首页 > 最新文献

Law and Contemporary Problems最新文献

英文 中文
Scientific Models of Human Health Risk Analysis in Legal and Policy Decisions 法律和政策决策中人类健康风险分析的科学模型
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-09-22 DOI: 10.2307/1192291
D. Crawford‐Brown
DOUGLAS CRAWFORD-BROWN [*] I INTRODUCTION Scientists working in the fields of law or policy faced with risk-based decisions find themselves in very different positions epistemologically than those in the routine practice of science. First, risk assessment is an interdisciplinary activity, requiring the piecing together of expertise from many fields. Only a community of scientists could possess so much expertise. It is problematic when a single scientist, or a small group of them, is called upon to speak on behalf of the entire community. Second, science is by nature forward-looking. It is a process by which truth is progressively refined and approached, rather than an end point. In court, or in the policy arena, however, scientists are called on to "freeze" this process in a snapshot that will be regarded as final. Scientists may have little or no experience in this activity. The quality of scientific predictions of risk in the courtroom and policy arena rests in large measure on how these two differences between the normal practice and the legal/po licy practice of science are reconciled. This article considers a variety of issues that arise in reconciling these differences, and the problems that remain with scientific estimates of risk when these are used in decisions. II DEFINITION OF RISK Before turning to the issues arising from risk predictions, a definition of risk is needed. Three schools of thought are prevalent in the field of risk assessment. [1] (1) Objective risk. This school treats risk as an objective property of the world, much like any other scientific concept. Risk is identified with a combination of the probability and the severity of an outcome. [2] Often, the combination is the mathematical product of the probability and the severity, but this operation is not scientifically or logically necessary, as is demonstrated by the fact that there are competing operations in the scientific community such as Quality Adjusted Life Years ("QALY"). [3] (2) Subjective risk. This school treats risk as a subjective property of individuals in a society. Risk is identified as the degree of concern, or dread, expressed by an individual over some situation. It is measured using polls based on expressed or revealed opinions. [4] (3) Psychologistic risk. This school treats risk as a property of epistemological reflection, or analysis of existing evidence. Risk is identified as the degree of evidentiary support for the belief that an adverse effect will occur under certain circumstances. This school shares features with the objective school, such as the recognition that risks are related to probabilities. It is closer, however, to the Bayesian conception of probability because the objective school employs a long-term frequency concept of probability. [5] While some social scientists adhere to the subjective concept of risk, it generally is not the concept employed in the practice of natural science or in legal or policy decisionmaking. The differe
在法律或政策领域工作的科学家面临着基于风险的决策,他们发现自己在认识论上的立场与日常科学实践中的立场非常不同。首先,风险评估是一项跨学科的活动,需要将许多领域的专业知识拼凑在一起。只有一个科学家团体才能拥有如此多的专业知识。当一个科学家或一小群科学家被要求代表整个科学界发言时,这是有问题的。第二,科学本质上是前瞻性的。它是真理逐渐被提炼和接近的过程,而不是终点。然而,在法庭上或在政策舞台上,科学家们被要求将这一过程“冻结”在一个将被视为最终结果的快照中。科学家在这方面可能很少或根本没有经验。法庭和政策领域对风险的科学预测的质量在很大程度上取决于如何调和科学的正常实践和法律/政策实践之间的这两种差异。本文考虑了在协调这些差异时出现的各种问题,以及在决策中使用科学风险评估时仍然存在的问题。在讨论由风险预测引起的问题之前,需要对风险进行定义。在风险评估领域有三种流行的思想流派。[1](1)客观风险。这一学派将风险视为世界的客观属性,就像任何其他科学概念一样。风险是通过结果的可能性和严重程度的结合来确定的。[2]通常,这种组合是概率和严重程度的数学乘积,但这种操作在科学上或逻辑上都不是必要的,正如科学界存在竞争性操作(如质量调整生命年)这一事实所证明的那样。[3](2)主观风险。这个学派把风险看作是社会中个人的主观属性。风险是指个体在某种情况下所表现出的担忧或恐惧程度。它是通过基于表达或透露的意见的民意调查来衡量的。[4](3)心理风险。该学派将风险视为认识论反思或现有证据分析的一种属性。风险是指在某种情况下会发生不利影响的证据支持程度。这一学派与客观学派有共同的特点,比如认为风险与概率有关。然而,它更接近于贝叶斯的概率概念,因为客观学派采用了概率的长期频率概念。[5]虽然一些社会科学家坚持风险的主观概念,但它通常不是自然科学实践或法律或政策决策中使用的概念。然而,风险的客观概念和心理概念之间的区别在实际中并不像其他方面那样明显。例如,两者的支持者都会同意美国国家科学院国家研究委员会的以下声明:人类健康风险评估需要评估关于环境物质的危险特性和人类接触这些物质的程度的科学信息。评估的结果是关于暴露在这种情况下的人群受到伤害的可能性及其程度的陈述。概率可以用定量或相对定性的方式来表示。此外,双方都同意风险包括概率和严重性。两者都同意概率和严重性是世界的客观属性。然而,客观学派仅仅将风险等同于概率和严重性,而心理学派则为风险增加了第三个组成部分:对概率和严重性估计的理性信心。…
{"title":"Scientific Models of Human Health Risk Analysis in Legal and Policy Decisions","authors":"D. Crawford‐Brown","doi":"10.2307/1192291","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192291","url":null,"abstract":"DOUGLAS CRAWFORD-BROWN [*] I INTRODUCTION Scientists working in the fields of law or policy faced with risk-based decisions find themselves in very different positions epistemologically than those in the routine practice of science. First, risk assessment is an interdisciplinary activity, requiring the piecing together of expertise from many fields. Only a community of scientists could possess so much expertise. It is problematic when a single scientist, or a small group of them, is called upon to speak on behalf of the entire community. Second, science is by nature forward-looking. It is a process by which truth is progressively refined and approached, rather than an end point. In court, or in the policy arena, however, scientists are called on to \"freeze\" this process in a snapshot that will be regarded as final. Scientists may have little or no experience in this activity. The quality of scientific predictions of risk in the courtroom and policy arena rests in large measure on how these two differences between the normal practice and the legal/po licy practice of science are reconciled. This article considers a variety of issues that arise in reconciling these differences, and the problems that remain with scientific estimates of risk when these are used in decisions. II DEFINITION OF RISK Before turning to the issues arising from risk predictions, a definition of risk is needed. Three schools of thought are prevalent in the field of risk assessment. [1] (1) Objective risk. This school treats risk as an objective property of the world, much like any other scientific concept. Risk is identified with a combination of the probability and the severity of an outcome. [2] Often, the combination is the mathematical product of the probability and the severity, but this operation is not scientifically or logically necessary, as is demonstrated by the fact that there are competing operations in the scientific community such as Quality Adjusted Life Years (\"QALY\"). [3] (2) Subjective risk. This school treats risk as a subjective property of individuals in a society. Risk is identified as the degree of concern, or dread, expressed by an individual over some situation. It is measured using polls based on expressed or revealed opinions. [4] (3) Psychologistic risk. This school treats risk as a property of epistemological reflection, or analysis of existing evidence. Risk is identified as the degree of evidentiary support for the belief that an adverse effect will occur under certain circumstances. This school shares features with the objective school, such as the recognition that risks are related to probabilities. It is closer, however, to the Bayesian conception of probability because the objective school employs a long-term frequency concept of probability. [5] While some social scientists adhere to the subjective concept of risk, it generally is not the concept employed in the practice of natural science or in legal or policy decisionmaking. The differe","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"43 1","pages":"63-82"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86008588","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Rationalism and Empiricism in Modern Medicine 现代医学中的理性主义与经验主义
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-09-22 DOI: 10.2307/1192299
W. Newton
WARREN NEWTON [*] I INTRODUCTION About ten years ago, after fellowships and clinical experience in a community setting, I had my first experience as a ward attending in a university hospital. [1] We were working with cardiac patients, and I was struck by the common treatment each patient received. No matter what the symptoms, patients received an exercise treadmill, an echocardiogram, and were put on a calcium channel blocker. [2] This was remarkable at the time because there were in excess of thirty randomized controlled trials showing the benefit of beta-blockers, a different class of medicines, to treat patients following a heart attack. Indeed, by 1990, there was initial evidence that calcium channel blockers not only failed to improve outcomes, but actually made them worse. The point is not to criticize the medical culture at that hospital--similar examples can be found at every medical center--but rather to explore why there was so much fondness for calcium channel blockers. One factor was the substantial drug company support of faculty research on silent myocardial ischemia. Another factor was what might be called medical fashion. The most likely explanation, however, was more fundamental. For my cardiology colleagues, it was biologically plausible that calcium channel blockers were better than betablockers. Like beta-blockers, calcium channel blockers reduce heart rate and myocardial wall stress, but they lack the side effects of beta-blockers. In other words, what was important to my colleagues was not the outcome of the critical trials, but our understanding of the mechanisms of disease. This is an example of the tension between rationalism and empiricism in medicine. Rationalism is the search for and emphasis on basic mechanisms of disease, which then color all clinical decisions. Empiricism is defined as the emphasis on the outcomes of individual patients and groups of patients. My thesis is that there is an ongoing and fundamental tension between these two different ways of thinking. While these ways of thinking can be complementary, the tension persists, exploding around specific clinical and legal controversies. Understanding the tension between rationalism and empiricism provides important background in considering the role of expert advice. Part II of this article explores the roots of rationalism and empiricism in the Hippocratic tradition. Using the Flexner report as a text, Part III emphasizes the triumph of the rationalists in the founding of modern medicine. Part IV briefly describes the development of clinical epidemiology and the evidence-based medicine over the last thirty years. Part VI attempts to explicate how this tension illuminates fundamental clinical and policy questions that doctors, the health care system, and the legal system confront today. My goal is not to present a detailed explication of the epistemology of medical science, but rather an intellectual history [3] sketching out what has animated the thinking
大约十年前,在获得了社区的研究和临床经验之后,我第一次有了在一所大学医院当病房护理员的经历。[1]我们治疗的是心脏病患者,我对每个患者接受的普通治疗感到震惊。无论症状如何,患者都接受了跑步机锻炼,超声心动图检查,并服用钙通道阻滞剂。[2]这在当时是值得注意的,因为有超过30个随机对照试验显示了-受体阻滞剂(另一类药物)治疗心脏病发作后的疗效。事实上,到1990年,有初步证据表明,钙通道阻滞剂不仅不能改善结果,反而会使情况变得更糟。重点不是要批评那家医院的医疗文化——类似的例子在每家医疗中心都能找到——而是要探讨为什么人们如此喜欢钙通道阻滞剂。一个因素是大量的制药公司支持教师对无症状心肌缺血的研究。另一个因素可能是所谓的医疗时尚。然而,最可能的解释却是更为根本的。对于我的心脏病学同事来说,从生物学角度来说,钙通道阻滞剂比β受体阻滞剂更好是合理的。像β受体阻滞剂一样,钙通道阻滞剂可以降低心率和心肌壁压力,但它们没有β受体阻滞剂的副作用。换句话说,对我的同事来说,重要的不是关键试验的结果,而是我们对疾病机制的理解。这是医学上理性主义和经验主义之间矛盾的一个例子。理性主义是对疾病基本机制的探索和强调,它为所有的临床决策涂上了色彩。经验主义被定义为强调患者个体和患者群体的结果。我的论点是,在这两种不同的思维方式之间存在着一种持续的、根本的紧张关系。虽然这些思维方式可以互补,但紧张局势仍然存在,围绕具体的临床和法律争议爆发。理解理性主义和经验主义之间的紧张关系为考虑专家建议的作用提供了重要的背景。本文的第二部分探讨了希波克拉底传统中理性主义和经验主义的根源。第三部分以Flexner报告为文本,强调了理性主义者在现代医学建立中的胜利。第四部分简要介绍了近三十年来临床流行病学和循证医学的发展。第六部分试图解释这种紧张关系如何阐明医生、医疗保健系统和法律系统今天面临的基本临床和政策问题。我的目标不是对医学科学的认识论进行详细的解释,而是描绘出一个思想史[3],勾勒出是什么激发了临床医生的思维。希波克拉底的传统建立在许多作家的基础上,不仅是历史上的科斯的希波克拉底,还有从希腊到亚历山大再到罗马的许多后来的作家。这篇文章主要关注从公元前4世纪到罗马时代在亚历山大统治的两个主要教派。[4]在古典时代,主导医学影响的是理性主义。理性主义的起源可以追溯到希波克拉底的儿子塞萨洛和德拉坎,是最古老的教派。塞萨洛斯和德拉坎斯强调自然哲学在医学中的重要性,认为“在观察失败的地方,理性可能会带来惊喜。”[5]基本理论是毕达哥拉斯首先提出的“幽默”学说:人的身体里有血液、痰、黄胆汁和黑胆汁……[N]现在,当这些因素在复合力和体积方面彼此适当地成比例,当它们完美地混合在一起时,他就能享有最完美的健康。…
{"title":"Rationalism and Empiricism in Modern Medicine","authors":"W. Newton","doi":"10.2307/1192299","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192299","url":null,"abstract":"WARREN NEWTON [*] I INTRODUCTION About ten years ago, after fellowships and clinical experience in a community setting, I had my first experience as a ward attending in a university hospital. [1] We were working with cardiac patients, and I was struck by the common treatment each patient received. No matter what the symptoms, patients received an exercise treadmill, an echocardiogram, and were put on a calcium channel blocker. [2] This was remarkable at the time because there were in excess of thirty randomized controlled trials showing the benefit of beta-blockers, a different class of medicines, to treat patients following a heart attack. Indeed, by 1990, there was initial evidence that calcium channel blockers not only failed to improve outcomes, but actually made them worse. The point is not to criticize the medical culture at that hospital--similar examples can be found at every medical center--but rather to explore why there was so much fondness for calcium channel blockers. One factor was the substantial drug company support of faculty research on silent myocardial ischemia. Another factor was what might be called medical fashion. The most likely explanation, however, was more fundamental. For my cardiology colleagues, it was biologically plausible that calcium channel blockers were better than betablockers. Like beta-blockers, calcium channel blockers reduce heart rate and myocardial wall stress, but they lack the side effects of beta-blockers. In other words, what was important to my colleagues was not the outcome of the critical trials, but our understanding of the mechanisms of disease. This is an example of the tension between rationalism and empiricism in medicine. Rationalism is the search for and emphasis on basic mechanisms of disease, which then color all clinical decisions. Empiricism is defined as the emphasis on the outcomes of individual patients and groups of patients. My thesis is that there is an ongoing and fundamental tension between these two different ways of thinking. While these ways of thinking can be complementary, the tension persists, exploding around specific clinical and legal controversies. Understanding the tension between rationalism and empiricism provides important background in considering the role of expert advice. Part II of this article explores the roots of rationalism and empiricism in the Hippocratic tradition. Using the Flexner report as a text, Part III emphasizes the triumph of the rationalists in the founding of modern medicine. Part IV briefly describes the development of clinical epidemiology and the evidence-based medicine over the last thirty years. Part VI attempts to explicate how this tension illuminates fundamental clinical and policy questions that doctors, the health care system, and the legal system confront today. My goal is not to present a detailed explication of the epistemology of medical science, but rather an intellectual history [3] sketching out what has animated the thinking","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"21 1","pages":"299-316"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82780244","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 19
Beyond "It Just Ain't Worth It": Alternative Strategies for Damage Class Action Reform 超越“它只是不值得”:损害集体诉讼改革的替代策略
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-06-25 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.274949
D. Hensler, Thomas D. Rowe
In this article we explore alternative strategies for class action reform aimed at improving the cost-benefit ratio of a damage class action regime. Our analysis draws on RAND's recently completed study of contemporary damage class action practice and on the extensive theoretical literature on entrepreneurial litigation. Our goal is to identify mechanisms for enhancing the system's capacity to screen out non-meritorious suits, while preserving access for meritorious actions. While recognizing other concerns related to class actions (such as agency problems between class counsel and class members, and ethical issues), we do not address these problems except as they pertain to the question of screening. Similarly, we do not attempt to discuss the full range of proposals that have been put forward to address the various perceived problems relating to damage class actions, but instead focus on those proposals that are most relevant to the question of screening. The first two strategies we consider would attempt to enhance the system's screening capacity directly, at the front end of the litigation process, by applying a cost-benefit test at the time of certification, or by requiring class members to decide whether to participate at the inception of litigation. We conclude that it is unlikely that judges could apply a cost-benefit test fairly and consistently, and that an opt-in requirement might screen out as many meritorious suits as non-meritorious actions (if not more). The next two strategies would attempt to enhance the system's screening capacity indirectly, at the back end rather than the front end. The first and relatively non-controversial back-end strategy relies on judges to use more vigorously their authority to scrutinize class action settlements and fee award requests. By better calibrating the benefits to class members and financial rewards to class counsel, more rigorous judicial management would drive out "bad" class actions while maintaining access for meritorious lawsuits. The theoretical literature on entrepreneurial litigation and RAND's case study investigations provide the grounding for this strategy. While we believe that increased judicial scrutiny could substantially improve the system's screening capacity, relying solely on judicial discretion for regulatory purposes has some obvious weaknesses?particularly in our federal system, in which parties who cannot satisfy one judge may simply depart that jurisdiction for another whose judges are more congenial. Hence we consider a different and more controversial approach to re-calibrating incentives to file and settle non-meritorious suits: adopting loser-pays attorney fee-shifting for certified damage class actions, with liability on the plaintiffs' side borne by class counsel. Although critics of class actions have proposed other manipulations of financial incentives, such as auctions, to improve the cost-benefit ratio of damage class actions, those who support the use of repre
在本文中,我们探讨了旨在提高损害集体诉讼制度的成本效益比的集体诉讼改革的替代策略。我们的分析借鉴了兰德公司最近完成的关于当代损害集体诉讼实践的研究,以及关于企业诉讼的大量理论文献。我们的目标是确定一种机制,以增强系统筛选非正当诉讼的能力,同时保留对正当行为的访问。虽然认识到与集体诉讼相关的其他问题(如集体律师和集体成员之间的代理问题,以及道德问题),但我们不解决这些问题,除非它们与筛选问题有关。同样,我们不试图讨论已提出的解决与损害集体诉讼有关的各种已知问题的所有建议,而是将重点放在与筛选问题最相关的建议上。我们考虑的前两种策略将试图在诉讼过程的前端直接增强系统的筛选能力,方法是在认证时应用成本效益测试,或者要求集体成员在诉讼开始时决定是否参与。我们的结论是,法官不太可能公平和一致地应用成本效益测试,而选择加入的要求可能会筛选出与非有价值行为一样多的有价值诉讼(如果不是更多的话)。接下来的两项战略将试图间接提高系统的筛选能力,在后端而不是前端。第一种、也是相对没有争议的后端策略依赖于法官更积极地使用他们的权力来审查集体诉讼和解和费用赔偿请求。通过更好地调整集体诉讼成员的利益和集体诉讼律师的经济回报,更严格的司法管理将驱逐“不良”集体诉讼,同时保持有价值诉讼的机会。关于创业诉讼的理论文献和兰德公司的案例研究调查为这一战略提供了基础。虽然我们认为增加司法审查可以大大提高系统的筛选能力,但仅仅依靠司法自由裁量权进行监管有一些明显的弱点。特别是在我们的联邦制度中,当事人如果不能让一个法官满意,就可以简单地离开这个司法管辖区,去找另一个法官更合意的法官。因此,我们考虑了一种不同的、更有争议的方法来重新调整提起和解决不值得的诉讼的动机:对已证实的损害集体诉讼采取败诉支付律师费转移,原告一方的责任由集体律师承担。尽管对集体诉讼持批评态度的人提出了其他操纵财政激励的方法,如拍卖,以提高损害集体诉讼的成本效益比,但至少在某些情况下,那些支持使用代表诉讼的人普遍拒绝立即转移费用。我们的分析表明,这种败诉赔偿制度可能会对损害集体诉讼制度产生一些积极影响,因为它增加了提起非正当诉讼的成本,同时在一定程度上增加了追求正当诉讼的利益。然而,将这种方法整合到美国集体诉讼实践中所遇到的许多实际问题,使人们对其实用性产生了疑问,而且目前尚不清楚成本效益比的改善是否大到足以值得寻求解决这些棘手问题的办法。因此,我们最后敦促进一步关注司法监管,同时邀请对收费转移策略进行更认真的学术考虑。
{"title":"Beyond \"It Just Ain't Worth It\": Alternative Strategies for Damage Class Action Reform","authors":"D. Hensler, Thomas D. Rowe","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.274949","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.274949","url":null,"abstract":"In this article we explore alternative strategies for class action reform aimed at improving the cost-benefit ratio of a damage class action regime. Our analysis draws on RAND's recently completed study of contemporary damage class action practice and on the extensive theoretical literature on entrepreneurial litigation. Our goal is to identify mechanisms for enhancing the system's capacity to screen out non-meritorious suits, while preserving access for meritorious actions. While recognizing other concerns related to class actions (such as agency problems between class counsel and class members, and ethical issues), we do not address these problems except as they pertain to the question of screening. Similarly, we do not attempt to discuss the full range of proposals that have been put forward to address the various perceived problems relating to damage class actions, but instead focus on those proposals that are most relevant to the question of screening. The first two strategies we consider would attempt to enhance the system's screening capacity directly, at the front end of the litigation process, by applying a cost-benefit test at the time of certification, or by requiring class members to decide whether to participate at the inception of litigation. We conclude that it is unlikely that judges could apply a cost-benefit test fairly and consistently, and that an opt-in requirement might screen out as many meritorious suits as non-meritorious actions (if not more). The next two strategies would attempt to enhance the system's screening capacity indirectly, at the back end rather than the front end. The first and relatively non-controversial back-end strategy relies on judges to use more vigorously their authority to scrutinize class action settlements and fee award requests. By better calibrating the benefits to class members and financial rewards to class counsel, more rigorous judicial management would drive out \"bad\" class actions while maintaining access for meritorious lawsuits. The theoretical literature on entrepreneurial litigation and RAND's case study investigations provide the grounding for this strategy. While we believe that increased judicial scrutiny could substantially improve the system's screening capacity, relying solely on judicial discretion for regulatory purposes has some obvious weaknesses?particularly in our federal system, in which parties who cannot satisfy one judge may simply depart that jurisdiction for another whose judges are more congenial. Hence we consider a different and more controversial approach to re-calibrating incentives to file and settle non-meritorious suits: adopting loser-pays attorney fee-shifting for certified damage class actions, with liability on the plaintiffs' side borne by class counsel. Although critics of class actions have proposed other manipulations of financial incentives, such as auctions, to improve the cost-benefit ratio of damage class actions, those who support the use of repre","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"4 1","pages":"137-162"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-06-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88754204","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 11
Aggregation, Auctions, and other Developments in the Selection of Lead Counsel Under the PSLRA 根据PSLRA选择首席律师的汇总、拍卖和其他进展
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-03-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.261580
Jill E. Fisch
This article focuses on aggregation and auctions, two key litigation developments in the selection of counsel under the Private Securities Litigation Reform Act of 1995. After reviewing some of the background concerns, including collective action problems presented by the class action structure and issues regarding the award of attorneys fees, the article explains how the lead plaintiff provision, adopted by Congress, addresses these concerns through a model of client empowerment. The article then explains two recent trends: the use of lead counsel groups, in which courts appoint multiple investors and aggregate their holdings, and the use of an auction procedure to select lead counsel and determine counsel fees. The trends deal with facially separate issues, yet they are disturbing for the same reasons. First, both aggregation and lead counsel auctions weaken the relationship between the lead plaintiff and class counsel and specifically reduce the ability of the lead plaintiff to exert control over litigation decisionmaking. Second, both trends lead to serious problems in implementing the lead plaintiff provision. Finally, the trends maintain an active judicial role in supervising the conduct of the litigation. The article challenges the propriety of aggregation and auctions under the PSLRA, arguing that neither development is supported by the statutory text or legislative history. The article further argues that these approaches are inconsistent with and likely to frustrate the objectives of the PSLRA. Courts that appoint groups of unrelated investors as lead plaintiffs will face difficult questions of appropriate group size and composition. Lead plaintiff groups are unlikely to function in accordance with the statutory design; in particular, they are unlikely to select or monitor class counsel effectively. Selection of lead counsel by auction is not an attractive alternative. Lead counsel auctions present substantial issues in design and implementation, and there is little reason to believe that a judicially conducted auction can replicate the market process or result in a selection decision and fee award more appropriate than the decisions made by a suitable lead plaintiff. Finally, the article argues that both developments are based on the mistaken perception that class action abuses can be addressed through judicial oversight. In adopting the lead plaintiff provision, however, Congress expressly rejected this premise. The effect of both aggregation and lead counsel auctions is to maintain judicial empowerment at the expense of client control. This approach undermines the potential for client empowerment to achieve meaningful litigation reform.
本文主要关注1995年《私人证券诉讼改革法案》下律师选择的两个关键诉讼进展——聚合和拍卖。在回顾了一些背景问题之后,包括集体诉讼结构带来的集体诉讼问题以及与律师费奖励有关的问题,本文解释了国会采用的主要原告条款如何通过客户授权模式解决这些问题。文章随后解释了最近的两个趋势:使用首席律师小组,法院指定多个投资者并汇总他们的持股,以及使用拍卖程序选择首席律师并确定律师费。这些趋势处理的是表面上不同的问题,但出于同样的原因,它们令人不安。首先,集体律师拍卖和首席律师拍卖都削弱了首席原告与集体律师之间的关系,特别是降低了首席原告对诉讼决策施加控制的能力。其次,这两种趋势都导致了主要原告条款在执行中的严重问题。最后,趋势在监督诉讼行为方面保持了积极的司法作用。文章对PSLRA下的聚合和拍卖的适当性提出了质疑,认为这两种发展都没有得到法定文本或立法历史的支持。这篇文章进一步指出,这些方法不符合并有可能使PSLRA的目标受挫。指派不相关的投资者团体作为主要原告的法院将面临团体规模和组成适当的难题。主要原告团体不太可能按照法定设计运作;特别是,他们不可能有效地选择或监督集体律师。通过拍卖方式选择首席律师并不是一个有吸引力的选择。首席律师拍卖在设计和实施方面存在重大问题,并且没有理由相信司法进行的拍卖可以复制市场过程或产生比合适的首席原告做出的决定更合适的选择决定和费用裁决。最后,本文认为,这两种发展都是基于一种错误的观念,即集体诉讼的滥用可以通过司法监督来解决。然而,在采用主要原告条款时,国会明确拒绝了这一前提。集体律师和首席律师拍卖的效果都是以牺牲客户控制为代价来维持司法授权。这种做法破坏了赋予客户权力以实现有意义的诉讼改革的潜力。
{"title":"Aggregation, Auctions, and other Developments in the Selection of Lead Counsel Under the PSLRA","authors":"Jill E. Fisch","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.261580","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.261580","url":null,"abstract":"This article focuses on aggregation and auctions, two key litigation developments in the selection of counsel under the Private Securities Litigation Reform Act of 1995. After reviewing some of the background concerns, including collective action problems presented by the class action structure and issues regarding the award of attorneys fees, the article explains how the lead plaintiff provision, adopted by Congress, addresses these concerns through a model of client empowerment. The article then explains two recent trends: the use of lead counsel groups, in which courts appoint multiple investors and aggregate their holdings, and the use of an auction procedure to select lead counsel and determine counsel fees. The trends deal with facially separate issues, yet they are disturbing for the same reasons. First, both aggregation and lead counsel auctions weaken the relationship between the lead plaintiff and class counsel and specifically reduce the ability of the lead plaintiff to exert control over litigation decisionmaking. Second, both trends lead to serious problems in implementing the lead plaintiff provision. Finally, the trends maintain an active judicial role in supervising the conduct of the litigation. The article challenges the propriety of aggregation and auctions under the PSLRA, arguing that neither development is supported by the statutory text or legislative history. The article further argues that these approaches are inconsistent with and likely to frustrate the objectives of the PSLRA. Courts that appoint groups of unrelated investors as lead plaintiffs will face difficult questions of appropriate group size and composition. Lead plaintiff groups are unlikely to function in accordance with the statutory design; in particular, they are unlikely to select or monitor class counsel effectively. Selection of lead counsel by auction is not an attractive alternative. Lead counsel auctions present substantial issues in design and implementation, and there is little reason to believe that a judicially conducted auction can replicate the market process or result in a selection decision and fee award more appropriate than the decisions made by a suitable lead plaintiff. Finally, the article argues that both developments are based on the mistaken perception that class action abuses can be addressed through judicial oversight. In adopting the lead plaintiff provision, however, Congress expressly rejected this premise. The effect of both aggregation and lead counsel auctions is to maintain judicial empowerment at the expense of client control. This approach undermines the potential for client empowerment to achieve meaningful litigation reform.","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"13 1","pages":"53-96"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81397017","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 16
Scientific Misconceptions Among Daubert Gatekeepers: The Need for Reform of Expert Review Procedures 道伯特看门人之间的科学误解:专家评审程序改革的必要性
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-03-22 DOI: 10.2307/1192316
J. Beyea, D. Berger
JAN BEYEA [*] DANIEL BERGER [**] I INTRODUCTION The Supreme Court's opinions in Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc. [1], General Electric Company v. Joiner [2], and Kumho Tire v. Carmichael [3] contain two inconsistent views of science. In some places, the Court views science as an imperfect "process" for refining theories, whereas in other places, the Court views science as universal knowledge derived through "formal logic." The latter view, long out of favor with philosophers and historians of science, comports with the current cultural vision of science and is likely to be adopted by district and appeals court judges, without vigorous "education," or until such time as higher courts recognize that the two views need to be synthesized into a consistent whole. The interpretation of science as seamless logic puts an undue burden on scientific experts who are challenged under Daubert. In fact, Daubert, as interpreted by "logician" judges, can amount to a super-Frye [4] test requiring universal acceptance of the reasoning in an expert's testimony. It also can, in effect, raise the burden of proof in science-dominated cases from the acceptable "more likely than not" standard to the nearly impossible burden of "beyond a reasonable doubt." Instead of relying solely on the second view, courts should combine the two. A synthesis of the two views of science can be achieved by recognizing that subjective assumptions and inferences can never be completely eliminated from expert testimony. As a result, expert testimony always amounts, in effect, to conditional statements. An expert's statements can be considered "reasonable"--or likely, or beyond a reasonable doubt--if, and only if, the assumptions and inferences made by the expert are considered reasonable, or likely, or beyond a reasonable doubt. This "Bayesian" approach [5] may offer a pragmatic synthesis of the tension in the Daubert decisions for science-dominated cases, provided that courts can find ways to judge fairly the reasonableness of underlying scientific assumptions. This article offers a number of proposals to meet this goal, along with other suggestions for reform of the Daubert review process. The gatekeeping function assigned to judges by the Daubert decision and strengthened by the subsequent Supreme Court cases Joiner and Kumho Tire, has been both vilified and praised in the legal literature. [6] This article supports the critics of Daubert, who see science as a contentious process, rather than a catalog of truths, and who argue that courts are now demanding more of individual scientists and engineers than is expected of them in their own research and practice. Moreover this article follows cues about science from world-renowned scientists, including Neils Bohr [7] and Norbert Wiener, [8] and influential philosophers of science, such as Thomas Kuhn, [9] all of whom have written about the limitations of individual scientists and the subjective elements inherent in the scientific
最高法院在Daubert诉Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc.[1]、通用电气公司诉Joiner案[2]和Kumho Tire诉Carmichael案[3]中包含了两种不一致的科学观点。在某些地方,最高法院认为科学是提炼理论的一个不完美的“过程”,而在其他地方,最高法院认为科学是通过“形式逻辑”推导出来的普遍知识。后一种观点长期以来不受哲学家和科学史家的青睐,但它符合当前的科学文化观,而且很可能被地区法院和上诉法院的法官所接受,即使他们没有接受有力的“教育”,或者直到高等法院认识到这两种观点需要综合成一个一致的整体。把科学解释为天衣无缝的逻辑,给在道伯特时代受到挑战的科学专家带来了不必要的负担。事实上,正如“逻辑学家”法官所解释的那样,道伯特可以相当于一个超级弗莱[4]测试,要求普遍接受专家证词中的推理。实际上,它还可以将科学主导案件的举证责任从可接受的“可能性大于不可能性”标准提高到几乎不可能承担的“排除合理怀疑”标准。法院不应仅仅依赖第二种观点,而应将两者结合起来。通过认识到主观假设和推断永远不能从专家证词中完全消除,可以实现两种科学观点的综合。因此,专家证词实际上总是条件陈述。专家的陈述可以被认为是“合理的”——或可能的,或超出合理怀疑——当且仅当专家所做的假设和推论被认为是合理的,或可能的,或超出合理怀疑。这种“贝叶斯”方法[5]可能提供了一种实用主义的综合,在科学主导的案件中,Daubert判决的紧张关系,前提是法院可以找到公平判断潜在科学假设合理性的方法。本文提供了一些实现这一目标的建议,以及对Daubert审查过程进行改革的其他建议。在“道伯特案”判决中赋予法官的“把关”功能,在随后的“乔伊纳案”和“锦湖轮胎案”中得到强化,在法律文献中受到了褒贬参半的评价。[6]这篇文章支持道伯特的批评者,他们认为科学是一个有争议的过程,而不是真理的目录,他们认为法院现在对个别科学家和工程师的要求比他们在自己的研究和实践中所期望的要多。此外,本文遵循了世界知名科学家的科学线索,包括尼尔斯·玻尔[7]和诺伯特·维纳[8],以及有影响力的科学哲学家,如托马斯·库恩[9],他们都写过关于科学家个人的局限性和科学过程中固有的主观因素的文章。与之竞争的那一派可能被认为是约翰·冯·诺伊曼(John von Neumann)的智力后裔,后者发明了数字计算机的基本方法论。[10]冯·诺伊曼认为科学是一组由逻辑推导出来的普遍事实,从而将科学知识置于一种形式的逻辑结构中,他认为这种结构是基本的和普遍的。[11]本文提出,法院对道伯特要求“无缝逻辑”的解释未能认识到,科学是一个不完美的过程,经常建立在假设和推论之上,而这些假设和推论根本无法通过道伯特似乎要求的形式逻辑方法来证明。第一部分概述了科学哲学的两个相互竞争的学派,并考察了这两个学派在诉讼中所扮演的角色。第二部分将倾向于遵循“形式逻辑”方法的道伯特与科学的“过程”观点区分开来,展示了道伯特方法中的缺陷,以及转向“过程”学派将使道伯特更容易被接受的方式。…
{"title":"Scientific Misconceptions Among Daubert Gatekeepers: The Need for Reform of Expert Review Procedures","authors":"J. Beyea, D. Berger","doi":"10.2307/1192316","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192316","url":null,"abstract":"JAN BEYEA [*] DANIEL BERGER [**] I INTRODUCTION The Supreme Court's opinions in Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc. [1], General Electric Company v. Joiner [2], and Kumho Tire v. Carmichael [3] contain two inconsistent views of science. In some places, the Court views science as an imperfect \"process\" for refining theories, whereas in other places, the Court views science as universal knowledge derived through \"formal logic.\" The latter view, long out of favor with philosophers and historians of science, comports with the current cultural vision of science and is likely to be adopted by district and appeals court judges, without vigorous \"education,\" or until such time as higher courts recognize that the two views need to be synthesized into a consistent whole. The interpretation of science as seamless logic puts an undue burden on scientific experts who are challenged under Daubert. In fact, Daubert, as interpreted by \"logician\" judges, can amount to a super-Frye [4] test requiring universal acceptance of the reasoning in an expert's testimony. It also can, in effect, raise the burden of proof in science-dominated cases from the acceptable \"more likely than not\" standard to the nearly impossible burden of \"beyond a reasonable doubt.\" Instead of relying solely on the second view, courts should combine the two. A synthesis of the two views of science can be achieved by recognizing that subjective assumptions and inferences can never be completely eliminated from expert testimony. As a result, expert testimony always amounts, in effect, to conditional statements. An expert's statements can be considered \"reasonable\"--or likely, or beyond a reasonable doubt--if, and only if, the assumptions and inferences made by the expert are considered reasonable, or likely, or beyond a reasonable doubt. This \"Bayesian\" approach [5] may offer a pragmatic synthesis of the tension in the Daubert decisions for science-dominated cases, provided that courts can find ways to judge fairly the reasonableness of underlying scientific assumptions. This article offers a number of proposals to meet this goal, along with other suggestions for reform of the Daubert review process. The gatekeeping function assigned to judges by the Daubert decision and strengthened by the subsequent Supreme Court cases Joiner and Kumho Tire, has been both vilified and praised in the legal literature. [6] This article supports the critics of Daubert, who see science as a contentious process, rather than a catalog of truths, and who argue that courts are now demanding more of individual scientists and engineers than is expected of them in their own research and practice. Moreover this article follows cues about science from world-renowned scientists, including Neils Bohr [7] and Norbert Wiener, [8] and influential philosophers of science, such as Thomas Kuhn, [9] all of whom have written about the limitations of individual scientists and the subjective elements inherent in the scientific","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"96 1","pages":"327-372"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81897918","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
Confronting the Future: Coping with Discovery of Electronic Material 面对未来:应对电子材料的发现
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-03-22 DOI: 10.2307/1192313
R. Marcus
The question for the present is whether this new development calls for a reconsideration of our rules or methods of discovery. Ideally, a procedural system should be designed so that it can cope with technological (and other) developments without a major overhaul, and perhaps without any revision. For instance, in 1999, the Supreme Court dealt with the thorny problem of interpreting a 1949 amendment to the removal statute in a case involving a “courtesy copy” of the complaint sent by fax. The court noted that Congress could not have foreseen the use of this technology when it amended the statute in 1949 but did not find that fact critical to interpreting the statute suitably for the era of faxed communications. The question whether the advent of the Internet generation calls for a reexamination of other procedural techniques and rules has divided scholars. Although the Supreme Court has noted that the Internet is “a unique and wholly new medium of worldwide human communication,” that does not mean that existing doctrines governing the limits of personal jurisdiction, for example, must be revised to cope with the new technology. Thus, some scholars argue that personal jurisdiction issues raised by Internet activity can be readily analyzed under the existing legal rules while others see the Internet as upsetting the apple cart of contemporary personal jurisdiction rules. This article addresses similar issues about the rules governing discovery. It first sketches the background of the current rules, for this is not the first time someone has argued that the discovery rules are no longer suitable for the challenges of contemporary discovery, particularly in complex cases. The article then examines the ways in which the discovery of electronically stored materials might present qualitatively different problems from those raised by the discovery of hard copy materials. Against that background, it surveys possible courses of action, by rule amendment or otherwise, and concludes that no clear solution has yet emerged. Indeed, as members of the generation that has seen the most vigorous challenge to unfettered discovery, we might conclude that there is really no generation gap because the types of discovery problems that arise with the new technology are analogous to those presented by hard copy discovery.
目前的问题是,这种新的发展是否需要重新考虑我们的发现规则或方法。理想情况下,程序系统的设计应使其能够应付技术(和其他)发展,而不需要进行重大改革,也许不需要任何修订。例如,1999年,最高法院处理了一个棘手的问题,即在一个涉及通过传真发送投诉的“礼貌副本”的案件中,解释1949年对搬迁法规的修正案。法院指出,国会在1949年修订该法规时不可能预见到这项技术的使用,但并不认为这一事实对解释该法规适用于传真通信时代至关重要。对于互联网时代的到来是否需要重新审视其他程序技术和规则的问题,学者们产生了分歧。尽管最高法院指出,互联网是“世界范围内人类交流的一种独特的、全新的媒介”,但这并不意味着,为了适应新技术的发展,必须修改诸如管辖属人管辖权的现有原则。因此,一些学者认为,互联网活动引发的属人管辖权问题可以在现有法律规则下轻易分析,而另一些学者则认为,互联网颠覆了当代属人管辖权规则。本文讨论了关于发现规则的类似问题。它首先概述了现行规则的背景,因为这不是第一次有人争论发现规则不再适合当代发现的挑战,特别是在复杂的案件中。然后,本文探讨了电子存储材料的发现可能与发现硬拷贝材料所提出的问题在质量上不同的方式。在这一背景下,委员会通过修订规则或其他方式调查了可能的行动方针,并得出结论认为尚未出现明确的解决办法。的确,作为目睹了无拘无束的发现所面临的最激烈挑战的一代人,我们可能会得出这样的结论:确实不存在代沟,因为新技术出现的发现问题的类型与硬拷贝发现所呈现的问题类似。
{"title":"Confronting the Future: Coping with Discovery of Electronic Material","authors":"R. Marcus","doi":"10.2307/1192313","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192313","url":null,"abstract":"The question for the present is whether this new development calls for a reconsideration of our rules or methods of discovery. Ideally, a procedural system should be designed so that it can cope with technological (and other) developments without a major overhaul, and perhaps without any revision. For instance, in 1999, the Supreme Court dealt with the thorny problem of interpreting a 1949 amendment to the removal statute in a case involving a “courtesy copy” of the complaint sent by fax. The court noted that Congress could not have foreseen the use of this technology when it amended the statute in 1949 but did not find that fact critical to interpreting the statute suitably for the era of faxed communications. The question whether the advent of the Internet generation calls for a reexamination of other procedural techniques and rules has divided scholars. Although the Supreme Court has noted that the Internet is “a unique and wholly new medium of worldwide human communication,” that does not mean that existing doctrines governing the limits of personal jurisdiction, for example, must be revised to cope with the new technology. Thus, some scholars argue that personal jurisdiction issues raised by Internet activity can be readily analyzed under the existing legal rules while others see the Internet as upsetting the apple cart of contemporary personal jurisdiction rules. This article addresses similar issues about the rules governing discovery. It first sketches the background of the current rules, for this is not the first time someone has argued that the discovery rules are no longer suitable for the challenges of contemporary discovery, particularly in complex cases. The article then examines the ways in which the discovery of electronically stored materials might present qualitatively different problems from those raised by the discovery of hard copy materials. Against that background, it surveys possible courses of action, by rule amendment or otherwise, and concludes that no clear solution has yet emerged. Indeed, as members of the generation that has seen the most vigorous challenge to unfettered discovery, we might conclude that there is really no generation gap because the types of discovery problems that arise with the new technology are analogous to those presented by hard copy discovery.","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"1 1","pages":"253-282"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82944756","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
A Modest Reform for Federal Procedural Rulemaking 联邦程序规则制定的适度改革
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-03-22 DOI: 10.2307/1192314
C. Tobias
CARL TOBIAS [*] The Judicial Conference of the United States Advisory Committee on Civil Rules (the "Advisory Committee"), which has primary responsibility to study the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure (the "Federal Rules") and to formulate recommendations for improvement, recently developed a thorough package of revisions to the Federal Rules that govern discovery. [1] During April 2000, the United States Supreme Court promulgated essentially intact the set of amendments that the Advisory Committee had proposed. [2] Those changes became effective in December 2000. [3] The rule revision entities commissioned discovery studies, developed proposals, and solicited and considered extensive public input on the recommended alterations to the Federal Rules. Despite concerted effort, the efficacy of the new amendments remains unclear, partly because federal district courts have not actually applied them. The revisions, this deficiency in the amendment process, and prospects for its remediation warrant analysis. The efforts to revise the rules commenced several years ago. In 1996, the Advisory Committee appointed a Discovery Subcommittee that it asked to explore the prospect of additional changes to the Federal Rules' discovery provisions, a number of which the Supreme Court had amended as recently as 1993. [4] The Discovery Subcommittee investigated the necessity of further altering the discovery provisions, in part by commissioning several assessments that two expert entities conducted. One of these institutions was the Federal Judicial. Center (the "FJC"), the principal research arm of the federal courts. [5] The second body was the Institute for Civil Justice of the RAND Corporation (the "ICJ"), which had recently completed a comprehensive evaluation of the procedures for reducing expense and delay adopted and enforced by the ninety-four federal district courts under the Civil Justice Reform Act (the "CJRA") of 1990. [6] The FJC and the ICJ collected and analyzed considerable empirical data on the application an d operation of the 1993 revisions of the Federal Rules. [7] The Advisory Committee substantially relied on those studies in formulating a group of proposed amendments to the discovery rules for the consideration of the Judicial Conference Committee on Rules of Practice and Procedure (the "Standing Committee"), [8] which reviews proposals developed by the advisory committees on appellate, bankruptcy, civil, criminal, and evidentiary rules. The Standing Committee instituted few modifications to the Advisory Committee draft and published proposed revisions on which it sought public input. [9] The Standing Committee then evaluated the public comments, minimally changed the suggested alterations, and, in 1999, compiled a final package of proposed amendments for the Judicial Conference, the policymaking arm of the federal courts. [10] The Conference made one modification in the set that the Advisory Committee tendered [11] and submitted the group to
卡尔·托拜厄斯(CARL TOBIAS)[*]美国民事诉讼规则咨询委员会(“咨询委员会”)司法会议的主要职责是研究《联邦民事诉讼规则》(“联邦规则”)并提出改进建议,该委员会最近对《联邦规则》中有关证据开示的内容进行了全面修订。2000年4月,美国最高法院颁布了基本完好无损的咨询委员会提出的一系列修正案。bbb这些变动于2000年12月生效。[3]规则修订实体委托进行发现研究,制定提案,并就联邦规则的建议修改征求并考虑了广泛的公众意见。尽管各方做出了一致努力,但新修正案的效力仍不明朗,部分原因是联邦地区法院并未实际应用这些修正案。此次修订,对修订过程中存在的不足,以及对其补救权证的展望进行了分析。修订规则的工作几年前就开始了。1996年,咨询委员会任命了一个证据开示小组委员会,要求该小组委员会探讨对《联邦规则》的证据开示条款进行进一步修改的可能性,最高法院最近在1993年修订了其中一些条款。[4]证据开示小组委员会调查了进一步修改证据开示条款的必要性,部分方式是委托两个专家实体进行了几项评估。其中一个机构是联邦司法机构。中心(“FJC”),联邦法院的主要研究机构。bbb第二个机构是兰德公司民事司法研究所(“国际法院”),该机构最近完成了对94个联邦地区法院根据1990年《民事司法改革法》(“民事司法改革法”)采用和执行的减少费用和延误的程序的全面评估。[10]司法委员会和国际法院收集和分析了关于1993年《联邦规则》修订案的适用和执行情况的大量经验数据。[7]咨询委员会在制定一组关于开示规则的拟议修正案以供司法会议惯例和程序规则委员会(“常设委员会”)审议时,在很大程度上依赖于这些研究报告。[8]审查上诉、破产、民事、刑事和证据规则咨询委员会提出的建议。常设委员会对咨询委员会草案作了几处修改,并公布了征求公众意见的修订建议。随后,常委会对公众意见进行了评估,对建议的修改进行了最低限度的修改,并于1999年为联邦法院的决策机构司法会议编制了最终的一揽子拟议修正案。[10]会议对咨询委员会提交[11]的一套文件作了一处修改,并将该小组提交最高法院;bbb法院于2000年4月公布了修订后的条例。这些修正案在几个重要方面改变了目前的发现制度。首先,2000年的修正案中有一项强制预先发现,或自动披露,要求当事人披露的信息比1993年的版本少。此外,《2000年修正案》的自动披露条款适用于全国;因此,它取消了1993年的条款,该条款授权94个联邦地区法院中的每一个都可以通过改变联邦规则中的限制或完全拒绝这些要求来选择退出。2000年修正案还缩小了诉讼当事人传统上能够获得的证据开示范围。多年来,当事人可以获得“与未决诉讼中涉及的主题事项相关”的任何信息。然而,新版本将发现的范围限制在“与索赔或辩护有关”的材料上,诉讼当事人只有在当事人提出动议,证明他们有权获得更广泛的发现理由后,才能获得与主题有关的信息。…
{"title":"A Modest Reform for Federal Procedural Rulemaking","authors":"C. Tobias","doi":"10.2307/1192314","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192314","url":null,"abstract":"CARL TOBIAS [*] The Judicial Conference of the United States Advisory Committee on Civil Rules (the \"Advisory Committee\"), which has primary responsibility to study the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure (the \"Federal Rules\") and to formulate recommendations for improvement, recently developed a thorough package of revisions to the Federal Rules that govern discovery. [1] During April 2000, the United States Supreme Court promulgated essentially intact the set of amendments that the Advisory Committee had proposed. [2] Those changes became effective in December 2000. [3] The rule revision entities commissioned discovery studies, developed proposals, and solicited and considered extensive public input on the recommended alterations to the Federal Rules. Despite concerted effort, the efficacy of the new amendments remains unclear, partly because federal district courts have not actually applied them. The revisions, this deficiency in the amendment process, and prospects for its remediation warrant analysis. The efforts to revise the rules commenced several years ago. In 1996, the Advisory Committee appointed a Discovery Subcommittee that it asked to explore the prospect of additional changes to the Federal Rules' discovery provisions, a number of which the Supreme Court had amended as recently as 1993. [4] The Discovery Subcommittee investigated the necessity of further altering the discovery provisions, in part by commissioning several assessments that two expert entities conducted. One of these institutions was the Federal Judicial. Center (the \"FJC\"), the principal research arm of the federal courts. [5] The second body was the Institute for Civil Justice of the RAND Corporation (the \"ICJ\"), which had recently completed a comprehensive evaluation of the procedures for reducing expense and delay adopted and enforced by the ninety-four federal district courts under the Civil Justice Reform Act (the \"CJRA\") of 1990. [6] The FJC and the ICJ collected and analyzed considerable empirical data on the application an d operation of the 1993 revisions of the Federal Rules. [7] The Advisory Committee substantially relied on those studies in formulating a group of proposed amendments to the discovery rules for the consideration of the Judicial Conference Committee on Rules of Practice and Procedure (the \"Standing Committee\"), [8] which reviews proposals developed by the advisory committees on appellate, bankruptcy, civil, criminal, and evidentiary rules. The Standing Committee instituted few modifications to the Advisory Committee draft and published proposed revisions on which it sought public input. [9] The Standing Committee then evaluated the public comments, minimally changed the suggested alterations, and, in 1999, compiled a final package of proposed amendments for the Judicial Conference, the policymaking arm of the federal courts. [10] The Conference made one modification in the set that the Advisory Committee tendered [11] and submitted the group to","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"128 2","pages":"283-287"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/1192314","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72486325","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Pleading Securities Fraud 抗辩证券欺诈
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-03-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.245769
E. Weiss
In the roughly five years since the Private Securities Litigation Reform Act of 1995 became law, courts and commentators have devoted considerable attention to two questions relating to the requirement, set forth in section 21D(b)(2), that a complaint alleging securities fraud must "state with particularity facts giving rise to a strong inference that the defendant acted with the required state of mind." Those questions concern: (1) What constitutes "the required state of mind" in suits under section 10(b) and Rule 10b-5? And (2) Are facts indicating a defendant had a motive and the opportunity to engage in fraud, standing alone, sufficient to create a strong inference that that defendant acted with the required state of mind? Courts and commentators have devoted far less attention to what I call the Basis Requirement - the portion of section 21D(b)(1) that requires a plaintiff to specifying not only "each statement alleged to have been misleading" and "the reason or reasons why the statement is misleading," but also, with respect to every allegation made on information and belief, "all facts on which that belief is formed." This article argues that issues relating to the Basis Requirement in the long run will prove to be far more significant than the issues relating to motive, opportunity and degrees of recklessness that have preoccupied courts and commentators to date. A threshold question is the amount and quality of corroborating information a plaintiff must include in her complaint. The article explains why, in order to implement Congress' goal of discouraging the filing and prosecution of speculative claims of securities fraud, courts must adopt an interpretation of the Basis Requirement similar to that adopted by the Ninth and First Circuits in In re Silicon Graphics Securities Litigation and Greebel v. FTP Software, respectively. Only by doing so will courts prevent plaintiffs from continuing to make speculative allegations of fraud and then relying on the discovery process to seek evidence to support their claims. The article next highlights two additional holdings in Greebel: (1) A court must consider the nature of the corroborating information plaintiff has provided when evaluating whether plaintiff has pled facts sufficient to create a strong inference of scienter. (2) The Reform Act effectively rejects the notice pleading philosophy reflected in Conley v. Gibson by requiring plaintiffs in securities fraud actions to plead facts that give rise to a strong, rather than merely a reasonable, inference of scienter. Using the analytic framework created by Greebel and Silicon Graphics, the article then considers two cases currently pending in courts in the Second and Third Circuits. The first is Novak v. Kasaks, in which the Second Circuit reversed and remanded a district court decision granting a motion to dismiss. The article points out that the Second Circuit's opinion is rather muddled, but can be reconciled with Silicon Graphics and Gr
自1995年《私人证券诉讼改革法案》(Private Securities Litigation Reform Act of 1995)成为法律以来的大约5年时间里,法院和评论员对与第21D(b)(2)条规定的要求有关的两个问题给予了相当大的关注,即指控证券欺诈的投诉必须“以具体事实陈述,从而有力地推断被告的行为符合所要求的精神状态”。这些问题涉及:(1)根据第10(b)条和规则10b-5,什么构成诉讼中“所需的精神状态”?(2)表明被告有动机和机会进行欺诈的事实是否足以形成一个强有力的推论,即被告的行为具有所需的精神状态?法院和评论员很少关注我所说的基础要求——第21D(b)(1)条的一部分,它要求原告不仅要指定“每一个被指控具有误导性的陈述”和“该陈述具有误导性的原因或原因”,而且,对于每一个关于信息和信念的指控,“形成该信念的所有事实”。本文认为,从长远来看,与基础要求有关的问题将被证明比迄今为止法院和评论员所关注的与动机、机会和鲁莽程度有关的问题要重要得多。一个门槛问题是原告在其申诉中必须包括的确证信息的数量和质量。这篇文章解释了为什么为了实现国会的目标,即阻止证券欺诈的投机性索赔的提交和起诉,法院必须采用类似于第九和第一巡回法院在硅图形证券诉讼和格林贝尔诉FTP软件案中所采用的基础要求的解释。只有这样,法院才能防止原告继续提出欺诈的投机性指控,然后依靠发现程序寻求证据来支持他们的主张。这篇文章接下来强调了grebel案的两个额外主张:(1)法院在评估原告是否提供了足够的事实以形成强有力的科学推断时,必须考虑原告提供的佐证信息的性质。(2)《改革法》实际上拒绝了康利诉吉布森案中反映的通知辩护哲学,要求证券欺诈诉讼中的原告就能够产生强有力而不仅仅是合理的科学推理的事实进行辩护。使用由grebel和Silicon Graphics创建的分析框架,文章随后考虑了目前在第二和第三巡回法院悬而未决的两个案件。第一起是诺瓦克诉卡萨克案,在该案中,第二巡回法院推翻并发回了地方法院批准驳回动议的判决。文章指出,第二巡回法院的意见相当混乱,但可以与Silicon Graphics和Greebel的意见保持一致。文章还指出,第二巡回法院对诺瓦克案的解释是否如此,将为下级联邦法院在解释《改革法案》的抗辩要求时采用统一的方法还是分散的方法提供一个重要的指示。(文章还指出,在这篇文章完成后,诺瓦克收到了一份调卷令的申请。)第二个案例是In - re Cell Pathways, Inc。证券诉讼,被告向第三巡回上诉法院请求法院颁令撤销一项明显不正确的地方法院判决,驳回他们的驳回动议。正如诺瓦克案一样,第三巡回法院如何处理这一请愿书,将为下级联邦法院将采取何种方式来解释和执行《改革法案》的抗辩要求提供一个重要的指示。文章最后讨论了在证券集体诉讼中对原告施加这些严格的辩护要求的一些潜在的政策后果。文章指出,评估《改革法案》的影响在很大程度上是一个经验问题,而且,由于解释《改革法案》抗辩要求的第一批上诉判决是在相对较近的时间发布的,而且几个巡回法院的法律格局仍不明朗,关于该法案的抗辩要求——假设它们被统一解释——是否使证券欺诈的受害者难以获得适当救济,还需要几年的时间才能获得足够的数据来支持任何知情的结论。
{"title":"Pleading Securities Fraud","authors":"E. Weiss","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.245769","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.245769","url":null,"abstract":"In the roughly five years since the Private Securities Litigation Reform Act of 1995 became law, courts and commentators have devoted considerable attention to two questions relating to the requirement, set forth in section 21D(b)(2), that a complaint alleging securities fraud must \"state with particularity facts giving rise to a strong inference that the defendant acted with the required state of mind.\" Those questions concern: (1) What constitutes \"the required state of mind\" in suits under section 10(b) and Rule 10b-5? And (2) Are facts indicating a defendant had a motive and the opportunity to engage in fraud, standing alone, sufficient to create a strong inference that that defendant acted with the required state of mind? Courts and commentators have devoted far less attention to what I call the Basis Requirement - the portion of section 21D(b)(1) that requires a plaintiff to specifying not only \"each statement alleged to have been misleading\" and \"the reason or reasons why the statement is misleading,\" but also, with respect to every allegation made on information and belief, \"all facts on which that belief is formed.\" This article argues that issues relating to the Basis Requirement in the long run will prove to be far more significant than the issues relating to motive, opportunity and degrees of recklessness that have preoccupied courts and commentators to date. A threshold question is the amount and quality of corroborating information a plaintiff must include in her complaint. The article explains why, in order to implement Congress' goal of discouraging the filing and prosecution of speculative claims of securities fraud, courts must adopt an interpretation of the Basis Requirement similar to that adopted by the Ninth and First Circuits in In re Silicon Graphics Securities Litigation and Greebel v. FTP Software, respectively. Only by doing so will courts prevent plaintiffs from continuing to make speculative allegations of fraud and then relying on the discovery process to seek evidence to support their claims. The article next highlights two additional holdings in Greebel: (1) A court must consider the nature of the corroborating information plaintiff has provided when evaluating whether plaintiff has pled facts sufficient to create a strong inference of scienter. (2) The Reform Act effectively rejects the notice pleading philosophy reflected in Conley v. Gibson by requiring plaintiffs in securities fraud actions to plead facts that give rise to a strong, rather than merely a reasonable, inference of scienter. Using the analytic framework created by Greebel and Silicon Graphics, the article then considers two cases currently pending in courts in the Second and Third Circuits. The first is Novak v. Kasaks, in which the Second Circuit reversed and remanded a district court decision granting a motion to dismiss. The article points out that the Second Circuit's opinion is rather muddled, but can be reconciled with Silicon Graphics and Gr","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"28 1","pages":"5-52"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80160491","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Ulysses Tied to the Generic Whipping Post: The Continuing Odyssey of Discovery “Reform” 尤利西斯被绑在普通的鞭笞柱上:发现“改革”的持续奥德赛
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-03-22 DOI: 10.2307/1192312
J. Stempel
JEFFREY W. STEMPEL [*] I INTRODUCTION One need not be a charter member of the Critical Legal Studies Movement ("CLS") to see a few fundamental contradictions in litigation practice in the United States. [1] A prominent philosophical tenet of the CLS movement is that law and society are gripped by a "fundamental contradiction" and simultaneously seek to embrace contradictory objectives. [2] Civil litigation, particularly discovery, is no exception: New amendments to the discovery rules are the latest example of this contradiction. [3] Although the new changes are not drastic, they continue the post-1976 pattern of making discovery the convenient scapegoat for generalized complaints about the dispute resolution system. [4] One Change--the narrowing of the scope of discovery--could have a substantial adverse impact. Its presence on the roster of new amendments demonstrates the degree to which discovery has been blamed unfairly for society's--and the legal profession's--general disgust with litigation. At the same time, the discovery process is never seriously rehabilitated but rather only adjusted in ways that fail to address its fundamental (but manageable) problems in the context of civil litigation. [5] Simultaneously, a litigant's ability to obtain information significantly shrinks, favoring disputants who would provide less information. For the most part, this group is comprised of defendants, particularly products liability and statutory rights defendants. [6] Rulemaking is viewed on the one hand as an apolitical procedure and on the other hand as a "disguised outcry for tort reform." [7] Historically, trial judges in the United States have been vested with great discretion over almost all aspects of litigation--in particular, discovery. [8] Since the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure were enacted in 1938, the default has been broad-based "relevant-to-the-subject-matter" discoverability, but judges have always had ample discretion to alter this rule. For much of the long-running debate about discovery, the prevailing view seemed to be that the wise discretion of judges would save us from the potential evils and abuses of discovery (and other litigation evils). [9] Judges were viewed as Solomon-like, able to resolve discovery disputes by contextual decisionmaking on a case-by-case basis. [10] By the 1990s, however, this school of thought seemed to have given way to the view that judges needed to be saved from their own discretion, which was not used frequently enough to limit discovery, or at least subject to a more restrictive default rule. [11] This prong of the "trend," if one can call it th at, encompasses not only civil discovery, but also pleadings and motion papers, as well as criminal sentencing. Another--perhaps equally strong--modern trend continues to accord trial judges substantial discretion. This second trend continues the significant departure from default rules and reins in only highly idiosyncratic judicial discretion expressed
[*]一个人不需要成为批判性法律研究运动(CLS)的创始成员,就能看到美国诉讼实践中的一些基本矛盾。[1] CLS运动的一个突出的哲学原则是,法律和社会被一种“基本矛盾”所控制,同时寻求拥抱相互矛盾的目标。[2]民事诉讼,尤其是证据开示,也不例外:对证据开示规则的新修订是这种矛盾的最新例子。[3]虽然新的变化并不剧烈,但它们延续了1976年后的模式,即把发现作为对争端解决制度普遍不满的方便替罪羊。[4]一个变化——发现范围的缩小——可能会产生重大的不利影响。它出现在新修正案的名单上,表明人们在多大程度上把社会——以及法律界——对诉讼的普遍厌恶归咎于证据开示。与此同时,在民事诉讼的背景下,证据开示程序从未得到认真的恢复,而只是以无法解决其根本(但可管理的)问题的方式进行调整。[5]与此同时,诉讼当事人获取信息的能力大大减少,这有利于提供较少信息的当事人。在大多数情况下,这一群体由被告组成,特别是产品责任和法定权利被告。[6]规则制定一方面被视为一种非政治性的程序,另一方面被视为“变相地呼吁侵权法改革”。[7]从历史上看,美国的审判法官在诉讼的几乎所有方面都被赋予了很大的自由裁量权——特别是在证据开示方面。[8]自《联邦民事诉讼规则》于1938年颁布以来,“与案件主题相关”的可发现性一直是普遍存在的,但法官总是有足够的自由裁量权来改变这一规则。在关于证据开证的长期争论中,主流的观点似乎是,法官明智的裁量权将使我们免于证据开证的潜在弊端和滥用(以及其他诉讼弊端)。[9]法官被视为所罗门一样的人,能够在个案的基础上通过上下文决策来解决证据发现纠纷。[10]然而,到了20世纪90年代,这一思想学派似乎让位给了另一种观点,即法官需要免于自己的自由裁量权,而这种自由裁量权的使用不够频繁,不足以限制证据开示,或者至少受到更严格的默认规则的约束。[11]〔11〕这一“趋势”——如果可以称之为“趋势”的话——不仅包括民事证据开示,还包括诉状和动议文件,以及刑事判决。另一个——或许同样强大的——现代趋势继续赋予初审法官很大的自由裁量权。这第二种趋势延续了对默认规则的重大背离,只控制通过常设命令和审中裁决表达的高度特殊的司法自由裁量权。[12]〔12〕1993年的《民事规则修正案》是这种限制或至少改变司法自由裁量权的行动的最有力证据,也是这一行动的最新篇章。但与此同时,1993年的修正案也表明,美国法律在规则与自由裁量权的问题上存在持续的不一致。1993年的修正案建立了一种公开制度,以代替最初的发现,希望法官可以免除他们的一些发现管理职责。[13]这在一定程度上减少了司法部门行使自由裁量权的机会。然而,与此同时,个别地区法院有权选择不参与披露制度,个别法院保留了相当大的自由裁量权,即使法官没有这样做。[14]同样,对审讯(每一方二十五次)和证词(每一方十次)也规定了推定限度。...
{"title":"Ulysses Tied to the Generic Whipping Post: The Continuing Odyssey of Discovery “Reform”","authors":"J. Stempel","doi":"10.2307/1192312","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192312","url":null,"abstract":"JEFFREY W. STEMPEL [*] I INTRODUCTION One need not be a charter member of the Critical Legal Studies Movement (\"CLS\") to see a few fundamental contradictions in litigation practice in the United States. [1] A prominent philosophical tenet of the CLS movement is that law and society are gripped by a \"fundamental contradiction\" and simultaneously seek to embrace contradictory objectives. [2] Civil litigation, particularly discovery, is no exception: New amendments to the discovery rules are the latest example of this contradiction. [3] Although the new changes are not drastic, they continue the post-1976 pattern of making discovery the convenient scapegoat for generalized complaints about the dispute resolution system. [4] One Change--the narrowing of the scope of discovery--could have a substantial adverse impact. Its presence on the roster of new amendments demonstrates the degree to which discovery has been blamed unfairly for society's--and the legal profession's--general disgust with litigation. At the same time, the discovery process is never seriously rehabilitated but rather only adjusted in ways that fail to address its fundamental (but manageable) problems in the context of civil litigation. [5] Simultaneously, a litigant's ability to obtain information significantly shrinks, favoring disputants who would provide less information. For the most part, this group is comprised of defendants, particularly products liability and statutory rights defendants. [6] Rulemaking is viewed on the one hand as an apolitical procedure and on the other hand as a \"disguised outcry for tort reform.\" [7] Historically, trial judges in the United States have been vested with great discretion over almost all aspects of litigation--in particular, discovery. [8] Since the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure were enacted in 1938, the default has been broad-based \"relevant-to-the-subject-matter\" discoverability, but judges have always had ample discretion to alter this rule. For much of the long-running debate about discovery, the prevailing view seemed to be that the wise discretion of judges would save us from the potential evils and abuses of discovery (and other litigation evils). [9] Judges were viewed as Solomon-like, able to resolve discovery disputes by contextual decisionmaking on a case-by-case basis. [10] By the 1990s, however, this school of thought seemed to have given way to the view that judges needed to be saved from their own discretion, which was not used frequently enough to limit discovery, or at least subject to a more restrictive default rule. [11] This prong of the \"trend,\" if one can call it th at, encompasses not only civil discovery, but also pleadings and motion papers, as well as criminal sentencing. Another--perhaps equally strong--modern trend continues to accord trial judges substantial discretion. This second trend continues the significant departure from default rules and reins in only highly idiosyncratic judicial discretion expressed ","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"60 1","pages":"197-252"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82604447","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Kumho and How We Know 锦湖和我们是怎么知道的
Q2 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-03-22 DOI: 10.2307/1192317
J. Sanders
JOSEPH SANDERS [*] I INTRODUCTION In the summer of 1999, the United States Supreme Court issued the last in a trilogy of 1990s cases dealing with the question of the admissibility of expert testimony in federal courts. [1] In Kumho Tire Co. v. Carmichael, [2] the Court was asked to decide if the judicial gatekeeping role it set forth in the first of these three cases, Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, [3] applied only to "scientific" knowledge or to all expert testimony. The court concluded that all expert testimony must be both relevant and reliable before it can be admitted, but that the specific factors set forth in Daubert to judge the reliability of scientific evidence may be supplemented and perhaps replaced by other factors when expert testimony is based on "technical" or "other specialized" knowledge. [4] The opinion explicitly recognized that not all expert testimony can be judged by a single standard because not all experts know things in exactly the same way. [5] This point had been colorfully made five years earlier in the Sixth Circuit's opinion in Berry v. City of Detroit. [6] In Berry, while wrestling with the admissibility of the expert testimony of a "sociologist cum sheriff" [7] as to whether the disciplinary practices of the Detroit police department demonstrated a policy of deliberate indifference to the rights of the citizenry, thus giving rise to municipal liability under 42 U.S.C. [sections] 1983, the Sixth Circuit made the following comparison between scientific and nonscientific expert testimony: The distinction between scientific and non-scientific expert testimony is a critical one. By way of illustration, if one wanted to explain to a jury how a bumblebee is able to fly, an aeronautical engineer might be a helpful witness. Since flight principles have some universality, the expert could apply general principles to the case of the bumblebee. Conceivably, even if he had never seen a bumblebee, he still would be qualified to testify, as long as he was familiar with its component parts. On the other hand, if one wanted to prove that bumblebees always take off into the wind, a beekeeper with no scientific training at all would be an acceptable expert witness if a proper foundation were laid for his conclusions. The foundation would not relate to his formal training, but to his firsthand observations. In other words, the beekeeper does not know any more about flight principles than the jurors, but he has seen a lot more bumblebees than they have. [8] How do aeronautical engineers and beekeepers know what they know? How does their knowledge differ and how is it the same? The insight of the Berry opinion is that a satisfactory answer to the legal question of admissibility is in part contingent upon our understanding of the nature of expert knowledge. But this alone is not enough. Admissibility standards are also influenced by the organization of the legal system itself. In this article, I attempt to shed some light on di
1999年夏天,美国最高法院发布了20世纪90年代关于联邦法院专家证词可采性问题的三部曲中的最后一部。[1]在Kumho Tire Co. v. Carmichael一案中,[2]法院被要求决定它在这三个案件中的第一个案件(道伯特诉梅雷尔陶氏制药公司案)[3]中提出的司法守门人的角色是否只适用于“科学”知识,还是适用于所有专家证词。法院的结论是,所有的专家证词必须既相关又可靠,才能被接受,但是,当专家证词基于“技术”或“其他专业”知识时,Daubert案中规定的判断科学证据可靠性的具体因素可以被补充或可能被其他因素所取代。[4]该意见明确承认,并非所有专家的证词都可以用单一标准来判断,因为并非所有专家都以完全相同的方式了解事情。[5]五年前,在第六巡回法院审理的贝里诉底特律市案中,这一观点已经得到了生动的阐述。[6]在贝里一案中,在与“社会学家兼治安官”的专家证词的可采性作斗争时[7],底特律警察局的纪律处分是否表明了一种故意漠视公民权利的政策,从而导致了《美国法典》1983年第42条规定的市政责任,第六巡回法院对科学和非科学专家证词进行了以下比较:区分科学和非科学的专家证词是一个关键问题。举例来说,如果有人想向陪审团解释大黄蜂是如何飞行的,航空工程师可能是一个有用的证人。由于飞行原则具有一定的普遍性,专家可以将一般原则应用于大黄蜂的情况。可以想象,即使他从未见过大黄蜂,只要他熟悉它的组成部分,他仍然有资格作证。另一方面,如果有人想证明大黄蜂总是迎风而飞,一个根本没有受过科学训练的养蜂人,如果他的结论有适当的基础,也可以成为一个可以接受的专家证人。这个基础与他的正式训练无关,而是与他的第一手观察有关。换句话说,养蜂人对飞行原理的了解并不比陪审员多,但他见过的大黄蜂比陪审员多得多。[8]航空工程师和养蜂人是怎么知道他们所知道的呢?他们的知识有什么不同,又有什么相同?贝里一案的见解是,对可采性这一法律问题的满意答案部分取决于我们对专家知识本质的理解。但仅靠这一点是不够的。可采性标准也受到法律体系本身组织的影响。在这篇文章中,我试图阐明专家(和非专家)了解事物的不同方式,然后就这应该如何影响专家证词可采性的法律评估提出一些想法。[9]在第二部分中,我回顾了导致锦湖案的法律发展。我特别强调Frye[10]和Daubert[11]测试中反映的可采理性的替代方法,以及锦湖决定将非科学证据纳入Daubert的保护罩。[12]第三部分解决了两个问题:关于科学知识,法律的隐含认识论是什么?科学知识与其他形式的认识有何不同?我认为,虽然各个知识领域之间可能存在差异,比如依赖个人“经验”作为判断的基础,以及各个领域将自己与政治、经济和社会压力隔离开来的能力,但学科内部的差异往往与学科之间的差异一样大。…
{"title":"Kumho and How We Know","authors":"J. Sanders","doi":"10.2307/1192317","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192317","url":null,"abstract":"JOSEPH SANDERS [*] I INTRODUCTION In the summer of 1999, the United States Supreme Court issued the last in a trilogy of 1990s cases dealing with the question of the admissibility of expert testimony in federal courts. [1] In Kumho Tire Co. v. Carmichael, [2] the Court was asked to decide if the judicial gatekeeping role it set forth in the first of these three cases, Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, [3] applied only to \"scientific\" knowledge or to all expert testimony. The court concluded that all expert testimony must be both relevant and reliable before it can be admitted, but that the specific factors set forth in Daubert to judge the reliability of scientific evidence may be supplemented and perhaps replaced by other factors when expert testimony is based on \"technical\" or \"other specialized\" knowledge. [4] The opinion explicitly recognized that not all expert testimony can be judged by a single standard because not all experts know things in exactly the same way. [5] This point had been colorfully made five years earlier in the Sixth Circuit's opinion in Berry v. City of Detroit. [6] In Berry, while wrestling with the admissibility of the expert testimony of a \"sociologist cum sheriff\" [7] as to whether the disciplinary practices of the Detroit police department demonstrated a policy of deliberate indifference to the rights of the citizenry, thus giving rise to municipal liability under 42 U.S.C. [sections] 1983, the Sixth Circuit made the following comparison between scientific and nonscientific expert testimony: The distinction between scientific and non-scientific expert testimony is a critical one. By way of illustration, if one wanted to explain to a jury how a bumblebee is able to fly, an aeronautical engineer might be a helpful witness. Since flight principles have some universality, the expert could apply general principles to the case of the bumblebee. Conceivably, even if he had never seen a bumblebee, he still would be qualified to testify, as long as he was familiar with its component parts. On the other hand, if one wanted to prove that bumblebees always take off into the wind, a beekeeper with no scientific training at all would be an acceptable expert witness if a proper foundation were laid for his conclusions. The foundation would not relate to his formal training, but to his firsthand observations. In other words, the beekeeper does not know any more about flight principles than the jurors, but he has seen a lot more bumblebees than they have. [8] How do aeronautical engineers and beekeepers know what they know? How does their knowledge differ and how is it the same? The insight of the Berry opinion is that a satisfactory answer to the legal question of admissibility is in part contingent upon our understanding of the nature of expert knowledge. But this alone is not enough. Admissibility standards are also influenced by the organization of the legal system itself. In this article, I attempt to shed some light on di","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"14 1","pages":"373-416"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2001-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78913790","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 11
期刊
Law and Contemporary Problems
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1