首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Tort Law最新文献

英文 中文
Strict Products Liability 2.0: The Triumph of Judicial Reasoning Over Mainstream Tort Theory 严格产品责任2.0:司法推理对主流侵权理论的胜利
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1515/jtl-2021-0027
Mark A. Geistfeld
Abstract Strict products liability has evolved in a manner that is widely misunderstood. The liability rule was first formulated to govern defective products that did not minimally perform one of their ordinary functions as expected by consumers—a malfunction that violates the implied warranty of quality. After adopting this rule, courts began applying it to products that did not malfunction and found that a test for defect based on consumer expectations often is indeterminate or can otherwise unduly limit liability in an important class of cases. To address these problems, most courts adopted the risk-utility test, a form of cost-benefit analysis that functions like the negligence standard of reasonable care. Relying on these cases, the Restatement (Third) of Torts: Products Liability embraced the risk-utility test, jettisoned the consumer expectations test, and characterized strict products liability as a misleading label that perpetuates confusion about liability being strict when it instead is based on negligence. In response, a clear majority of courts have rejected this negligence-based framework and affirmed the continued vitality of strict products liability. Puzzled by this unexpected development, mainstream scholars claim that courts are confused by the rhetoric of strict products liability. The prevailing scholarly opinion about this matter is confused; its fixation on negligence ignores the implied warranty rationale for strict products liability. Having been largely formulated as a rule of contract law, the implied warranty is under-theorized as a tort doctrine. Once adequately developed, the tort version of the implied warranty shows why courts have transformed the rule of strict products liability from the last century into a more comprehensive regime—“strict products liability 2.0”—that relies on consumer expectations to incorporate the risk-utility test into the framework of strict products liability. As compared to ordinary negligence liability, the implied warranty defines the safety problem in the normatively appropriate manner, thereby sharpening the inquiry about what’s at stake. In dismissing this important development, mainstream tort theory relies on legal categories that fundamentally differ from the ones courts have used to develop strict products liability with analogical reasoning. Scholars have either resorted to overly general theories of tort liability or have otherwise focused on narrow doctrinal questions. By not engaging in the mid-level categorical theorizing required by analogical reasoning, the mainstream position could not see how this characteristic form of judicial reasoning has created the substantively sound regime of strict products liability 2.0.
摘要严格的产品责任以一种被广泛误解的方式演变。责任规则最初是为了管理缺陷产品,这些缺陷产品没有按照消费者的预期最低限度地发挥其正常功能之一,即违反隐含质量保证的故障。在采用这一规则后,法院开始将其适用于没有故障的产品,并发现基于消费者期望的缺陷测试通常是不确定的,或者在重要的一类案件中可能会不适当地限制责任。为了解决这些问题,大多数法院采用了风险效用测试,这是一种成本效益分析形式,其功能类似于合理谨慎的疏忽标准。基于这些案例,《侵权行为重述(第三):产品责任》接受了风险效用测试,放弃了消费者期望测试,并将严格的产品责任描述为一个误导性标签,当责任是基于疏忽时,它会使人们对责任的严格性感到困惑。作为回应,绝大多数法院驳回了这一基于疏忽的框架,并确认了严格产品责任的持续活力。主流学者对这一意外的发展感到困惑,声称法院被严格产品责任的修辞所迷惑。学术界对这一问题的普遍看法是混乱的;其对过失的执着忽略了严格产品责任的隐含保证理由。默示保证在很大程度上是作为合同法的一项规则制定的,但作为侵权行为学说,其理论化程度较低。一旦得到充分发展,隐含担保的侵权版本就表明了为什么法院已经将上个世纪的严格产品责任规则转变为一个更全面的制度——“严格产品责任2.0”——它依赖于消费者的期望,将风险效用测试纳入严格产品责任的框架。与普通过失责任相比,默示保证以规范适当的方式定义了安全问题,从而加强了对利害关系的调查。在否定这一重要发展的过程中,主流侵权理论所依据的法律类别与法院通过类比推理制定严格产品责任的法律类别有根本不同。学者们要么求助于过于笼统的侵权责任理论,要么专注于狭隘的理论问题。由于没有参与类比推理所需的中级分类理论,主流立场看不出这种独特的司法推理形式是如何创造出实质上健全的严格产品责任2.0制度的。
{"title":"Strict Products Liability 2.0: The Triumph of Judicial Reasoning Over Mainstream Tort Theory","authors":"Mark A. Geistfeld","doi":"10.1515/jtl-2021-0027","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jtl-2021-0027","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Strict products liability has evolved in a manner that is widely misunderstood. The liability rule was first formulated to govern defective products that did not minimally perform one of their ordinary functions as expected by consumers—a malfunction that violates the implied warranty of quality. After adopting this rule, courts began applying it to products that did not malfunction and found that a test for defect based on consumer expectations often is indeterminate or can otherwise unduly limit liability in an important class of cases. To address these problems, most courts adopted the risk-utility test, a form of cost-benefit analysis that functions like the negligence standard of reasonable care. Relying on these cases, the Restatement (Third) of Torts: Products Liability embraced the risk-utility test, jettisoned the consumer expectations test, and characterized strict products liability as a misleading label that perpetuates confusion about liability being strict when it instead is based on negligence. In response, a clear majority of courts have rejected this negligence-based framework and affirmed the continued vitality of strict products liability. Puzzled by this unexpected development, mainstream scholars claim that courts are confused by the rhetoric of strict products liability. The prevailing scholarly opinion about this matter is confused; its fixation on negligence ignores the implied warranty rationale for strict products liability. Having been largely formulated as a rule of contract law, the implied warranty is under-theorized as a tort doctrine. Once adequately developed, the tort version of the implied warranty shows why courts have transformed the rule of strict products liability from the last century into a more comprehensive regime—“strict products liability 2.0”—that relies on consumer expectations to incorporate the risk-utility test into the framework of strict products liability. As compared to ordinary negligence liability, the implied warranty defines the safety problem in the normatively appropriate manner, thereby sharpening the inquiry about what’s at stake. In dismissing this important development, mainstream tort theory relies on legal categories that fundamentally differ from the ones courts have used to develop strict products liability with analogical reasoning. Scholars have either resorted to overly general theories of tort liability or have otherwise focused on narrow doctrinal questions. By not engaging in the mid-level categorical theorizing required by analogical reasoning, the mainstream position could not see how this characteristic form of judicial reasoning has created the substantively sound regime of strict products liability 2.0.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"403 - 467"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49251867","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From Liability Shields to Democratic Theory: What We Need from Tort Theory Now 从责任盾牌到民主理论:侵权理论对我们的启示
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1515/jtl-2021-0034
H. Feldman
Abstract In the United States, one startling response to COVID-19 has been a push for so-called “liability shields,” laws modifying tort doctrine so as to largely eliminate tort liability for negligently causing COVID-19. Though not enacted at the federal level, such changes have been adopted in numerous states. This article excavates and articulates the tort theory that lies behind this puzzlingly response to a pandemic. I call the theory “tort deflationism.” Grounded in modern American conservatism and with a doctrinal pedigree dating back to the 1970s, tort deflationism explains and justifies only minimal tort liability, out of deference to non-governmental actors – especially family, church, and business—and suspicion of government competence and power. Other tort theories should reckon with tort deflationism, and I discuss some challenges of doing so. The contest between tort deflationism and other theories speaks to ongoing debates about the legitimacy of law in pluralist democracies. I urge tort theorists to enter these debates and to consider their implications for tort law itself.
摘要在美国,对新冠肺炎的一个惊人反应是推动所谓的“责任保护”,即修改侵权原则的法律,以在很大程度上消除过失导致新冠肺炎的侵权责任。虽然没有在联邦层面颁布,但这些变化已经在许多州被采纳。本文挖掘并阐述了这一令人困惑的疫情应对措施背后的侵权理论。我称之为“侵权通缩主义”。基于现代美国保守主义,其理论渊源可以追溯到20世纪70年代,出于对非政府行为者(尤其是家庭、教会和企业)的尊重,以及对政府能力和权力的怀疑,侵权通缩主义只解释和证明了最低限度的侵权责任。其他侵权理论应该考虑侵权通缩主义,我讨论了这样做的一些挑战。侵权通缩主义和其他理论之间的竞争表明了关于多元民主国家法律合法性的持续辩论。我敦促侵权行为理论家参与这些辩论,并考虑它们对侵权法本身的影响。
{"title":"From Liability Shields to Democratic Theory: What We Need from Tort Theory Now","authors":"H. Feldman","doi":"10.1515/jtl-2021-0034","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jtl-2021-0034","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In the United States, one startling response to COVID-19 has been a push for so-called “liability shields,” laws modifying tort doctrine so as to largely eliminate tort liability for negligently causing COVID-19. Though not enacted at the federal level, such changes have been adopted in numerous states. This article excavates and articulates the tort theory that lies behind this puzzlingly response to a pandemic. I call the theory “tort deflationism.” Grounded in modern American conservatism and with a doctrinal pedigree dating back to the 1970s, tort deflationism explains and justifies only minimal tort liability, out of deference to non-governmental actors – especially family, church, and business—and suspicion of government competence and power. Other tort theories should reckon with tort deflationism, and I discuss some challenges of doing so. The contest between tort deflationism and other theories speaks to ongoing debates about the legitimacy of law in pluralist democracies. I urge tort theorists to enter these debates and to consider their implications for tort law itself.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"373 - 401"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47553314","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Q: What is Tort? A: Categorical Hurt Q: 什么是Tort?A: 分类伤害
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1515/jtl-2021-0028
Anita Bernstein
Abstract The capacious and hard-to-confine term Tort challenges observers to identify what it includes and does not include. Offered here to describe tort, the label “categorical hurt” makes reference to two foundational characteristics. “Hurt,” the noun in this phrase, insists that tort plaintiffs bring to court their experience of suffering. Its adjective, used in this article to echo the word Immanuel Kant chose to modify a different noun, “imperative,” means that tort courts hear claims of general rather than exclusively personal interest. To earn a tort remedy, the suffering reported by a hurt plaintiff must be of a kind that other people can experience and understand.
摘要“侵权”这个宽泛而难以限定的术语让观察者很难确定它包括什么和不包括什么。这里提供的“绝对伤害”这个标签是为了描述侵权行为,它提到了两个基本特征。“伤害”,这个短语中的名词,坚持侵权原告将他们的痛苦经历诉诸法庭。它的形容词在本文中用来呼应伊曼纽尔·康德选择修改另一个名词“命令”的词,意思是侵权法庭审理的是一般而非个人利益的索赔。为了获得侵权救济,受害原告所报告的痛苦必须是其他人能够体验和理解的。
{"title":"Q: What is Tort? A: Categorical Hurt","authors":"Anita Bernstein","doi":"10.1515/jtl-2021-0028","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jtl-2021-0028","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The capacious and hard-to-confine term Tort challenges observers to identify what it includes and does not include. Offered here to describe tort, the label “categorical hurt” makes reference to two foundational characteristics. “Hurt,” the noun in this phrase, insists that tort plaintiffs bring to court their experience of suffering. Its adjective, used in this article to echo the word Immanuel Kant chose to modify a different noun, “imperative,” means that tort courts hear claims of general rather than exclusively personal interest. To earn a tort remedy, the suffering reported by a hurt plaintiff must be of a kind that other people can experience and understand.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"53 2","pages":"261 - 278"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41303950","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Inward Turn and the Future of Tort Theory 侵权理论的内向转向与未来
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1515/jtl-2021-0031
K. Abraham, George E. White
Abstract The future of tort theory cannot be sensibly imagined without understanding its past. Our aim is to understand where tort theory has been in order to predict where it may go. We contend that tort theory has experienced two different eras, and that it may well be about to enter a third. In the first era, spanning roughly the first three-quarters of the twentieth century, tort theory faced outward to the world, focusing on issues affecting redress for civil injuries that were being decided in the courts and emerging in American society at large. In the second era, roughly the last 30 to 40 years, tort theory turned inward and focused mostly on itself. The tort theory that has been done during this second era, valuable though it has been, may well have borne most of its scholarly fruit. We may therefore be ready to move into a third era, in which tort theory turns outward again and becomes occupied with the cutting-edge issues of tort law policy and principle that will be generated as the twenty-first century progresses. This Essay chronicles the first era, in which tort theory faced outward, the second era, in which tort theory turned inward, and identifies three issues that we believe may be on the tort theory agenda, when and if tort theory turns outward again. These involve the coordination and systematization of tort with other sources of regulation and compensation; redressing data theft and digital invasions of privacy; and heightened sensitivity to harm associated with sex, gender, and race-related misconduct.
如果不了解侵权理论的过去,就无法合理地想象其未来。我们的目的是了解侵权理论的现状,以便预测它可能走向何方。我们认为,侵权理论经历了两个不同的时代,很可能即将进入第三个时代。在第一个时代,大约跨越了20世纪前四分之三,侵权理论面向世界,专注于影响民事损害赔偿的问题,这些问题正在法院裁决,并在整个美国社会中出现。在第二个时代,大约是过去的30到40年,侵权理论转向了内部,主要关注自身。第二个时代的侵权理论虽然很有价值,但很可能已经结出了大部分学术成果。因此,我们可能准备进入第三个时代,在这个时代,侵权理论再次转向外部,并被侵权法政策和原则的前沿问题所占据,这些问题将随着21世纪的发展而产生。本文记录了侵权理论向外发展的第一个时代和侵权理论向内发展的第二个时代,并确定了我们认为可能被列入侵权理论议程的三个问题,即侵权理论何时以及是否再次向外发展。其中包括侵权行为与其他监管和赔偿来源的协调和系统化;纠正数据盗窃和数字侵犯隐私的行为;以及对与性、性别和种族相关的不当行为相关的伤害的敏感性提高。
{"title":"The Inward Turn and the Future of Tort Theory","authors":"K. Abraham, George E. White","doi":"10.1515/jtl-2021-0031","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jtl-2021-0031","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The future of tort theory cannot be sensibly imagined without understanding its past. Our aim is to understand where tort theory has been in order to predict where it may go. We contend that tort theory has experienced two different eras, and that it may well be about to enter a third. In the first era, spanning roughly the first three-quarters of the twentieth century, tort theory faced outward to the world, focusing on issues affecting redress for civil injuries that were being decided in the courts and emerging in American society at large. In the second era, roughly the last 30 to 40 years, tort theory turned inward and focused mostly on itself. The tort theory that has been done during this second era, valuable though it has been, may well have borne most of its scholarly fruit. We may therefore be ready to move into a third era, in which tort theory turns outward again and becomes occupied with the cutting-edge issues of tort law policy and principle that will be generated as the twenty-first century progresses. This Essay chronicles the first era, in which tort theory faced outward, the second era, in which tort theory turned inward, and identifies three issues that we believe may be on the tort theory agenda, when and if tort theory turns outward again. These involve the coordination and systematization of tort with other sources of regulation and compensation; redressing data theft and digital invasions of privacy; and heightened sensitivity to harm associated with sex, gender, and race-related misconduct.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"245 - 259"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44497462","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Tort Theory, Private Attorneys General, and State Action: From Mass Torts to Texas S.B. 8 侵权理论、私人总检察长和国家行为:从大规模侵权到德克萨斯州S.B.
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1515/jtl-2022-0009
John C. P. Goldberg, Benjamin c. Zipursky
Abstract Late twentieth-century tort theory was dominated by scholars who regarded tort law as primarily a means employed by government to deter anti-social conduct. On this model, tort plaintiffs are cast as private attorneys general whose lawsuits promote safety. Tort theorists today better appreciate that this approach obscures crucial respects in which tort law is private law–law that empowers persons who have been wronged to redress the wrongs done to them. But in practice there is a continued failure to perceive the ways in which the deterrence model has shaped and distorted views of tort law, as evidenced by the terms on which both the ‘right’ and the ‘left’ critique modern mass tort litigation. More troublingly, the problem extends beyond the field of torts. Indeed, we contend that the lawyerly loss of feel for distinctions between public law and private law explains the inability of the United States Supreme Court Justices, in Whole Woman’s Health v. Jackson, to capture why S.B. 8–Texas’s radical anti-abortion statute–really is a private attorney general statute and why, as such, it should be subject to preenforcement constitutional review.
摘要二十世纪末的侵权理论主要由学者主导,他们认为侵权法主要是政府用来阻止反社会行为的手段。在这种模式下,侵权原告被塑造成私人检察长,其诉讼促进了安全。如今,侵权理论家们更清楚地认识到,这种方法掩盖了侵权法是私法的关键方面,私法赋予受冤枉的人纠正对他们所犯错误的权利。但在实践中,威慑模式塑造和扭曲侵权法观点的方式仍然没有得到理解,“右翼”和“左翼”对现代大规模侵权诉讼的批评就证明了这一点。更令人不安的是,这个问题超出了侵权行为的范畴。事实上,我们认为,律师们对公法和私法之间的区别失去了感觉,这解释了美国最高法院法官在Whole Women’s Health v.Jackson一案中无法理解为什么s.B.8——德克萨斯州激进的反堕胎法规——真的是一部私人司法部长法规,以及为什么它应该接受强制执行前的宪法审查。
{"title":"Tort Theory, Private Attorneys General, and State Action: From Mass Torts to Texas S.B. 8","authors":"John C. P. Goldberg, Benjamin c. Zipursky","doi":"10.1515/jtl-2022-0009","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jtl-2022-0009","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Late twentieth-century tort theory was dominated by scholars who regarded tort law as primarily a means employed by government to deter anti-social conduct. On this model, tort plaintiffs are cast as private attorneys general whose lawsuits promote safety. Tort theorists today better appreciate that this approach obscures crucial respects in which tort law is private law–law that empowers persons who have been wronged to redress the wrongs done to them. But in practice there is a continued failure to perceive the ways in which the deterrence model has shaped and distorted views of tort law, as evidenced by the terms on which both the ‘right’ and the ‘left’ critique modern mass tort litigation. More troublingly, the problem extends beyond the field of torts. Indeed, we contend that the lawyerly loss of feel for distinctions between public law and private law explains the inability of the United States Supreme Court Justices, in Whole Woman’s Health v. Jackson, to capture why S.B. 8–Texas’s radical anti-abortion statute–really is a private attorney general statute and why, as such, it should be subject to preenforcement constitutional review.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"469 - 491"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43266660","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Symposium Issue: The State of Tort Theory 专题讨论会议题:侵权理论的现状
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1515/jtl-2022-0005
C. Robinette
{"title":"Symposium Issue: The State of Tort Theory","authors":"C. Robinette","doi":"10.1515/jtl-2022-0005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jtl-2022-0005","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"241 - 243"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41807849","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Public Right and Wrongs: Tort Theory and the Problem of Public Nuisance 公共的对与错:侵权理论与公害问题
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1515/jtl-2021-0032
A. Sebok
Abstract Tort theory over the past two decades has been characterized by a fruitful dialectic between two models. Instrumentalism, especially, in its deterrence mode, has been promoted by a wide coalition of scholars and jurists. In response, various critics of instrumentalism have argued for the autonomy of tort law, first under the umbrella of corrective justice and later under civil recourse. The success of civil recourse depends in part on its ability to explain emerging areas of focus in tort law. One such area is public nuisance, which, despite some setbacks, is viewed by the plaintiffs bar, state actors, and some members of the academy as an effective tool to address significant social problems, such as the opioid crisis. This article asks whether, and how, civil recourse theory can accommodate modern public nuisance law.
摘要近二十年来,侵权理论以两种模式之间卓有成效的辩证为特征。工具主义,尤其是它的威慑模式,得到了广泛的学者和法学家联盟的推动。作为回应,各种工具主义的批评者主张侵权法的自治,首先在纠正正义的保护伞下,后来在民事追索权下。民事追索权的成功部分取决于其解释侵权法中新兴焦点领域的能力。其中一个领域是公害,尽管遇到了一些挫折,但它被原告律师协会、国家行为者和学院的一些成员视为解决重大社会问题(如阿片类药物危机)的有效工具。民事追索权理论能否适应现代公害法,以及如何适应现代公害法。
{"title":"The Public Right and Wrongs: Tort Theory and the Problem of Public Nuisance","authors":"A. Sebok","doi":"10.1515/jtl-2021-0032","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jtl-2021-0032","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Tort theory over the past two decades has been characterized by a fruitful dialectic between two models. Instrumentalism, especially, in its deterrence mode, has been promoted by a wide coalition of scholars and jurists. In response, various critics of instrumentalism have argued for the autonomy of tort law, first under the umbrella of corrective justice and later under civil recourse. The success of civil recourse depends in part on its ability to explain emerging areas of focus in tort law. One such area is public nuisance, which, despite some setbacks, is viewed by the plaintiffs bar, state actors, and some members of the academy as an effective tool to address significant social problems, such as the opioid crisis. This article asks whether, and how, civil recourse theory can accommodate modern public nuisance law.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"531 - 549"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43697663","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Instrumental Comparative Tort Law 工具比较侵权法
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3973401
R. Perry
Abstract This article examines the possible uses of comparative tort law in practice and theory. It takes the view that comparative law is always a means, never an end in itself, explains how it can be utilized by judges, legislatures, and legal scholars, and puts forward important caveats and qualifications. Part 2 demonstrates the traditional role of comparative law in interpreting and implementing shared or similar tort doctrines and in providing ideas for domestic tort law gap-filling and reform. It highlights the challenges that such utilization might present. Part 3 maintains that comparative research is the cornerstone of unification endeavors. Starting with coordinated projects, Part 3 argues that unification is in itself an instrument (making comparative law a second-order instrument) and that it cannot be pursued without taking into account some concerns about its desirability and practicability. Part 3 then discusses uncoordinated unification processes, whereby lawmakers in one jurisdiction identify a “global consensus” and decide to join it, and elaborates on the normative and positive components of these strategies. Part 4 acknowledges that comparative analysis usually uncovers trans-jurisdictional diversity and argues that such findings can underlie normative and positive theories of tort law. A comparison can offer a systematic taxonomy of possible legal solutions to a particular problem, enabling scholars to critically evaluate and compare the alternatives from their preferred theoretical perspective. Moreover, any hypothesis about the impact of cultural, economic, political, technological, and other conditions and changes on the law can be substantiated or refuted through comparative analyses that seek out legal differences (or similarities) among systems with different (or similar) underlying backgrounds. Through this analysis, the article aims to reignite and enrich the debate and inspire tort-law makers and scholars to integrate comparative research into their work.
本文探讨了比较侵权法在实践和理论上的可能应用。它认为比较法本身始终是一种手段,而不是目的,解释了法官、立法机构和法律学者如何利用比较法,并提出了重要的警告和条件。第二部分论述了比较法在解释和实施共同或相似侵权学说以及为填补和改革国内侵权法空白提供思路方面的传统作用。它强调了这种利用可能带来的挑战。第三部分认为,比较研究是统一努力的基石。从协调项目开始,第3部分认为,统一本身就是一种工具(使比较法成为一种二阶工具),如果不考虑到对其可取性和实用性的一些担忧,就无法实现统一。然后,第3部分讨论了不协调的统一进程,即一个管辖区的立法者确定并决定加入“全球共识”,并阐述了这些战略的规范和积极组成部分。第4部分承认,比较分析通常揭示跨司法管辖区的多样性,并认为这些发现可以作为侵权法规范和积极理论的基础。比较可以为特定问题的可能法律解决方案提供系统的分类,使学者能够从他们喜欢的理论角度批判性地评估和比较替代方案。此外,任何关于文化、经济、政治、技术和其他条件及变化对法律影响的假设都可以通过比较分析来证实或反驳,这些比较分析旨在找出具有不同(或相似)潜在背景的制度之间的法律差异(或相似性)。通过这一分析,本文旨在重新点燃和丰富这场争论,并激励侵权法制定者和学者将比较研究纳入他们的工作中。
{"title":"Instrumental Comparative Tort Law","authors":"R. Perry","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3973401","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3973401","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This article examines the possible uses of comparative tort law in practice and theory. It takes the view that comparative law is always a means, never an end in itself, explains how it can be utilized by judges, legislatures, and legal scholars, and puts forward important caveats and qualifications. Part 2 demonstrates the traditional role of comparative law in interpreting and implementing shared or similar tort doctrines and in providing ideas for domestic tort law gap-filling and reform. It highlights the challenges that such utilization might present. Part 3 maintains that comparative research is the cornerstone of unification endeavors. Starting with coordinated projects, Part 3 argues that unification is in itself an instrument (making comparative law a second-order instrument) and that it cannot be pursued without taking into account some concerns about its desirability and practicability. Part 3 then discusses uncoordinated unification processes, whereby lawmakers in one jurisdiction identify a “global consensus” and decide to join it, and elaborates on the normative and positive components of these strategies. Part 4 acknowledges that comparative analysis usually uncovers trans-jurisdictional diversity and argues that such findings can underlie normative and positive theories of tort law. A comparison can offer a systematic taxonomy of possible legal solutions to a particular problem, enabling scholars to critically evaluate and compare the alternatives from their preferred theoretical perspective. Moreover, any hypothesis about the impact of cultural, economic, political, technological, and other conditions and changes on the law can be substantiated or refuted through comparative analyses that seek out legal differences (or similarities) among systems with different (or similar) underlying backgrounds. Through this analysis, the article aims to reignite and enrich the debate and inspire tort-law makers and scholars to integrate comparative research into their work.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"493 - 529"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45989006","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Tort Theory and Restatements: Of Immanence and Lizard Lips 侵权理论与重述:内在性与蜥蜴唇
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1515/jtl-2022-0003
N. Engstrom, Michael D. Green
Abstract This Essay gingerly enters the tort theory “wars” that torts scholars have been debating for many decades. Is the essence of tort law instrumentalism in some form, including most notably in providing appropriate incentives to minimize the costs of accidents, as Guido Calabresi normatively proposed and William Landes and Richard Posner descriptively claimed? Or, on the other hand, is tort law simply about the injurer and victim and the just manner for allocating the victim’s loss—blind to any collateral consequences? We address these debates from our perspective as Restatement Reporters, honing in on the question of what role tort theory plays in our work. Our answer is virtually none. There are two independent and sufficient reasons for this conclusion. First, we are deeply skeptical that there is an immanent meta-theory that explains tort law or guides its development. Instead, we think tort law is a hodgepodge, influenced by public policy, culture, administrative concerns, evidentiary lacunae, technological developments, and random events. These eclectic and shifting forces influence what tort law is and how it evolves with the felt needs of any given era. Tort law, in short, is built from the bottom up, not the top down and is far too messy to be the product of intelligent design. Beyond that, even if there were such a force at tort law’s heart, that force would still have little influence on our work. The doctrinal level at which Restatements operate and the case law that fuels the production of Restatements—ground level law—is a disjunction from theory, which operates at 30,000 feet. This disjunction means that the latter is of little assistance when it comes to addressing the quotidian matters important to tort law and Restatements. Whether tort law is entirely instrumental or solely about corrective justice cannot answer the question of whether parents should have immunity from tort suits by their children. The answer to that question must be found in the case law, not in Kant.
摘要本文小心翼翼地进入了侵权学界争论了几十年的侵权理论“战争”。侵权法的本质是某种形式的工具主义吗,包括提供适当的激励以使事故成本最小化,正如Guido Calabresi规范性地提出的以及William Landes和Richard Posner的描述性主张?或者,另一方面,侵权法仅仅是关于加害人和受害者以及分配受害者损失的公正方式——无视任何附带后果吗?我们从我们作为重述记者的角度来解决这些争论,专注于侵权理论在我们的工作中扮演的角色。我们的答案是几乎没有。这一结论有两个独立而充分的理由。首先,我们对是否存在一种内在的元理论来解释侵权法或指导其发展深表怀疑。相反,我们认为侵权法是一个大杂烩,受到公共政策、文化、行政问题、证据缺失、技术发展和随机事件的影响。这些折衷的和不断变化的力量影响着侵权法是什么,以及它如何随着任何特定时代的感觉需求而演变。简而言之,侵权法是由下而上建立的,而不是由上而下建立的,它太混乱了,不可能是智能设计的产物。除此之外,即使侵权法的核心存在这样一种力量,这种力量对我们的工作也几乎没有影响。《重述》所处的理论层面和推动《重述》产生的判例法——基础层面法——与理论是脱节的,而理论在三万英尺的高空运行。这种分离意味着,当涉及到解决侵权法和重述重要的日常事务时,后者几乎没有帮助。无论侵权法完全是工具性的还是仅仅是关于纠正性正义的,都不能回答父母是否应该对其子女的侵权诉讼享有豁免权的问题。这个问题的答案必须在判例法中找到,而不是在康德中。
{"title":"Tort Theory and Restatements: Of Immanence and Lizard Lips","authors":"N. Engstrom, Michael D. Green","doi":"10.1515/jtl-2022-0003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jtl-2022-0003","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This Essay gingerly enters the tort theory “wars” that torts scholars have been debating for many decades. Is the essence of tort law instrumentalism in some form, including most notably in providing appropriate incentives to minimize the costs of accidents, as Guido Calabresi normatively proposed and William Landes and Richard Posner descriptively claimed? Or, on the other hand, is tort law simply about the injurer and victim and the just manner for allocating the victim’s loss—blind to any collateral consequences? We address these debates from our perspective as Restatement Reporters, honing in on the question of what role tort theory plays in our work. Our answer is virtually none. There are two independent and sufficient reasons for this conclusion. First, we are deeply skeptical that there is an immanent meta-theory that explains tort law or guides its development. Instead, we think tort law is a hodgepodge, influenced by public policy, culture, administrative concerns, evidentiary lacunae, technological developments, and random events. These eclectic and shifting forces influence what tort law is and how it evolves with the felt needs of any given era. Tort law, in short, is built from the bottom up, not the top down and is far too messy to be the product of intelligent design. Beyond that, even if there were such a force at tort law’s heart, that force would still have little influence on our work. The doctrinal level at which Restatements operate and the case law that fuels the production of Restatements—ground level law—is a disjunction from theory, which operates at 30,000 feet. This disjunction means that the latter is of little assistance when it comes to addressing the quotidian matters important to tort law and Restatements. Whether tort law is entirely instrumental or solely about corrective justice cannot answer the question of whether parents should have immunity from tort suits by their children. The answer to that question must be found in the case law, not in Kant.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"333 - 372"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48294514","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Justifying and Categorizing Tort Doctrines: What is the Optimal Level of Generality? 侵权理论的证明和分类:什么是最佳概括水平?
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.4006612
K. Simons
Abstract This essay explores the issue of generality and tort law from two directions. First, when common law judges offer justifications of tort doctrine, what is the appropriate level of generality or specificity of those justifying principles and policies? Second, when judges identify and refine tort doctrines, what is the appropriate level of generality or specificity of the doctrines themselves? With respect to the first issue, Stephen A. Smith has argued that judges ordinarily do, and should, invoke only “intermediate” justifications for their decisions (such as dignity, fairness, or reasonableness), rather than “foundational” ones (such as utilitarianism or corrective justice). Smith’s argument has some purchase: intermediate principles indeed do and should play a prominent role in common law decision-making. However, foundational principles can legitimately play a more significant role than Smith suggests, especially if they are pluralistic. And intermediate principles are sometimes too vacuous to operate as genuine justifications. With respect to the second issue, Stephen D. Sugarman and Caitlin Boucher have proposed that numerous torts that might be characterized as “dignitary” torts should be merged into a single “unifying” tort, the tort of wrongfully harming another’s dignity in a highly offensive way. The authors plausibly argue that courts have not paid sufficient attention to gaps and arbitrary distinctions between these torts. However, their more radical claim that one uber-tort should replace all “dignitary” torts is not persuasive. Torts as distinct as battery, false imprisonment, intrusion into a private place, and malicious prosecution reflect distinct wrongs and should not be supplanted by a single tort prohibiting wrongful and highly offensive conduct. The analysis offered in this essay is informed by many examples from the Restatement Third, Torts: Intentional Torts to Persons, for which I have served as co-Reporter or Reporter.
摘要本文从两个方向探讨了一般性与侵权法问题。首先,当普通法法官为侵权原则提供辩护时,这些辩护原则和政策的普遍性或特殊性的适当程度是多少?其次,当法官识别和完善侵权原则时,原则本身的普遍性或特殊性的适当程度是多少?关于第一个问题,斯蒂芬·a·史密斯(Stephen A. Smith)认为,法官通常只会、也应该援引“中间”理由(如尊严、公平或合理性),而不是“基本”理由(如功利主义或纠正正义)。史密斯的观点有一定的可取之处:中间原则确实在普通法决策中发挥并且应该发挥突出作用。然而,基本原则可以合法地发挥比史密斯所建议的更重要的作用,特别是如果它们是多元的。中间原则有时过于空洞,无法作为真正的理由。关于第二个问题,斯蒂芬·d·舒格曼(Stephen D. Sugarman)和凯特琳·鲍彻(Caitlin Boucher)提出,许多可能被定性为“尊严”侵权的侵权行为应该合并为一个单一的“统一”侵权行为,即以高度冒犯的方式错误地损害他人尊严的侵权行为。作者似乎认为,法院没有对这些侵权行为之间的差距和任意区分给予足够的重视。然而,他们更为激进的主张,即一种超级侵权行为应该取代所有“尊严”侵权行为,是没有说服力的。像殴打、非法监禁、侵入私人场所和恶意起诉等不同的侵权行为反映了不同的错误,不应被禁止错误和高度冒犯性行为的单一侵权行为所取代。本文所提供的分析来自于《重述三:侵权:对人的故意侵权》中的许多例子,我曾担任该重述三的联合记者或记者。
{"title":"Justifying and Categorizing Tort Doctrines: What is the Optimal Level of Generality?","authors":"K. Simons","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.4006612","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.4006612","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This essay explores the issue of generality and tort law from two directions. First, when common law judges offer justifications of tort doctrine, what is the appropriate level of generality or specificity of those justifying principles and policies? Second, when judges identify and refine tort doctrines, what is the appropriate level of generality or specificity of the doctrines themselves? With respect to the first issue, Stephen A. Smith has argued that judges ordinarily do, and should, invoke only “intermediate” justifications for their decisions (such as dignity, fairness, or reasonableness), rather than “foundational” ones (such as utilitarianism or corrective justice). Smith’s argument has some purchase: intermediate principles indeed do and should play a prominent role in common law decision-making. However, foundational principles can legitimately play a more significant role than Smith suggests, especially if they are pluralistic. And intermediate principles are sometimes too vacuous to operate as genuine justifications. With respect to the second issue, Stephen D. Sugarman and Caitlin Boucher have proposed that numerous torts that might be characterized as “dignitary” torts should be merged into a single “unifying” tort, the tort of wrongfully harming another’s dignity in a highly offensive way. The authors plausibly argue that courts have not paid sufficient attention to gaps and arbitrary distinctions between these torts. However, their more radical claim that one uber-tort should replace all “dignitary” torts is not persuasive. Torts as distinct as battery, false imprisonment, intrusion into a private place, and malicious prosecution reflect distinct wrongs and should not be supplanted by a single tort prohibiting wrongful and highly offensive conduct. The analysis offered in this essay is informed by many examples from the Restatement Third, Torts: Intentional Torts to Persons, for which I have served as co-Reporter or Reporter.","PeriodicalId":39054,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Tort Law","volume":"14 1","pages":"551 - 573"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42306696","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of Tort Law
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1