{"title":"Does Art Have A Truth-Seeking Project?","authors":"S. Schlassa","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1174","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1174","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"17 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123740863","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
This paper examines the emotional and social motivations of belief and belief correction. As beliefs motivate one’s actions, one must examine how one revises an erroneous or harmful belief and what methodology one can employ in order to best facilitate this revision, resulting in more conscientious action. This paper examines belief formation and revision in the context of David Hume’s 1739-1740 work A Treatise of Human Nature, with particular attention to not only Hume’s account of belief and belief revision, but also the interaction of passions, the mechanism of sympathy, reason, and probability judgments. It is hypothesized Hume’s theory of belief will be reflected in contemporary psychology and cognitive science, with individuals more likely to revise their beliefs based emotional and social factors and experiences proposed by Hume. Sarah Paquette Portland State University s.a.paquette@icloud.com https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1173 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1173 Res Cogitans Introduction David Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature maintains a uniquely prescient outlook in philosophy, as well as contemporary cognitive research. As Hume recognized, not only the relationship between philosophy and science, but that science can be used to examine human nature,1 he set his sights on uncovering the science of the mind, posited as discoverable using a framework established by the sciences of the time: observation and experimentation. We must first understand the mind in order to understand other sciences, as the mind is the foundation upon which all other sciences rest.2 Hume hypothesized that this new science of the mind is deciphered through “cautious observation of human life,” best conducted in their natural environments as they occur, and in all manner of states.3 Considering Hume’s empirical framework and dedication to uncovering the natural operations of the mind, he may well have been one of the first psychologists in the contemporary sense of the word, fitting cognitive research into his philosophical objectives rather neatly. It is my intention to assess Hume’s account of belief and to further analyze the contributions the Treatise may have granted contemporary psychology. In order to explore the subject, it becomes imperative to examine Hume’s account of belief, probability, passions, and the mechanism of sympathy. I therefore aim to establish Hume’s outlined theory will be reflected in contemporary research, with individuals being more likely to revise beliefs based on emotions, as proposed by Hume. Hume’s Treatise Examined Belief & Probability Belief, defined by Hume, is any opinion or recollection that is “a lively idea related with a present impression”.4 This proposes that beliefs are informed by conceptions of past experiences captured with sensory, cognitive, and passionate faculties. An 1 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Edited by David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), T Intr
本文考察了信念和信念矫正的情感动机和社会动机。当信念激发一个人的行为时,一个人必须检查如何修正错误或有害的信念,以及为了最好地促进这种修正,可以使用什么方法,从而产生更认真的行动。本文以休谟1739-1740年的著作《人性论》为背景,考察了信念的形成和修正,不仅关注了休谟对信念和信念修正的描述,还关注了激情、同情、理性和概率判断机制的相互作用。假设休谟的信念理论将反映在当代心理学和认知科学中,个体更有可能根据休谟提出的情感和社会因素和经验来修正他们的信念。萨拉·帕奎特波特兰州立大学s.a.paquette@icloud.com https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1173卷9,第1期Res Cogitans 2 | eP1173 Res Cogitans引言大卫·休谟的《人性论》在哲学和当代认知研究中保持了独特的先见之明。休谟不仅认识到哲学和科学之间的关系,而且认识到科学可以用来检验人性,因此他把目光投向了揭示心灵科学,并假定可以利用当时科学建立的框架来发现:观察和实验。为了理解其他科学,我们必须首先了解心灵,因为心灵是所有其他科学赖以建立的基础休谟假设,这门新的心灵科学是通过“对人类生活的谨慎观察”来解读的,最好是在他们发生的自然环境中,在各种状态下进行考虑到休谟的经验框架和对揭示心灵自然运作的奉献,他很可能是当代意义上的第一批心理学家之一,将认知研究相当利落地融入了他的哲学目标。我的目的是评估休谟对信仰的描述,并进一步分析《人性论》对当代心理学的贡献。为了探究这一主题,有必要考察休谟对信念、概率、激情和同情机制的描述。因此,我的目标是建立休谟概述的理论将在当代研究中得到反映,正如休谟所提出的那样,个人更有可能根据情绪来修改信念。休谟对信念的定义是:“与当前印象相关的生动的想法”,即任何观点或回忆这一理论提出,信念是由感官、认知和激情官能捕捉到的过去经历的概念所决定的。1大卫·休谟:《人性论》,大卫·福特·诺顿和玛丽·j·诺顿主编(牛津:牛津大学出版社,2009),T导论第4页;SBN x. 2 T引言7;SBN xvi-xvii。3《导论》10;SBN xviii-xix。例如,观察别人的快乐。4 t 1.3.7.5;SBN 96。帕奎特|信念修正commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans eP1173 | 3想法是原始印象的模糊副本;这些复制品具有与原作相同的激情和回忆的感官功能,但在力量和活力上不那么有力。它们存在于想象和记忆中,就像一个可供绘画的储存库我们必须首先经历印象,形成导致判断和信仰的观念;由此可见,当我们做出因果判断时,我们仅仅是基于从过去印象中收集到的信息进行评估。这一过程始于我们最初的印象和对因果关系的持续联系的感知重复的经历会形成一种信念习惯,这种习惯会为我们的期望和对未来的判断提供基础对印象的记忆会被相似的印象重新激活,通过相似的因素:邻近、相似和接近。因此,我们假设我们过去的经历与我们未来的经历是相似的。因此,对因果关系的信念、观点和期望是反复经历的结果重要的是要注意与信仰有关的感觉的重要性。信仰不仅仅是想象力的锻炼。我们的头脑可以容纳许多东西——他称之为遐想——但这并不意味着所有理解的都被相信要表示同意,必须有一个与当前印象有关的生动的想法休谟断言,信仰不是建立在理性的基础上的,而是建立在有力而生动的感知上的,这种感知能使激情和对快乐与痛苦的概念活跃起来这个过程伴随着记忆和想象。
{"title":"Belief Revision in the Context of Hume’s Treatise and Contemporary Psychology","authors":"Sarah Paquette","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1173","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1173","url":null,"abstract":"This paper examines the emotional and social motivations of belief and belief correction. As beliefs motivate one’s actions, one must examine how one revises an erroneous or harmful belief and what methodology one can employ in order to best facilitate this revision, resulting in more conscientious action. This paper examines belief formation and revision in the context of David Hume’s 1739-1740 work A Treatise of Human Nature, with particular attention to not only Hume’s account of belief and belief revision, but also the interaction of passions, the mechanism of sympathy, reason, and probability judgments. It is hypothesized Hume’s theory of belief will be reflected in contemporary psychology and cognitive science, with individuals more likely to revise their beliefs based emotional and social factors and experiences proposed by Hume. Sarah Paquette Portland State University s.a.paquette@icloud.com https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1173 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1173 Res Cogitans Introduction David Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature maintains a uniquely prescient outlook in philosophy, as well as contemporary cognitive research. As Hume recognized, not only the relationship between philosophy and science, but that science can be used to examine human nature,1 he set his sights on uncovering the science of the mind, posited as discoverable using a framework established by the sciences of the time: observation and experimentation. We must first understand the mind in order to understand other sciences, as the mind is the foundation upon which all other sciences rest.2 Hume hypothesized that this new science of the mind is deciphered through “cautious observation of human life,” best conducted in their natural environments as they occur, and in all manner of states.3 Considering Hume’s empirical framework and dedication to uncovering the natural operations of the mind, he may well have been one of the first psychologists in the contemporary sense of the word, fitting cognitive research into his philosophical objectives rather neatly. It is my intention to assess Hume’s account of belief and to further analyze the contributions the Treatise may have granted contemporary psychology. In order to explore the subject, it becomes imperative to examine Hume’s account of belief, probability, passions, and the mechanism of sympathy. I therefore aim to establish Hume’s outlined theory will be reflected in contemporary research, with individuals being more likely to revise beliefs based on emotions, as proposed by Hume. Hume’s Treatise Examined Belief & Probability Belief, defined by Hume, is any opinion or recollection that is “a lively idea related with a present impression”.4 This proposes that beliefs are informed by conceptions of past experiences captured with sensory, cognitive, and passionate faculties. An 1 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Edited by David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), T Intr","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"306 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114589585","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Albert Camus’ idea of the absurd lands one in nihilism and the danger of rationally justified suicide. His attempt to solve this problem fails because it requires that one make an arbitrary choice to live without having good reasons to do so. By using Levinas’ ethics of an infinite responsibility and distinguishing between two types of meaning (cosmic and terrestrial), I propose that one can accept the condition of the absurd—where no cosmic meaning exists—and escape the problem of suicide by finding terrestrial meaning in our relations to others. Susana Camacho Plascencia Central Washington University camachopls@cwu.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1176 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1176 Res Cogitans Should people live or commit suicide? This is what Camus considers the most important question in philosophy, and he sets out to answer it by discussing the absurd. The absurd is the desire to find meaning in a world that does not have any; but Camus tries to answer the basic question of life or suicide in favor of life by proposing that people choose to live despite the lack of meaning. His solution is not very convincing; the absurd leaves people without meaning or the possibility for ethics. By considering Levinas’ ethical relation of the one and the other, one can embrace the absurd and still have meaning in their lives. This way, there is a convincing answer that people should live. From the individualistic view he adopts, Camus focuses on cosmic meaning, which is meaning within the world. His rational approach prevents him from recognizing terrestrial meaning, which is found in people’s lives and is independent of the world. What Levinas describes as meaning in the relation of the one to the other is a type of terrestrial meaning, and one that is significant without being arbitrary. Camus’ claim that people can be happy living with the absurd fails to avoid suicide because the arbitrary choice that would bring someone happiness is inconsistent with the passivity of the absurd. Since meaning is necessary for life and happiness, one cannot genuinely live happily by accepting Camus’ idea of the absurd without any meaning. In addition to a lack of meaning, Camus’ idea of the absurd has no possibility for a valid ethics. I propose that instead of arbitrarily choosing to be happy while living without any meaning, people should embrace the absurd in relation to the world and recognize the possibility to find meaning in the ethical relation to others. In The Myth of Sisyphus (MS), Albert Camus introduces the idea of the absurd, which is the contrast between the reality of the meaninglessness of the world and the human desire to find meaning in it. He says that the world is not rational in a way that coincides with human reason, and “What is absurd is the confrontation of this irrational and the wild longing for clarity whose call echoes in the human heart” (MS 455). The world is indifferent to human beings, who are just another species res
这个世界必须被理解为没有任何人类特征;它对人类的命运漠不关心(以一种无意识的方式),它不能被称为理性或非理性。荒谬是人类想要在这个世界上找到理由和意义的欲望,就好像它们是这个世界固有的属性一样,而实际上它们并不是。在这个冷漠的世界里,科学不能给予它真正的知识,因为它只能找到原因而不能找到目的。有了这种解释,我们就可以从新的角度来看待生活中的普通事件。如果在一个雨水稀少的地方突然下雨,而一个讨厌下雨的人正在结婚,这并不意味着这个人正在受到上帝或其他更高权力的惩罚。这也不是婚礼的预兆,也与相关人员没有任何关系。这纯粹是出于偶然;在一个事情毫无原因地发生的世界里,一切都取决于机遇——这个世界就是这样,并不关心生活在其中的人类。加缪的荒谬观念可以被理性地接受,尤其是在上帝观念消亡之后;没有比这更高的力量能定义人类的生命是有意义的,并赋予他们目标。即使是经验科学也不能提供任何喘息的机会;这个世界没有固有的意义。这种意义的缺乏会导致虚无主义,这是“生活的明显无意义,在近代西方历史中,由于以前给予生活一致性和方向的评价结构的破产而带来的”(伍德沃德,544)。当上帝的观念具有很大影响力时,那些指导人们生活的结构随着宗教信仰的丧失和荒谬观念的诞生而崩溃。上帝的死意味着人类应该如何生活不再有指导;没有更高的目标,也没有指导我们如何去实现它。这种观念不容易被理性或其他道德权威所取代。虚无主义的问题在于,因为没有意义。这个观点来自德国哲学家弗里德里希·尼采,他在《快乐的科学》中声称“上帝已经死了”。第9卷,第1期Res Cogitans 4 | eP1176 Res Cogitans,没有活下去的理由,自杀成了最好的选择。还有一个问题是,没有意义就没有道德的可能性。西蒙娜·德·波伏娃指出:“荒谬挑战每一种伦理”(413页)。这是因为在荒谬中,没有任何东西可以帮助人们区分好与坏。在荒谬的情况下,区分好与坏变得无关紧要,因为所有的行动和行为都有同样的意义——那就是没有意义。加缪认识到虚无主义可能导致理性合理的自杀,所以他继续提出了一种避免自杀的方法,同时接受了荒谬的想法。他说,荒谬的人“可以决定接受这样一个宇宙,并从中汲取力量,拒绝希望,以及没有安慰的生活的坚定证据”(BW 484)。人们不应该试图通过在没有意义的地方寻找意义来避免生活的荒谬,也不应该通过自杀来避免。他们应该做的是接受荒谬的想法,选择快乐,尽管世界毫无意义。因为生活缺乏意义,对加缪来说,一种生活并不比另一种生活好;一个人过什么样的生活并不重要,重要的是生活的长短。“一方面,荒谬教导我们所有的经验都是不重要的,另一方面,它促使我们追求最大量的经验”(加缪,BW 485)。简而言之,加缪的解决方案要求人们接受荒谬——生活中缺乏意义——并决定尽管缺乏意义也要快乐。这个解决方案的问题在于,它要求人们选择活下去而不是自杀,却没有给出一个好的理由。这个解决方案与荒谬不符;荒谬是一种被动性,因为不管人们是否愿意看到它,它都是存在的。催促人们去拥抱荒谬,然后又告诉他们要用自己的自由意志,在一个荒谬的世界里选择快乐,这是不一致的。加缪意识到荒谬使人陷入困境,他写道:“我必须承认,这种挣扎意味着完全没有希望(这与绝望无关),持续的拒绝(这不能与放弃混淆)和有意识的不满(这不能与不成熟的不安相比)”(BW 462)。处理荒谬带来了一种无望,阻止了任何意义的接受,而这种意义的缺乏是令人不满的。加缪说,绝望并不会使人陷入绝望,但完全没有希望才是绝望。他说,拒绝这种无意义的生活并不等于放弃它,不满意并不是一种暂时的东西,人们希望它会变得更好。但如果一个人拒绝一切意义,那他活着就没有什么意义了。如果什么都不重要,那么活下去也不重要。
{"title":"Camus and Levinas: Embracing the Absurd While Finding Meaning","authors":"Susana Camacho Plascencia","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1176","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1176","url":null,"abstract":"Albert Camus’ idea of the absurd lands one in nihilism and the danger of rationally justified suicide. His attempt to solve this problem fails because it requires that one make an arbitrary choice to live without having good reasons to do so. By using Levinas’ ethics of an infinite responsibility and distinguishing between two types of meaning (cosmic and terrestrial), I propose that one can accept the condition of the absurd—where no cosmic meaning exists—and escape the problem of suicide by finding terrestrial meaning in our relations to others. Susana Camacho Plascencia Central Washington University camachopls@cwu.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1176 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1176 Res Cogitans Should people live or commit suicide? This is what Camus considers the most important question in philosophy, and he sets out to answer it by discussing the absurd. The absurd is the desire to find meaning in a world that does not have any; but Camus tries to answer the basic question of life or suicide in favor of life by proposing that people choose to live despite the lack of meaning. His solution is not very convincing; the absurd leaves people without meaning or the possibility for ethics. By considering Levinas’ ethical relation of the one and the other, one can embrace the absurd and still have meaning in their lives. This way, there is a convincing answer that people should live. From the individualistic view he adopts, Camus focuses on cosmic meaning, which is meaning within the world. His rational approach prevents him from recognizing terrestrial meaning, which is found in people’s lives and is independent of the world. What Levinas describes as meaning in the relation of the one to the other is a type of terrestrial meaning, and one that is significant without being arbitrary. Camus’ claim that people can be happy living with the absurd fails to avoid suicide because the arbitrary choice that would bring someone happiness is inconsistent with the passivity of the absurd. Since meaning is necessary for life and happiness, one cannot genuinely live happily by accepting Camus’ idea of the absurd without any meaning. In addition to a lack of meaning, Camus’ idea of the absurd has no possibility for a valid ethics. I propose that instead of arbitrarily choosing to be happy while living without any meaning, people should embrace the absurd in relation to the world and recognize the possibility to find meaning in the ethical relation to others. In The Myth of Sisyphus (MS), Albert Camus introduces the idea of the absurd, which is the contrast between the reality of the meaninglessness of the world and the human desire to find meaning in it. He says that the world is not rational in a way that coincides with human reason, and “What is absurd is the confrontation of this irrational and the wild longing for clarity whose call echoes in the human heart” (MS 455). The world is indifferent to human beings, who are just another species res","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"29 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126398122","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Ignazio Silone’s novel Bread and Wine explores the complex nature of ethical decision-making in the context of Fascist Italy, a world in which lofty concerns of moral conduct seem the fodder of fools and idealists. Silone uses his central character, firebrand and part-time philosopher Pietro Spina, to plunge his readers into one man’s quest for goodness within the debauchery and despair of war-torn Italy. Pietro’s moral development through the context of his adventures illustrates the challenge of crafting any sound ethical code, and the ease with which one might be lost to cynicism or indifference. The road marks of Pietro’s philosophical evolution are explored through comparisons with Iris Murdoch’s work on moral vision, Elizabeth Anderson’s non-ideal theory, and the three crusaders of Samantha Vice, Ryan Preston-Roedder, and Vanessa Carbonell in their campaign for faith in humanity over cynicism. Sophie Zepf University of Portland zepf19@up.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1179 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1179 Res Cogitans Ignazio Silone’s novel Bread and Wine takes the readers on a wild ride through fascist Italy, as seen through the eyes of Pietro Spina, a one-man revolution in a world of pessimists. One could present Pietro as a less romantic version of James Bond, in his travels as a secret Communist revolutionary, complete with a priest disguise, clandestine meetings, and lots of secret note-passing. Throw in a bunch of worldweary Italian peasants, and Silone has himself a novel! Unconventional as it may be, Pietro’s search for justice in the harsh climate of fascist Italy strikes a familiar chord within anyone who has tried looking for light in what seems to be the darkest hour. Throughout his adventures, Pietro’s own philosophical evolution sheds light on the real life complexities of exercising moral judgment. This complexity can be usefully unpacked by drawing on Iris Murdoch’s work on moral vision, Elizabeth Anderson’s non-ideal theory, and recent work urging the need for faith in humanity to combat the threat of cynicism. Through Pietro, Silone illustrates the challenge of crafting any sound ethical code, while still providing a ray of hope in the tale of a good man’s fight for justice and truth. Both Pietro Spina and Iris Murdoch are connected through their particular and unique sense of moral vision. Pietro Spina first enters the reader’s awareness as a sort of ghostly rumor, floating above the mundane chatter of the other characters’ lives. The novel begins with two men named Nunzio and Concettino visiting Don Benedetto, a wizened and world-weary priest who was once their childhood teacher. Their conversation quickly turns to Pietro, another former student. Pietro is given a larger-thanlife reputation as an exiled firebrand and proponent of revolutionary communism. As it turns out, Nunzio runs into Pietro on his way back home, and quickly learns that Pietro has returned, hell-bent on turning Italy away from its fasc
伊格纳齐奥·西罗内(Ignazio Silone)的小说《面包与葡萄酒》(Bread and Wine)探讨了法西斯意大利背景下道德决策的复杂本质,在这个世界里,对道德行为的崇高关注似乎成了傻瓜和理想主义者的口粮。西罗内用他的中心人物、煽动者兼兼职哲学家彼得罗·斯皮纳(Pietro Spina)带领读者在饱受战争蹂躏的意大利的放荡和绝望中,探索一个人对善的追求。彼得罗通过他的冒险经历的道德发展说明了制定任何健全的道德准则的挑战,以及一个人很容易失去愤世嫉俗或冷漠。通过与艾里斯·默多克关于道德视野的著作、伊丽莎白·安德森的非理想理论,以及萨曼莎·Vice、瑞安·普雷斯顿-罗德和凡妮莎·卡伯内尔这三位十字军战士的比较,我们探索了彼得罗哲学进化的道路标志。Sophie Zepf波特兰大学zepf19@up.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1179第9卷第1期Res Cogitans 2 | eP1179 Res Cogitans伊格纳齐奥·西罗内的小说《面包与葡萄酒》通过彼得罗·斯皮纳(Pietro Spina)的眼睛,在悲观主义者的世界里进行了一场单人革命,带领读者在法西斯意大利进行了一次疯狂的旅行。人们可以把彼得罗描绘成一个不那么浪漫的詹姆斯·邦德,在他的旅行中,他是一个秘密的共产主义革命者,伪装成牧师,秘密会议,还有很多秘密的纸条传递。再加上一群厌世的意大利农民,西隆就有了一部小说!彼得罗在法西斯意大利严酷的气候下寻找正义,这可能是不寻常的,但在任何试图在最黑暗的时刻寻找光明的人心中,他的这种寻找正义的方式都引起了熟悉的共鸣。在他的冒险中,彼得罗自己的哲学演变揭示了现实生活中道德判断的复杂性。Iris Murdoch关于道德视野的著作,Elizabeth Anderson的非理想理论,以及最近敦促人们需要对人性的信仰来对抗犬儒主义威胁的著作,都可以有效地揭示这种复杂性。通过彼得罗,西隆说明了制定任何健全的道德准则的挑战,同时仍然在一个好人为正义和真理而战的故事中提供了一线希望。彼得罗·斯皮纳和艾瑞斯·默多克通过他们独特的道德观联系在一起。皮埃特罗·斯皮纳最初进入读者的意识,是一种幽灵般的谣言,漂浮在其他人物生活的世俗闲聊之上。小说一开始,两个名叫农齐奥和孔蒂蒂诺的人拜访了唐·贝内代托,一个干瘪、厌世的牧师,他曾经是他们童年的老师。他们的谈话很快转向彼得罗,另一个以前的学生。作为一名流亡的煽动者和革命共产主义的支持者,彼得罗被赋予了比生命更大的声誉。事实证明,努齐奥在回家的路上遇到了彼得罗,并很快得知彼得罗已经回来了,他一心想让意大利摆脱法西斯主义的道路。努齐奥冷淡地对彼得罗说:“普通人通常没有任何选择。”这代表了普通意大利人的情绪。他生活的环境是预先为他准备好的”(Silone 32)。彼得罗对这种对生活的严厉谴责感到震惊,他喊道:“一个用自己的头脑思考而不堕落的人是一个自由的人……如果你懒惰、无情、卑躬屈膝,你就没有自由”(Silone 33)。与Nunzio不同的是,彼得罗对意大利有着一种道德愿景,超越了一个依赖于农民的极权主义国家每天强加的苦难。他坚持认为,为了创造一个更美好的世界,我们可以做得更多。在最初的口头争论中,人们可以在彼得罗的道德哲学和默多克的道德愿景之间找到相似之处。和彼得罗一样,默多克认为道德在很大程度上取决于一个人的观点,从某种意义上说,“意志会不断影响信仰……理想情况下,能够通过持续关注现实来影响它……作为有道德的人,我们必须努力公正地看待事物,克服偏见……直接反映”(默多克39)。默多克的《拯救还是诅咒》(Zepf | Salvation or Damnation commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans eP1179 | 3)与典型的西方思想不同,她认为道德是一种个人努力,通过不偏不偏的反思实践,看到过去一个人的扭曲或“幻想”,默多克将其称为道德“关注”。在《面包与葡萄酒》的案例中,默多克可能会说,Nunzio被他的自满蒙蔽了双眼,尤其是作为一个处于社会特权地位的富人,他看不到有待完成的道德工作。像彼得罗一样,默多克重视个人反思,或“用自己的头脑思考”,这有助于克服社会习俗或个人神经质,这些习俗或神经质可能会使我们无法寻求道德真理。 罗尔斯认为,如果一个人开始,他可以提出这些规则来构建社会
{"title":"Salvation or Damnation, and where Ethics Fits in to all That","authors":"S. Zepf","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1179","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1179","url":null,"abstract":"Ignazio Silone’s novel Bread and Wine explores the complex nature of ethical decision-making in the context of Fascist Italy, a world in which lofty concerns of moral conduct seem the fodder of fools and idealists. Silone uses his central character, firebrand and part-time philosopher Pietro Spina, to plunge his readers into one man’s quest for goodness within the debauchery and despair of war-torn Italy. Pietro’s moral development through the context of his adventures illustrates the challenge of crafting any sound ethical code, and the ease with which one might be lost to cynicism or indifference. The road marks of Pietro’s philosophical evolution are explored through comparisons with Iris Murdoch’s work on moral vision, Elizabeth Anderson’s non-ideal theory, and the three crusaders of Samantha Vice, Ryan Preston-Roedder, and Vanessa Carbonell in their campaign for faith in humanity over cynicism. Sophie Zepf University of Portland zepf19@up.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1179 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1179 Res Cogitans Ignazio Silone’s novel Bread and Wine takes the readers on a wild ride through fascist Italy, as seen through the eyes of Pietro Spina, a one-man revolution in a world of pessimists. One could present Pietro as a less romantic version of James Bond, in his travels as a secret Communist revolutionary, complete with a priest disguise, clandestine meetings, and lots of secret note-passing. Throw in a bunch of worldweary Italian peasants, and Silone has himself a novel! Unconventional as it may be, Pietro’s search for justice in the harsh climate of fascist Italy strikes a familiar chord within anyone who has tried looking for light in what seems to be the darkest hour. Throughout his adventures, Pietro’s own philosophical evolution sheds light on the real life complexities of exercising moral judgment. This complexity can be usefully unpacked by drawing on Iris Murdoch’s work on moral vision, Elizabeth Anderson’s non-ideal theory, and recent work urging the need for faith in humanity to combat the threat of cynicism. Through Pietro, Silone illustrates the challenge of crafting any sound ethical code, while still providing a ray of hope in the tale of a good man’s fight for justice and truth. Both Pietro Spina and Iris Murdoch are connected through their particular and unique sense of moral vision. Pietro Spina first enters the reader’s awareness as a sort of ghostly rumor, floating above the mundane chatter of the other characters’ lives. The novel begins with two men named Nunzio and Concettino visiting Don Benedetto, a wizened and world-weary priest who was once their childhood teacher. Their conversation quickly turns to Pietro, another former student. Pietro is given a larger-thanlife reputation as an exiled firebrand and proponent of revolutionary communism. As it turns out, Nunzio runs into Pietro on his way back home, and quickly learns that Pietro has returned, hell-bent on turning Italy away from its fasc","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"91 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125493091","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
In this paper I examine the relationship between emotions and practical rationality, arguing that emotions are incredibly useful in assisting us in making practical choices. However, this enthusiasm needs to be met with some caution as it not the case that every one of our emotions give us reasons we should be considering in order to make a rational choice, and there are times where if we did follow our hearts we would end up feeling ashamed or displeased with ourselves afterward. At the same time, we can feel guilty about a decision we made while purposefully ignoring our emotions when they tell us otherwise. It is ultimately those instances of reflexive shame or displeasure that tell us something about our agency. Our reflexive emotions show us what we should really care about and when we are failing to do so. And, since the purpose of making rational decisions is to properly attend to our goals and aspirations, part of being rational is to purse what we care about. Our reflexive emotions act as a guide to how well or how poorly we are doing just that. Tyler Flanagan University of Wisconsin Osh Kosh flanat23@uwosh.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1180 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1180 Res Cogitans In recent years research concerning emotions and rationality has revealed that our abilities to reason and deliberate are not as opposed to our emotions as was once thought.1 Because our emotions are evaluations about the world rather than baseless feelings, they are subject to correctness conditions and justification conditions. We ask for reasons as to why we experienced this or that emotion, so that emotions are not simply passive irrational or arational phenomena but rather one of the ways in which we examine and make sense of the world around us through our own eyes (Deonna & Teroni, 2012).2 We would never accuse someone of being irrational if they feared losing their job in itself because of how important it is to have a job in order to survive and be happy. However, we may tell the worker that their fear is misguided and false if their fear comes from being paranoid that their boss does not like them, when it turns out their boss likes them very much. Part of developing a more positive outlook on the relationship between emotions and rationality includes recent reflections on the role emotions play in our practical reasoning. In this paper I argue that our emotions can in fact positively contribute to our practical reasoning, but only a particular set of emotions actually assist us in making rational decisions. These are emotions that are authentic to ourselves as agents, and I posit that the only way to reliably tell if an emotional experience is authentically ours is through our reflexive emotions. As our emotions are thought to give us privileged access to values as we examine the world, they make salient important reasons for our making one choice over another given what we care about. It is then argued that it is not at all ir
{"title":"Emotions, Practical Rationality, and the Self","authors":"Tyler J. Flanagan","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1180","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1180","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper I examine the relationship between emotions and practical rationality, arguing that emotions are incredibly useful in assisting us in making practical choices. However, this enthusiasm needs to be met with some caution as it not the case that every one of our emotions give us reasons we should be considering in order to make a rational choice, and there are times where if we did follow our hearts we would end up feeling ashamed or displeased with ourselves afterward. At the same time, we can feel guilty about a decision we made while purposefully ignoring our emotions when they tell us otherwise. It is ultimately those instances of reflexive shame or displeasure that tell us something about our agency. Our reflexive emotions show us what we should really care about and when we are failing to do so. And, since the purpose of making rational decisions is to properly attend to our goals and aspirations, part of being rational is to purse what we care about. Our reflexive emotions act as a guide to how well or how poorly we are doing just that. Tyler Flanagan University of Wisconsin Osh Kosh flanat23@uwosh.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1180 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1180 Res Cogitans In recent years research concerning emotions and rationality has revealed that our abilities to reason and deliberate are not as opposed to our emotions as was once thought.1 Because our emotions are evaluations about the world rather than baseless feelings, they are subject to correctness conditions and justification conditions. We ask for reasons as to why we experienced this or that emotion, so that emotions are not simply passive irrational or arational phenomena but rather one of the ways in which we examine and make sense of the world around us through our own eyes (Deonna & Teroni, 2012).2 We would never accuse someone of being irrational if they feared losing their job in itself because of how important it is to have a job in order to survive and be happy. However, we may tell the worker that their fear is misguided and false if their fear comes from being paranoid that their boss does not like them, when it turns out their boss likes them very much. Part of developing a more positive outlook on the relationship between emotions and rationality includes recent reflections on the role emotions play in our practical reasoning. In this paper I argue that our emotions can in fact positively contribute to our practical reasoning, but only a particular set of emotions actually assist us in making rational decisions. These are emotions that are authentic to ourselves as agents, and I posit that the only way to reliably tell if an emotional experience is authentically ours is through our reflexive emotions. As our emotions are thought to give us privileged access to values as we examine the world, they make salient important reasons for our making one choice over another given what we care about. It is then argued that it is not at all ir","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129761386","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Philosophers have relied heavily on the distinction between analytic truths and synthetic ones for various philosophical pursuits. In this paper I explore Immanuel Kant’s explanation of the distinction, W.V.O. Quine’s qualms with it, and the attempt of H.P. Grice and Strawson at saving synonymy in order to salvage analyticity from doubts. I conclude that although valiant, the efforts put forth by Grice and Strawson fall short. I argue that this is so because they attack a weak interpretation of Quine’s contention. Maité Castillo Humboldt State University mgc188@humboldt.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1175 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1175 Res Cogitans The following paper is an evaluative assessment of the distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments. To do this I have examined Quine’s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”1 and Kant’s The Critique of Pure Reason2 to contrast the views that Quine and Kant had of this distinction. Whereas Kant was proud to make this distinction in an effort to revive the study of metaphysics, Quine eventually, after a long period of accepting the distinction, followed with a rejection of analyticity as it was used in metaphysics for establishing necessary truths; claiming that all explanations of analytic truths in that way are circular, “or something like a closed curve in space.”3 Quine asserts that ‘necessity’ in the case of analytic statements does not do the work that past philosophers, such as Kant, wanted it to. I have also explored the criticisms of Quine put forth by Grice and Strawson in “In Defense of a Dogma”4 to see if they restore the analytic and synthetic distinction. I have mainly been concerned with the philosophical problem of establishing the possibility of objective necessary truths through the lenses of Kant, Quine, Grice, and Strawson. I intend to defend Quine by showing where Grice and Strawson fall short in their endeavor. Let us begin with Kant. In The Critique of Pure Reason, Kant attempts to answer the question of how synthetic a priori knowledge is possible. I will begin by explaining the distinctions between ways of conceptualizing or making theoretical judgments of the world, according to Kant, then I will explain his view of metaphysics by way of the possibility of synthetic a priori judgments. Kant distinguishes between a priori judgments that occur unconnected of all outside experiences and pure a priori judgments that happen completely free of experience without anything empirical intermixed. To highlight this distinction he uses an example of a man whose house has a faulty foundation. Given a flaw in infrastructure one can expect without waiting to experience it that the house will fall in on itself, i.e., one can predict it a priori. Reasoning is done a priori by modus ponens to arrive at the conclusion: “If there’s a faulty foundation, then the house will collapse. I see that there is no foundation, therefore the house will collapse.” The sentences themselves that ma
哲学家们在各种哲学追求中严重依赖于分析真理和综合真理之间的区别。本文探讨了康德对这一区别的解释,奎因对这一区别的质疑,以及格赖斯和斯特劳森为挽救分析性而试图挽救同义词的尝试。我的结论是,尽管格赖斯和斯特劳森的努力是勇敢的,但还是不够。我认为这是事实,因为他们攻击了奎因论点的一个薄弱解释。mait Castillo Humboldt州立大学mgc188@humboldt.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1175第9卷,第1期Res Cogitans 2 | eP1175 Res Cogitans以下论文是对分析和综合判断之间区别的评估性评估。为此,我考察了奎因的《经验主义的两个教条》和康德的《纯粹理性批判》,对比了奎因和康德对这一区别的看法。尽管康德很自豪地在努力恢复形而上学的研究中做出了这种区分,但奎因最终,在很长一段时间内接受了这种区分,随后拒绝了分析性,因为它在形而上学中被用来建立必要的真理;声称以这种方式对分析真理的所有解释都是圆形的,或者类似于空间中的封闭曲线。奎因断言,在分析性陈述的情况下,“必然性”并没有像康德等过去的哲学家所希望的那样发挥作用。我还探讨了格赖斯和斯特劳森在《捍卫教条》(in Defense of a Dogma)中对奎因的批评,看看他们是否恢复了分析和综合的区别。我主要关注的是通过康德、奎因、格赖斯和斯特劳森的视角来建立客观必然真理的可能性的哲学问题。我打算通过展示格赖斯和斯特劳森在努力中的不足之处来为奎因辩护。让我们从康德开始。在《纯粹理性批判》中,康德试图回答综合先验知识如何成为可能的问题。我将首先解释康德对世界进行概念化和理论化判断的方式之间的区别,然后我将通过综合先验判断的可能性来解释康德的形而上学观点。康德区分了与所有外部经验无关的先验判断和完全脱离经验,没有任何经验混合的纯粹先验判断。为了强调这种区别,他举了一个人的例子,他的房子地基有问题。假设基础设施存在缺陷,人们无需体验就可以预期房子会倒塌,也就是说,人们可以先验地预测它。推理是通过推理方法先验地得出结论:“如果地基有缺陷,那么房子就会倒塌。”我看这房子没有根基,所以要塌了。”构成前提的句子本身是后验的。2 .伊曼努尔·康德:《纯粹理性批判》,哈克特出版公司,1781年,《哲学评论》第60卷第1期(1951年1月),第20-43页
{"title":"Analytic vs. Synthetic, Distinction or Myth?: Kant’s Kantribution, Quine’s Inquisition, Grice and Strawson’s Salvation","authors":"M. Castillo","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1175","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1175","url":null,"abstract":"Philosophers have relied heavily on the distinction between analytic truths and synthetic ones for various philosophical pursuits. In this paper I explore Immanuel Kant’s explanation of the distinction, W.V.O. Quine’s qualms with it, and the attempt of H.P. Grice and Strawson at saving synonymy in order to salvage analyticity from doubts. I conclude that although valiant, the efforts put forth by Grice and Strawson fall short. I argue that this is so because they attack a weak interpretation of Quine’s contention. Maité Castillo Humboldt State University mgc188@humboldt.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1175 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1175 Res Cogitans The following paper is an evaluative assessment of the distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments. To do this I have examined Quine’s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”1 and Kant’s The Critique of Pure Reason2 to contrast the views that Quine and Kant had of this distinction. Whereas Kant was proud to make this distinction in an effort to revive the study of metaphysics, Quine eventually, after a long period of accepting the distinction, followed with a rejection of analyticity as it was used in metaphysics for establishing necessary truths; claiming that all explanations of analytic truths in that way are circular, “or something like a closed curve in space.”3 Quine asserts that ‘necessity’ in the case of analytic statements does not do the work that past philosophers, such as Kant, wanted it to. I have also explored the criticisms of Quine put forth by Grice and Strawson in “In Defense of a Dogma”4 to see if they restore the analytic and synthetic distinction. I have mainly been concerned with the philosophical problem of establishing the possibility of objective necessary truths through the lenses of Kant, Quine, Grice, and Strawson. I intend to defend Quine by showing where Grice and Strawson fall short in their endeavor. Let us begin with Kant. In The Critique of Pure Reason, Kant attempts to answer the question of how synthetic a priori knowledge is possible. I will begin by explaining the distinctions between ways of conceptualizing or making theoretical judgments of the world, according to Kant, then I will explain his view of metaphysics by way of the possibility of synthetic a priori judgments. Kant distinguishes between a priori judgments that occur unconnected of all outside experiences and pure a priori judgments that happen completely free of experience without anything empirical intermixed. To highlight this distinction he uses an example of a man whose house has a faulty foundation. Given a flaw in infrastructure one can expect without waiting to experience it that the house will fall in on itself, i.e., one can predict it a priori. Reasoning is done a priori by modus ponens to arrive at the conclusion: “If there’s a faulty foundation, then the house will collapse. I see that there is no foundation, therefore the house will collapse.” The sentences themselves that ma","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"147 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131622214","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Anthropological writings have, at times, been vague in the approach used to gather evidence of cultural and social beliefs of the peoples studied, and the method of representing the data to the reading public. This paper employs the theory of judgment aggregation in critiquing anthropological theory and practice. It will be structured in three parts: first, I will present the theory of judgment aggregation as constructed by Christian List and Philip Pettit; second, I will sketch some epistemological methods used by anthropologists, and assess their attitude toward the notions of judgment aggregation and group agency; and finally, I will apply List and Pettit’s arguments about effective group organization to anthropological practice of representing its studied peoples’ beliefs and judgments by proposing three possible changes in method that will allow for more accurate and faithful interpretations and descriptions. Dagan Douglas Reed College douglasd@reed.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1177 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1177 Res Cogitans Judgment Aggregation An emerging subfield of epistemology, social epistemology has sought to uncover the social element inherent in certain forms of knowledge.1 It expands from epistemology’s exclusive focus on individuals into “investigating the epistemic effects of social interactions and social systems.” The field of judgment aggregation2 investigates “the epistemic quality of group doxastic attitudes (whatever their provenance may be),” and “the epistemic consequences of adopting certain institutional arrangements or systemic relations as opposed to alternatives” as well.3 List called this the “radical form” of social epistemology, wherein “certain multi-member groups themselves are taken to be epistemic agents capable of acquiring beliefs and knowledge.”4 Judgment aggregation, where judgments are binary expressions of attitudes,5 is concerned with the establishment of group doxastic attitudes (judgments and beliefs) out of individual doxastic attitudes.6 Juries determining defendants’ guilt or innocence, expert panels of scientists recommending policy, and bank committees forecasting future opportunities are just the sort of groups List and Pettit want to explore.7 Much of their work on judgment aggregation since their famous 2002 article “Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result” has been clarification of the aggregation procedure, defense of the existence of group agents, and suggestion for certain configurations of groups using certain aggregation procedures to produce certain results. I will now briefly sketch their views on each of these first two matters, 1 Alvin I. Goldman and Thomas Blanchard, “Social Epistemology,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), section 1, https://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/win2016/entries/epistemology-social. The authors place its formal beginnings in the 1970s and 1980s. 2 One of the many types of s
除了反应性和合理性之外,这个过程,或“聚合函数”(“将个人对议程上的命题的态度映射到集体对这些命题的态度”10),还必须满足三个更小的条件,即List和Pettit声称我们期望“合理的群体态度形成”的条件:普遍领域、匿名性和系统性普遍领域是指“个人对议程上的命题的态度的任何可能的轮廓”可以输入该函数。匿名是指“在决定群体态度时,所有个人的态度都得到同等的重视”,就像无记名投票一样。系统性是指"群体对每个命题的态度只取决于个体对这个命题的态度,而不取决于个体对其他命题的态度,个人态度和集体态度之间的依赖模式对所有命题都是一样的"李斯特和佩蒂特表明,任何试图同时满足所有这些标准的组织都将失败,他们将这个问题称为话语悖论为了避免这种情况,他们建议至少忽略这些条件中的一个,这样团队就可以在不完美的情况下继续运作。我在结论部分回到这个观点上来。8 .《群体知识与群体理性:一个判断聚合的视角》,第2期。9 Christian List和Philip Pettit,“集合判断集:一个不可能的结果”,《经济学与哲学》18(1)(2002):91,96。理性本身受三个自身约束的约束,即完备性、一致性和演绎封闭性。定义见第97-98页。10 .集团代理,48。11集团代理,49。12“判断的集合”,95-96,100。第9卷,第1期Res Cogitans 4 | Res Cogitans判断聚合在很大程度上依赖于群体代理的概念,这可能不容易被接受为存在。List和Pettit声称,在日常用语中,我们经常将其归因于团体和组织的动机和行为,例如FBI调查这样或那样的嫌疑人,或者Goodwill想要雇用这样或那样的员工。尽管我们知道这些群体只是在一定的组织原则下作为其成员的集合而存在,但我们不仅发现以这种方式说话是可以接受的,而且,List和Pettit声称,我们不能把这些群体仅仅理解为个人的集合。他们认为,这些群体除了产生于个体成员的能动性之外,还具有能动性。列表表明,思想家[M]可能准备将某些群体视为代理人,只要满足一些严格的条件....特别是,要成为一个主体,一个群体面对外部世界必须表现出强烈满足某些理性条件的行为模式……简而言之,群体中认知代理的必要条件是一个制度结构(正式的或非正式的),它允许群体认可某些信念或判断作为集体的;而群体作为认知主体的表现(即他们在获取信念或知识方面的表现)取决于该制度结构的细节这个定义允许从公司到部落的群体被视为群体代理。
{"title":"The Social Epistemology of Anthropology: Insights from Judgment Aggregation","authors":"Dagan Douglas","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1177","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1177","url":null,"abstract":"Anthropological writings have, at times, been vague in the approach used to gather evidence of cultural and social beliefs of the peoples studied, and the method of representing the data to the reading public. This paper employs the theory of judgment aggregation in critiquing anthropological theory and practice. It will be structured in three parts: first, I will present the theory of judgment aggregation as constructed by Christian List and Philip Pettit; second, I will sketch some epistemological methods used by anthropologists, and assess their attitude toward the notions of judgment aggregation and group agency; and finally, I will apply List and Pettit’s arguments about effective group organization to anthropological practice of representing its studied peoples’ beliefs and judgments by proposing three possible changes in method that will allow for more accurate and faithful interpretations and descriptions. Dagan Douglas Reed College douglasd@reed.edu https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1177 Volume 9, Issue 1 Res Cogitans 2 | eP1177 Res Cogitans Judgment Aggregation An emerging subfield of epistemology, social epistemology has sought to uncover the social element inherent in certain forms of knowledge.1 It expands from epistemology’s exclusive focus on individuals into “investigating the epistemic effects of social interactions and social systems.” The field of judgment aggregation2 investigates “the epistemic quality of group doxastic attitudes (whatever their provenance may be),” and “the epistemic consequences of adopting certain institutional arrangements or systemic relations as opposed to alternatives” as well.3 List called this the “radical form” of social epistemology, wherein “certain multi-member groups themselves are taken to be epistemic agents capable of acquiring beliefs and knowledge.”4 Judgment aggregation, where judgments are binary expressions of attitudes,5 is concerned with the establishment of group doxastic attitudes (judgments and beliefs) out of individual doxastic attitudes.6 Juries determining defendants’ guilt or innocence, expert panels of scientists recommending policy, and bank committees forecasting future opportunities are just the sort of groups List and Pettit want to explore.7 Much of their work on judgment aggregation since their famous 2002 article “Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result” has been clarification of the aggregation procedure, defense of the existence of group agents, and suggestion for certain configurations of groups using certain aggregation procedures to produce certain results. I will now briefly sketch their views on each of these first two matters, 1 Alvin I. Goldman and Thomas Blanchard, “Social Epistemology,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), section 1, https://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/win2016/entries/epistemology-social. The authors place its formal beginnings in the 1970s and 1980s. 2 One of the many types of s","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"42 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131687920","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Issue Introduction","authors":"Ian O'Loughlin","doi":"10.7710/2155-4838.1181","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1181","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":167127,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Undergraduate Research and Creative Activities","volume":"7 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114462964","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}