了希腊复兴运动的繁荣,希腊形式在欧洲和美国的艺术和建筑生产中占主导地位。1837年,维多利亚女王登基,标志着人们对哥特式和中世纪风格的偏好发生了转变。新古典主义形式在19世纪下半叶看到了复苏,因为罗马建筑形式作为帝国的表达越来越受欢迎。“新古典主义”一词早在1872年1月就被罗伯特·克尔创造出来,他使用了这个词的褒义。后来,1892年,一位不知名的作家在《伦敦时报》上用它作为贬义词,它带有了一定的负面意味。随着20世纪早期现代主义的兴起,新古典主义建筑并没有得到更好的发展,从那时起,它就被视为过时的衍生品。新古典主义建筑并不是对古典建筑形式和室内设计的盲目模仿。18世纪中期的重要考古发现激发了人们对古典建筑和新古典主义建筑的兴趣,拓宽了人们对希腊和罗马建筑的认识。古代建筑的非凡灵活性体现了帝国的宏伟,以及新生民主的原则,这意味着它有巨大的潜力被无数的建筑师、赞助人、帝国和民族国家以不同的方式和不同的时间从18世纪到20世纪诠释和重新诠释。这个参考书目是按主题组织的(例如,一般概述;同伴、手册和理论著作;参考书;早期一般考古出版物;接待庞贝、赫库兰尼姆和那不勒斯湾;和世界博览会),然后在地理上,创建特定国家或地区的参考书目。虽然这种组织模式有一些缺陷,但它旨在避免重复,并强调后期古典建筑接受的相互联系的本质和过程。
{"title":"Classical Architecture in Europe and North America since 1700","authors":"E. Macaulay-Lewis","doi":"10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0318","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0318","url":null,"abstract":"Since the Western Roman Empire collapsed, classical, or Greco-Roman, architecture has served as a model to articulate the cultural, artistic, political, and ideological goals of later civilizations, empires, nations, and individuals. The Renaissance marked the first major, widespread re-engagement with classical antiquity in art, literature, and architecture. Debates over classical antiquity and its relation to the modern world continued ever since. One such important debate was that of the quarrel between the Ancients and Moderns, which resulted when Charles Perrault published his Parallèles des anciens et des modernes in 1688. This dispute focused on whether the modern age could surpass antiquity, especially in literature. The Greco-Roman controversy (1750s and 1760s) was another example of Europeans engaging with the classical past; this debate focused on whether Greek or Roman art was of greater historical value; an argument has continued unabated to this day. Figures like Johann Joachim Winckelmann argued (in publications such as Winckelmann 1764, cited under Early Archaeological Publications on Greece and Classical Ruins in the Roman East, on Greek art) for the supremacy of Greek forms, while others like Giovanni Battista Piranesi (whose 1748–1778 views of Rome are reproduced in Ficacci 2011, cited under Early Archaeological Publications on Italy) advocated for Rome’s preeminence. Such debates demonstrate how classical antiquity was an essential part of the intellectual and artistic milieu of 18th-century Europe. This bibliography focuses on the appropriation of classical architecture in the creation of built forms from 1700 to the present in Europe and North America, which is typically called neoclassical or neo-classical, both of which are acceptable. Scholars often define the neoclassical period as lasting from c. 1750 to 1830, when European art and architecture predominantly appropriated classical forms and ideas. The influence of classical architecture continued in popularity throughout the 19th century and early 20th century in the United States. The early 19th century saw the flourishing of the Greek Revival, where Greek forms dominated artistic and architectural production, both in Europe and the United States. The ascendance of Queen Victoria in 1837 marked a shift toward a preference for the Gothic and Medieval forms. Neoclassical forms saw a resurgence in the second half of the 19th century, as Roman architectural forms became increasingly popular as an expression of empire. The term “Neo-classical” was coined as early as January 1872 by Robert Kerr, who used the term positively. It later took on certain negative overtones, when it was used as a derogatory epithet by an unknown writer in the Times of London in 1892. Neoclassical architecture has fared no better with the rise of modernism in the early 20th century onward and since then it has been seen as old-fashioned and derivative. Neoclassical architecture was not a mindless i","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"24 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-07-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"91063624","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Plato’s Crito 柏拉图的《克里托篇》
Pub Date : 2012-02-27 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0368
B. Plato, G. P. Rose
The Crito belongs to Plato’s early dialogues. It presents a discussion between Socrates and a long-term associate of Socrates, Crito, that takes place while Socrates is in prison awaiting his execution. Crito tries to convince Socrates to escape from prison. Socrates refuses, arguing that doing so would be unjust. The dialogue may be divided into two parts. The first part (43a1-50a5) contains Crito’s arguments in favor of Socrates’ escape and Socrates’ initial rebuttal of those arguments, based on principles that were agreed in previous discussions between Socrates and Crito. The second part (50a6-54e2) contains a new set of arguments against escape that are presented in the form of an imaginary speech of the personified laws of Athens (usually referred to as “the speech of the Laws”). The bulk of scholarly literature on the Crito focuses broadly on three topics. The first concerns the dialectic of the Crito. The second concerns the consistency between the Crito and the Apology. The main issue is that the speech of the Laws appears to make strong authoritarian claims which are not straightforwardly compatible with either Socrates’ arguments in the first part of the dialogue or the Apology. The third concerns the proper interpretation of central elements of the speech of the Laws and their relevance to contemporary debates about political obligation, the authority of law, and civil disobedience. Those elements include the option that the Laws offer to the citizens to either persuade or obey them and the arguments in favor of the citizens’ subordination to the Laws based on gratitude and the citizens’ agreement. Other topics that have received significant scholarly attention include Socrates’ rejection of retaliation in the first part of the Crito and the place of the Crito in Socrates’ political philosophy. Recently there is also growing scholarly interest in the relevance of Socrates’ general views on filial obligations to the speech of the Laws in the Crito.
克里托属于柏拉图早期的对话录。它呈现了苏格拉底和他的长期伙伴克里托之间的讨论,发生在苏格拉底在监狱里等待处决的时候。克里托试图说服苏格拉底逃离监狱。苏格拉底拒绝了,他认为这样做是不公平的。对话可分为两部分。第一部分(43a1-50a5)包含了克里托支持苏格拉底逃跑的论点,以及苏格拉底最初对这些论点的反驳,这些论点是基于苏格拉底和克里托之前讨论中达成一致的原则。第二部分(50a6-54e2)包含了一系列反对逃避的新论点,这些论点以雅典人格化法律的想象演讲的形式呈现(通常被称为“法律演讲”)。关于克里托的大量学术文献主要集中在三个主题上。第一个是关于克里托的辩证法。第二个问题是《克里托篇》和《忏悔录》之间的一致性。主要的问题是,《律法》的演讲似乎提出了强有力的权威主张,这与苏格拉底在对话的第一部分或《自辩篇》中的论点都不直接相容。第三个问题涉及对《法律》演讲的核心要素的适当解释,以及它们与当代关于政治义务、法律权威和公民不服从的辩论的相关性。这些因素包括法律为公民提供的说服或服从法律的选择,以及支持公民基于感激和公民同意而服从法律的论点。其他受到学术关注的话题包括苏格拉底在《克里托篇》的第一部分中拒绝报复,以及《克里托篇》在苏格拉底政治哲学中的地位。最近也有越来越多的学者对苏格拉底关于孝道义务的一般观点与《克里托篇》中《律法》的演讲的相关性感兴趣。
{"title":"Plato’s Crito","authors":"B. Plato, G. P. Rose","doi":"10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0368","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0368","url":null,"abstract":"The Crito belongs to Plato’s early dialogues. It presents a discussion between Socrates and a long-term associate of Socrates, Crito, that takes place while Socrates is in prison awaiting his execution. Crito tries to convince Socrates to escape from prison. Socrates refuses, arguing that doing so would be unjust. The dialogue may be divided into two parts. The first part (43a1-50a5) contains Crito’s arguments in favor of Socrates’ escape and Socrates’ initial rebuttal of those arguments, based on principles that were agreed in previous discussions between Socrates and Crito. The second part (50a6-54e2) contains a new set of arguments against escape that are presented in the form of an imaginary speech of the personified laws of Athens (usually referred to as “the speech of the Laws”). The bulk of scholarly literature on the Crito focuses broadly on three topics. The first concerns the dialectic of the Crito. The second concerns the consistency between the Crito and the Apology. The main issue is that the speech of the Laws appears to make strong authoritarian claims which are not straightforwardly compatible with either Socrates’ arguments in the first part of the dialogue or the Apology. The third concerns the proper interpretation of central elements of the speech of the Laws and their relevance to contemporary debates about political obligation, the authority of law, and civil disobedience. Those elements include the option that the Laws offer to the citizens to either persuade or obey them and the arguments in favor of the citizens’ subordination to the Laws based on gratitude and the citizens’ agreement. Other topics that have received significant scholarly attention include Socrates’ rejection of retaliation in the first part of the Crito and the place of the Crito in Socrates’ political philosophy. Recently there is also growing scholarly interest in the relevance of Socrates’ general views on filial obligations to the speech of the Laws in the Crito.","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"99 3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-02-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83327379","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Lactantius
Pub Date : 1924-12-31 DOI: 10.1163/2589-7993_eeco_sim_00001875
S. Freund
Lucius Caelius Firmianus Lactantius (c. 250–c. 325 ce) was a Christian Latin author during the Diocletianic persecution and the times of Constantine the Great. Lactantius was born in Africa, studied with the rhetor Arnobius in Sicca Veneria, and became a teacher of rhetoric himself. In about 290, Emperor Diocletian offered him a chair at the court at Nicomedia, one of the new imperial residences of the Tetrarchy. There, in 303 the author faced the beginning of the Diocletianic persecution. The injustice he believed was being done to the Christians is of utmost importance for Lactantius. In order to become the champion of the oppressed, he resolved to defend and explain the Christian faith. His first two writings conceal their Christian character: The elegy on the Phoenix (De ave Phoenice) tries to illustrate the idea of resurrection by retelling the myth of the fabulous bird which dies and comes to life again; with it Lactantius establishes a Christian Latin poetry in the classical manner. His treatise On the Workmanship of God (De opificio dei) gives a detailed account of human physiology, which suggests that it was created through the working of God’s providence. In his magnum opus, the seven books entitled Divine Institutes (Divinae institutiones), consisting of more than six hundred modern pages, Lactantius gives an apologetic overall sketch of Christian teaching for pagan readers. The Divine Institutes were finished before 311, as the whole work suggests that persecution was still in progress while it was being written. Soon after the end of persecution, i.e., in 313/314, Lactantius composed his brief work On the Deaths of the Persecutors (De mortibus persecutorum), the first Latin treatise on ecclesiastical history. When Constantine appointed Lactantius to be tutor to his son Crispus, Lactantius came to the imperial court at Trier. In the following years, Lactantius wrote On the Anger of God (De ira dei), which argues that God does indeed show wrath, and also a short version of his Divine Institutes (Epitome divinarum institutionum). An unfinished second edition of the whole Divine Institutes, which contains dedications to the emperor Constantine and passages explaining the author’s dualistic worldview, presupposes the political conditions of 324 and thus dates the author’s death to 324/325. Lactantius was read in Late Antiquity, but was often supposed to be theologically outdated or problematic. In the later Middle Ages and Renaissance, however, the “Christian Cicero,” as he was called then, was greatly admired for the way he used classical style, rhetoric, poetry, education, and mythology to explain Christianity. The Divine Institutes are contained in the first book which was printed in Italy.
卢修斯·卡里乌斯·菲尔米亚努斯·拉克坦提斯(约250-c)公元325年)是戴克里先迫害时期和君士坦丁大帝时期的一位基督教拉丁作家。拉克坦提乌斯出生于非洲,在威尼斯的西西里跟随修辞学家阿诺比乌斯学习,后来成为一名修辞学老师。大约在290年,戴克里先皇帝给他提供了尼科米底亚宫廷的职位,尼科米底亚是四帝帝国的新宫殿之一。公元303年,作者面临戴克里先迫害的开始。他认为对基督徒的不公正对待对拉克坦提乌斯来说至关重要。为了成为被压迫者的捍卫者,他决心捍卫和解释基督教信仰。他的前两部作品隐藏了他们的基督教特征:《凤凰挽歌》(De ave Phoenice)试图通过重新讲述神话中的鸟死而复活的神话来说明复活的概念;通过它,拉克坦提乌斯以古典的方式建立了基督教拉丁诗歌。他的专著《论上帝的工作》(De opificio dei)详细描述了人类的生理机能,认为人类的生理机能是由上帝的旨意创造的。在他的巨著,七本书题为神圣机构(Divinae机构),包括六百多页的现代,拉克坦提乌斯给出了一个道歉的基督教教学的异教徒读者的总体草图。《神学院》在311年之前完成,因为整个工作表明,在写作时,迫害仍在进行中。迫害结束后不久,即公元313/314年,拉克坦提乌斯撰写了他的简短著作《迫害者之死》(De mortibus persecutorum),这是第一部关于教会历史的拉丁文专著。当君士坦丁任命拉克坦提乌斯为他儿子克里斯普斯的家庭教师时,拉克坦提乌斯来到了特里尔的朝廷。在接下来的几年里,拉克坦提乌斯写了《论上帝的愤怒》(De ira dei),这本书认为上帝确实表现出愤怒,他还写了他的《神圣机构》(Epitome divinarum institutionum)的简短版本。整个《神学》的未完成的第二版,包含了对君士坦丁皇帝的献词和解释作者二元论世界观的段落,预设了324年的政治状况,从而将作者的死亡日期定在324/325年。拉克坦提乌斯的著作是在古代晚期读到的,但通常被认为在神学上是过时的或有问题的。然而,在中世纪晚期和文艺复兴时期,这位当时被称为“基督教西塞罗”的人,因其运用古典风格、修辞、诗歌、教育和神话来解释基督教而备受推崇。《神学院》包含在意大利印刷的第一本书中。
{"title":"Lactantius","authors":"S. Freund","doi":"10.1163/2589-7993_eeco_sim_00001875","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/2589-7993_eeco_sim_00001875","url":null,"abstract":"Lucius Caelius Firmianus Lactantius (c. 250–c. 325 ce) was a Christian Latin author during the Diocletianic persecution and the times of Constantine the Great. Lactantius was born in Africa, studied with the rhetor Arnobius in Sicca Veneria, and became a teacher of rhetoric himself. In about 290, Emperor Diocletian offered him a chair at the court at Nicomedia, one of the new imperial residences of the Tetrarchy. There, in 303 the author faced the beginning of the Diocletianic persecution. The injustice he believed was being done to the Christians is of utmost importance for Lactantius. In order to become the champion of the oppressed, he resolved to defend and explain the Christian faith. His first two writings conceal their Christian character: The elegy on the Phoenix (De ave Phoenice) tries to illustrate the idea of resurrection by retelling the myth of the fabulous bird which dies and comes to life again; with it Lactantius establishes a Christian Latin poetry in the classical manner. His treatise On the Workmanship of God (De opificio dei) gives a detailed account of human physiology, which suggests that it was created through the working of God’s providence. In his magnum opus, the seven books entitled Divine Institutes (Divinae institutiones), consisting of more than six hundred modern pages, Lactantius gives an apologetic overall sketch of Christian teaching for pagan readers. The Divine Institutes were finished before 311, as the whole work suggests that persecution was still in progress while it was being written. Soon after the end of persecution, i.e., in 313/314, Lactantius composed his brief work On the Deaths of the Persecutors (De mortibus persecutorum), the first Latin treatise on ecclesiastical history. When Constantine appointed Lactantius to be tutor to his son Crispus, Lactantius came to the imperial court at Trier. In the following years, Lactantius wrote On the Anger of God (De ira dei), which argues that God does indeed show wrath, and also a short version of his Divine Institutes (Epitome divinarum institutionum). An unfinished second edition of the whole Divine Institutes, which contains dedications to the emperor Constantine and passages explaining the author’s dualistic worldview, presupposes the political conditions of 324 and thus dates the author’s death to 324/325. Lactantius was read in Late Antiquity, but was often supposed to be theologically outdated or problematic. In the later Middle Ages and Renaissance, however, the “Christian Cicero,” as he was called then, was greatly admired for the way he used classical style, rhetoric, poetry, education, and mythology to explain Christianity. The Divine Institutes are contained in the first book which was printed in Italy.","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"21 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1924-12-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86988611","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Greek Domestic Architecture c. 800 bce to c. 100 bce 希腊家庭建筑:公元前800年至公元前100年
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0364
This article discusses research on the housing of culturally-Greek settlements dating between c. 800 bce and c. 100 bce but with an emphasis on the central part of this period, and offers an overview of the various approaches. (Information on individual sites can be found by consulting the volumes listed under Period-Specific Overviews). While surviving textual sources shaped early research, relevant surviving texts are very limited in their number and scope. The most detailed source of information about Greek domestic architecture (and also about the organization of domestic activities) is the excavated remains of the houses themselves, which offer access to a wider range of aspects of the construction, in a greater variety of locations. Although the domestic buildings in ancient Greek settlements have historically received less attention from excavators than monumental civic and religious ones, sufficient evidence exists from which to generalize, and the available database continues to grow. This, coupled with the application of ever more sophisticated theoretical frameworks and archaeological field methods, has meant that the majority of current scholarship has come to focus on excavated houses. Over more than 150 years of research, the questions asked about domestic architecture have shifted, from the basic appearance of a house or attempts to ascertain how closely archaeological findings map onto the descriptions of ancient writers, toward analyses of a range of larger issues which include social relationships, the organization of the domestic economy, the cultural identities of households in various parts of the Mediterranean, and the way in which households changed between the earlier first millennium bce and Roman times. Throughout the period covered here, it is impossible to be certain whether the small sample of houses that have been excavated is representative of the range that were originally inhabited: it is likely that the homes of wealthier members of society are over-represented, since they were probably larger and more sturdily-built, hence surviving better in the archaeological record and more easily identified and excavated by archaeologists.
本文讨论了公元前800年至公元前100年文化希腊定居点的住房研究,但重点放在这一时期的中心部分,并提供了各种方法的概述。(个别地点的信息可参考特定时期概述下列出的卷)。虽然幸存的文本来源塑造了早期的研究,但相关的幸存文本在数量和范围上都非常有限。关于希腊家庭建筑(以及家庭活动的组织)最详细的信息来源是房屋本身的挖掘遗迹,它提供了更广泛的建筑方面,在更多不同的地点。尽管在历史上,古希腊居民点的住宅建筑受到挖掘者的关注要少于纪念性的市政和宗教建筑,但有足够的证据可供总结,而且可用的数据库也在不断增长。这一点,再加上越来越复杂的理论框架和考古现场方法的应用,意味着目前大多数学术研究都集中在挖掘出来的房屋上。在150多年的研究中,关于家庭建筑的问题已经发生了变化,从房子的基本外观,或者试图确定考古发现与古代作家的描述有多接近,转向分析一系列更大的问题,包括社会关系、家庭经济的组织、地中海不同地区家庭的文化特征、以及从公元前一千年早期到罗马时代家庭的变化方式。在本文所涵盖的整个时期内,我们无法确定出土的小样本房屋是否代表了最初有人居住的范围:很可能是社会中较富裕成员的房屋过多,因为它们可能更大,建筑更坚固,因此在考古记录中保存得更好,更容易被考古学家识别和挖掘。
{"title":"Greek Domestic Architecture c. 800 bce to c. 100 bce","authors":"","doi":"10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0364","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0364","url":null,"abstract":"This article discusses research on the housing of culturally-Greek settlements dating between c. 800 bce and c. 100 bce but with an emphasis on the central part of this period, and offers an overview of the various approaches. (Information on individual sites can be found by consulting the volumes listed under Period-Specific Overviews). While surviving textual sources shaped early research, relevant surviving texts are very limited in their number and scope. The most detailed source of information about Greek domestic architecture (and also about the organization of domestic activities) is the excavated remains of the houses themselves, which offer access to a wider range of aspects of the construction, in a greater variety of locations. Although the domestic buildings in ancient Greek settlements have historically received less attention from excavators than monumental civic and religious ones, sufficient evidence exists from which to generalize, and the available database continues to grow. This, coupled with the application of ever more sophisticated theoretical frameworks and archaeological field methods, has meant that the majority of current scholarship has come to focus on excavated houses. Over more than 150 years of research, the questions asked about domestic architecture have shifted, from the basic appearance of a house or attempts to ascertain how closely archaeological findings map onto the descriptions of ancient writers, toward analyses of a range of larger issues which include social relationships, the organization of the domestic economy, the cultural identities of households in various parts of the Mediterranean, and the way in which households changed between the earlier first millennium bce and Roman times. Throughout the period covered here, it is impossible to be certain whether the small sample of houses that have been excavated is representative of the range that were originally inhabited: it is likely that the homes of wealthier members of society are over-represented, since they were probably larger and more sturdily-built, hence surviving better in the archaeological record and more easily identified and excavated by archaeologists.","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"7 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88571358","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Cicero’s Philosophical Works 西塞罗的哲学著作
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0361
Cicero (106–43 bce) was a Roman statesman, orator, and philosopher. As well as speeches, letters, and rhetorical treatises, Cicero wrote numerous philosophical works. These can be divided into two periods—those written before the civil war between Julius Caesar and Pompey the Great (pre-49 bce), and those written during and after it (46 bce onward). Those written before are in dialogue form and the central topics are political: the ideal orator (De Oratore), the best citizen and the best state (De Re Publica), the best laws (De Legibus). Those following are predominately part of an ambitious project to bring philosophy to Rome in a systematic fashion; they are also mainly in dialogue form. Cicero composed an exhortation to philosophy (Hortensius), followed by books on epistemology (Academica, Lucullus) and works on broadly ethical concerns—the nature of good and evil (De Finibus); honor and glory (De Gloria); old age and friendship (De Senectute, De Amicitia); the soul, death, and suffering (Tusculans); consolation (Consolatio); the nature of the gods, divination, and providence (De Natura Deorum, De Divinatione, De Fato). Cicero’s final philosophical work is the De Officiis, presented as a letter to his son. Philosophy also figures prominently throughout Cicero’s letters, speeches, and rhetorical works. Indeed, it should be noted that Cicero felt his rhetorical works Orator and Brutus should be included in his philosophical corpus (Div. 2.4). There are two schools of thought on the novelty and value of Cicero’s philosophical works: (1) he is essentially just repackaging Greek material in Latin, offering renditions of existing ideas that are invaluable for saving much of the lost tradition of Hellenistic philosophy; (2) he is doing something more than that, developing distinctive philosophical contributions of his own. Most recent studies stress the innovative elements of Cicero’s philosophical thinking. Cicero’s own philosophical convictions are varied. Stoicism figures largely, as does his sympathy with Plato, Aristotle, and the Academic and Peripatetic traditions that follow them. He is strongly anti-Epicurean in both periods of his philosophical activity. Most scholars maintain that he is a pragmatic and flexible Academic skeptic, who weighs both sides of every argument and gives his assent to whatever he finds most compelling given the particular circumstances. Ostensibly a lack of political opportunity motivated Cicero to write philosophy. In the prefaces to his philosophical works he insists that it is not an escape from politics, but an intervention in it by other means.
西塞罗(公元前106-43年)是罗马政治家、演说家和哲学家。除了演讲、信件和修辞论文外,西塞罗还写了许多哲学著作。这些可以分为两个时期——写于恺撒大帝和庞培大帝内战之前(公元前49年以前)的时期,以及写于内战期间和之后(公元前46年以后)的时期。之前写的都是对话形式,中心话题是政治:理想的演说家(De Oratore),最好的公民和最好的国家(De Re Publica),最好的法律(De Legibus)。下面这些主要是一个雄心勃勃的计划的一部分,以系统的方式将哲学带到罗马;它们也以对话形式为主。西塞罗写了一本哲学劝诫书(Hortensius),接着写了认识论的书(Academica, Lucullus),以及关于广泛伦理问题的著作——善与恶的本质(De Finibus);荣誉和荣耀(De Gloria);老年与友谊(De Senectute, De Amicitia);灵魂、死亡和痛苦(图斯图兰人);安慰(Consolatio);神、占卜和天意的本质(De Natura Deorum, De divinationone, De Fato)。西塞罗最后的哲学著作是《论官职》,是写给他儿子的一封信。哲学在西塞罗的书信、演讲和修辞作品中也占有重要地位。事实上,应该指出的是,西塞罗认为他的修辞作品《演说家》和《布鲁图斯》应该被包括在他的哲学语料库中(第2.4节)。关于西塞罗哲学著作的新颖性和价值,有两种观点:(1)他本质上只是用拉丁语重新包装了希腊材料,提供了对现有思想的演绎,这些思想对于拯救许多失落的希腊哲学传统是无价的;(2)他所做的远不止于此,他正在形成自己独特的哲学贡献。最近的研究大多强调西塞罗哲学思想的创新元素。西塞罗自己的哲学信仰是多种多样的。斯多葛主义的影响很大,他对柏拉图、亚里士多德的同情,以及他们之后的学术和游学传统也是如此。他在两个哲学活动时期都强烈反对伊壁鸠鲁主义。大多数学者认为他是一个务实和灵活的学术怀疑论者,他权衡每一个论点的双方,并在特定情况下同意他认为最令人信服的任何东西。表面上看,缺乏政治机会促使西塞罗写哲学。在他的哲学著作的序言中,他坚持认为这不是对政治的逃避,而是通过其他方式对政治的干预。
{"title":"Cicero’s Philosophical Works","authors":"","doi":"10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0361","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0361","url":null,"abstract":"Cicero (106–43 bce) was a Roman statesman, orator, and philosopher. As well as speeches, letters, and rhetorical treatises, Cicero wrote numerous philosophical works. These can be divided into two periods—those written before the civil war between Julius Caesar and Pompey the Great (pre-49 bce), and those written during and after it (46 bce onward). Those written before are in dialogue form and the central topics are political: the ideal orator (De Oratore), the best citizen and the best state (De Re Publica), the best laws (De Legibus). Those following are predominately part of an ambitious project to bring philosophy to Rome in a systematic fashion; they are also mainly in dialogue form. Cicero composed an exhortation to philosophy (Hortensius), followed by books on epistemology (Academica, Lucullus) and works on broadly ethical concerns—the nature of good and evil (De Finibus); honor and glory (De Gloria); old age and friendship (De Senectute, De Amicitia); the soul, death, and suffering (Tusculans); consolation (Consolatio); the nature of the gods, divination, and providence (De Natura Deorum, De Divinatione, De Fato). Cicero’s final philosophical work is the De Officiis, presented as a letter to his son. Philosophy also figures prominently throughout Cicero’s letters, speeches, and rhetorical works. Indeed, it should be noted that Cicero felt his rhetorical works Orator and Brutus should be included in his philosophical corpus (Div. 2.4). There are two schools of thought on the novelty and value of Cicero’s philosophical works: (1) he is essentially just repackaging Greek material in Latin, offering renditions of existing ideas that are invaluable for saving much of the lost tradition of Hellenistic philosophy; (2) he is doing something more than that, developing distinctive philosophical contributions of his own. Most recent studies stress the innovative elements of Cicero’s philosophical thinking. Cicero’s own philosophical convictions are varied. Stoicism figures largely, as does his sympathy with Plato, Aristotle, and the Academic and Peripatetic traditions that follow them. He is strongly anti-Epicurean in both periods of his philosophical activity. Most scholars maintain that he is a pragmatic and flexible Academic skeptic, who weighs both sides of every argument and gives his assent to whatever he finds most compelling given the particular circumstances. Ostensibly a lack of political opportunity motivated Cicero to write philosophy. In the prefaces to his philosophical works he insists that it is not an escape from politics, but an intervention in it by other means.","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"41 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90267462","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Theoderic the Great and Ostrogothic Italy 狄奥德里克大帝和东哥特意大利
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0363
The Ostrogothic king Theoderic is the only non-Roman ruler of Late Antiquity to have acquired the epithet the Great, albeit only in modern times. Born around 453 in Pannonia (Hungary) as the son of a Gothic king named Thiudimir, he grew up in Constantinople, where he was held as a hostage for ten years. He returned to Pannonia in 471, in 474 succeeding his father, who had meanwhile led the “Pannonian Goths” into Macedonia. For several years Theoderic fought a Gothic king and rival claimant to imperial favor likewise named Theoderic whose power base was in Thrace (hence “Thracian Goths”). Only after the latter’s death in 481 did he succeed in uniting the two groups under his leadership. Although he was subsequently appointed magister militum and held the consulship in 484, relations with the emperor Zeno soon became hostile. In 488, Theoderic and Zeno made an agreement that Theoderic should take his people to Italy and eliminate Odovacer. After a devastating war, he slew Odovacer by his own hand in March 493, in breach of an oath sworn shortly before to share rule in Italy. Having secured sole rule in Italy, Theoderic turned his mobile and militarized followers into a standing army by allotting them ownership rights to landed estates (rather than shares in land tax, as some have argued). He defined his position as ruler over two peoples, Goths and Romans, to which he assigned complementary but separate roles (“integration by separation”). While Goths were warriors by definition, the civilian population was labeled Roman. Theoderic won over the senatorial elites by preserving their privileges, wealth, and social power and by giving them a share in his rule. He left the administrative structures of the Late Roman state largely unaltered and filled all positions of a civilian nature with people from the senatorial milieu. Although he belonged to a Christian denomination considered heretical by Catholics (“Arian”) he treated Catholic bishops with respect; they in turn asked him to act as an arbitrator when in 498 Symmachus and Laurentius were simultaneously elected to be bishop of Rome. From 508 to 511 he extended his rule over Provence and the Iberian peninsula. Relations with the senatorial elites and the Roman church became strained at the end of Theoderic’s life. He died in Ravenna on 30 August 526 without having nominated an heir to the throne. His kingdom fell within a generation after his death, but his memory lived on in Italy and in all Germanic-speaking lands where legend transformed him into Dietrich of Berne.
东哥特国王狄奥德里克是古代晚期唯一一位获得“大帝”称号的非罗马统治者,尽管只是在现代。公元453年左右,他出生于潘诺尼亚(匈牙利),父亲是一位名叫蒂乌迪米尔的哥特国王。他在君士坦丁堡长大,并在那里被扣为人质长达十年之久。他于471年接替他的父亲回到潘诺尼亚,在此期间,他的父亲曾率领“潘诺尼亚的哥特人”进入马其顿。几年来,狄奥德里克与一个同样名叫狄奥德里克的哥特国王作战,后者的权力基础在色雷斯(因此被称为“色雷斯哥特人”)。直到后者于481年去世后,他才成功地将这两个团体统一在他的领导下。虽然他后来被任命为军事长官,并于484年担任执政官,但他与皇帝芝诺的关系很快变得敌对。公元488年,狄奥德里克和芝诺达成协议,要求狄奥德里克带领他的人民前往意大利,消灭奥多瓦塞。在一场毁灭性的战争之后,他在493年3月亲手杀死了奥多瓦塞,这违反了他前不久宣誓分享意大利统治权的誓言。在确保了对意大利的唯一统治之后,狄奥德里克把他的流动的、军事化的追随者变成了常备军,给他们分配了土地所有权(而不是像一些人所说的那样分享土地税)。他将自己的地位定义为哥特人和罗马人这两个民族的统治者,并赋予这两个民族互补但独立的角色(“通过分离来整合”)。哥特人被定义为战士,而平民则被称为罗马人。狄奥德里克赢得了元老院精英的支持,他保留了他们的特权、财富和社会权力,并让他们分享他的统治。他没有改变晚期罗马国家的行政结构,而是用元老院出身的人填补了所有平民职位。虽然他属于被天主教徒视为异端的基督教教派(“阿里乌斯”),但他尊重天主教主教;当西马丘斯和劳伦提乌斯在498年同时被选为罗马主教时,他们又要求他担任仲裁者。从508年到511年,他扩大了对普罗旺斯和伊比利亚半岛的统治。狄奥德里克晚年与元老院精英和罗马教会的关系变得紧张起来。他于526年8月30日在拉文纳去世,没有提名王位继承人。他的王国在他死后不到一代人就灭亡了,但他的记忆在意大利和所有说日耳曼语的地方永远流传着,传说把他变成了伯尔尼的迪特里希。
{"title":"Theoderic the Great and Ostrogothic Italy","authors":"","doi":"10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0363","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0363","url":null,"abstract":"The Ostrogothic king Theoderic is the only non-Roman ruler of Late Antiquity to have acquired the epithet the Great, albeit only in modern times. Born around 453 in Pannonia (Hungary) as the son of a Gothic king named Thiudimir, he grew up in Constantinople, where he was held as a hostage for ten years. He returned to Pannonia in 471, in 474 succeeding his father, who had meanwhile led the “Pannonian Goths” into Macedonia. For several years Theoderic fought a Gothic king and rival claimant to imperial favor likewise named Theoderic whose power base was in Thrace (hence “Thracian Goths”). Only after the latter’s death in 481 did he succeed in uniting the two groups under his leadership. Although he was subsequently appointed magister militum and held the consulship in 484, relations with the emperor Zeno soon became hostile. In 488, Theoderic and Zeno made an agreement that Theoderic should take his people to Italy and eliminate Odovacer. After a devastating war, he slew Odovacer by his own hand in March 493, in breach of an oath sworn shortly before to share rule in Italy. Having secured sole rule in Italy, Theoderic turned his mobile and militarized followers into a standing army by allotting them ownership rights to landed estates (rather than shares in land tax, as some have argued). He defined his position as ruler over two peoples, Goths and Romans, to which he assigned complementary but separate roles (“integration by separation”). While Goths were warriors by definition, the civilian population was labeled Roman. Theoderic won over the senatorial elites by preserving their privileges, wealth, and social power and by giving them a share in his rule. He left the administrative structures of the Late Roman state largely unaltered and filled all positions of a civilian nature with people from the senatorial milieu. Although he belonged to a Christian denomination considered heretical by Catholics (“Arian”) he treated Catholic bishops with respect; they in turn asked him to act as an arbitrator when in 498 Symmachus and Laurentius were simultaneously elected to be bishop of Rome. From 508 to 511 he extended his rule over Provence and the Iberian peninsula. Relations with the senatorial elites and the Roman church became strained at the end of Theoderic’s life. He died in Ravenna on 30 August 526 without having nominated an heir to the throne. His kingdom fell within a generation after his death, but his memory lived on in Italy and in all Germanic-speaking lands where legend transformed him into Dietrich of Berne.","PeriodicalId":82164,"journal":{"name":"Nigeria and the classics","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81346361","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Nigeria and the classics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1