首页 > 最新文献

Quaestiones Disputatae最新文献

英文 中文
The Splendor of Truth in Fides et Ratio 《信仰与比例》中真理的光辉
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2019-03-08 DOI: 10.5840/QD20189115
E. Echeverria
Abstract:The lack of what may be termed "metaphysical authority" in [e.g., liberation theology, narrative theology, and hermeneutical theology] makes them ill equipped to render the theological totality of Catholic Christianity, which needs to speak about being as well as meaning and about eternity as well as time. . . . They must find ways of making space for other kinds of theological discourse, and above all, for those which, in their cherishing of ontology, enable the expression of Catholic doctrine as a description of reality—in its two poles, finite and infinite, and the relation between them. At the same time, such other kinds of theology, of which Thomism may stand as the paradigm by presenting human intelligence as above all the capacity for intake of the real, highlight in an irreplaceable fashion the Church's fundamental intuition about truth: namely, that it is not first and foremost an action to be done (cf. liberation theology) or a story to be told (cf. narrative theology) or a text to be interpreted (cf. hermeneutical theology), though it may indeed also be all of these. Primordially, truth is an encounter with what is not humanity's work: the deed of God in creation and salvation.
摘要:在(如解放神学、叙事神学和诠释神学)中缺乏所谓的“形而上学权威”,使他们没有能力呈现天主教基督教的神学整体性,这需要谈论存在和意义,关于永恒和时间. . . .他们必须设法为其他的神学话语,特别是为那些因为重视本体论而能把天主教教义表述为对现实的描述的神学话语,即有限和无限的两极,以及它们之间的关系的神学话语,腾出空间。同时,这样其他的神学,哲学学说可能站的范例,展示人类智慧的摄取能力最重要的是真实的,以不可替代的方式强调教会的基本直觉真理:也就是说,首先,它不是一个动作要做(参见解放神学)或者一个故事被告知(参看叙事神学)或一个文本解读(参见解释学的神学),尽管它可能也确实是所有这些。首先,真理是与非人类工作的相遇:天主在创造和救恩中的作为。
{"title":"The Splendor of Truth in Fides et Ratio","authors":"E. Echeverria","doi":"10.5840/QD20189115","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD20189115","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:The lack of what may be termed \"metaphysical authority\" in [e.g., liberation theology, narrative theology, and hermeneutical theology] makes them ill equipped to render the theological totality of Catholic Christianity, which needs to speak about being as well as meaning and about eternity as well as time. . . . They must find ways of making space for other kinds of theological discourse, and above all, for those which, in their cherishing of ontology, enable the expression of Catholic doctrine as a description of reality—in its two poles, finite and infinite, and the relation between them. At the same time, such other kinds of theology, of which Thomism may stand as the paradigm by presenting human intelligence as above all the capacity for intake of the real, highlight in an irreplaceable fashion the Church's fundamental intuition about truth: namely, that it is not first and foremost an action to be done (cf. liberation theology) or a story to be told (cf. narrative theology) or a text to be interpreted (cf. hermeneutical theology), though it may indeed also be all of these. Primordially, truth is an encounter with what is not humanity's work: the deed of God in creation and salvation.","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-03-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79064536","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Myth of a Pure Virtue Epistemology 纯粹美德认识论的神话
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-09-27 DOI: 10.5840/QD20188211
Joshue Orozco
G. E. M. Anscombe’s trenchant critique of consequentialist and deontological moral theories helped bring virtues back into moral philosophy.1 Ethicists committed to consequentialist or deontological frameworks gave virtues renewed attention by developing theories of moral virtue that assimilated virtue into their prior and more fundamental moral commitments.2 Others, rather than assimilating moral virtue, developed a pure virtue ethic that gives virtue and related aretaic notions of excellence and admirability a fundamental role in one’s moral framework. Some pure virtue ethicists address the traditional problems and questions (e.g., giving an account of right action) asked by consequentialists and deontologists, some argue that there is something flawed or importantly deficient with these traditional projects and questions addressed by the other moral frameworks. Virtue epistemology has experienced similar developments since Ernest Sosa’s “The Raft and the Pyramid.”3 Some virtue epistemologists offer theories of intellectual virtue that assimilate virtue into some more fundamental epistemic framework (e.g., reliabilism or evidentialism). Some, however, argue for a pure virtue epistemology that takes intellectual virtues as personally excellent or admirable intellectual character traits analogous to Aristotelian moral virtues, which purportedly play a fundamental role in one’s epistemic framework. As in the moral realm, some pure virtueepistemic
g.e.m.安斯库姆对结果主义和义务论道德理论的尖锐批判有助于将美德带回道德哲学致力于结果主义或义务论框架的伦理学家通过发展道德美德理论,将美德融入到他们先前的和更基本的道德承诺中,从而重新关注美德其他人,而不是吸收道德美德,发展了一种纯粹的道德伦理,使美德和相关的优秀和令人钦佩的概念在一个人的道德框架中发挥了基本作用。一些纯美德伦理学家解决了结果主义者和义务论者提出的传统问题和问题(例如,给出正确行为的解释),一些人认为,其他道德框架所解决的这些传统项目和问题存在缺陷或严重缺陷。自欧内斯特·索萨的《木筏与金字塔》以来,美德认识论经历了类似的发展。一些美德认识论提供了智力美德的理论,将美德同化到一些更基本的认识论框架中(例如,可靠性或证据主义)。然而,有些人主张纯美德认识论,认为智力美德是个人优秀或令人钦佩的智力特征,类似于亚里士多德的道德美德,据称在一个人的认识论框架中起着基本作用。就像在道德领域,一些纯粹的虚拟认知
{"title":"The Myth of a Pure Virtue Epistemology","authors":"Joshue Orozco","doi":"10.5840/QD20188211","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD20188211","url":null,"abstract":"G. E. M. Anscombe’s trenchant critique of consequentialist and deontological moral theories helped bring virtues back into moral philosophy.1 Ethicists committed to consequentialist or deontological frameworks gave virtues renewed attention by developing theories of moral virtue that assimilated virtue into their prior and more fundamental moral commitments.2 Others, rather than assimilating moral virtue, developed a pure virtue ethic that gives virtue and related aretaic notions of excellence and admirability a fundamental role in one’s moral framework. Some pure virtue ethicists address the traditional problems and questions (e.g., giving an account of right action) asked by consequentialists and deontologists, some argue that there is something flawed or importantly deficient with these traditional projects and questions addressed by the other moral frameworks. Virtue epistemology has experienced similar developments since Ernest Sosa’s “The Raft and the Pyramid.”3 Some virtue epistemologists offer theories of intellectual virtue that assimilate virtue into some more fundamental epistemic framework (e.g., reliabilism or evidentialism). Some, however, argue for a pure virtue epistemology that takes intellectual virtues as personally excellent or admirable intellectual character traits analogous to Aristotelian moral virtues, which purportedly play a fundamental role in one’s epistemic framework. As in the moral realm, some pure virtueepistemic","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-09-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79230635","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The World, the Deceiver, and The Face in the Frost 世界,骗子,冰霜中的脸
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-09-27 DOI: 10.5840/QD2018827
L. McGrew
In an appendix to The Foundations of Knowledge, Timothy McGrew provides the outline of a solution to the problem of the external world.1 McGrew argues that the probability of the existence of a deceiver who makes it appear that we live in a real external world must be lower than the probability of a real external world itself because the ontological commitments of the latter hypothesis will always necessarily be greater than those of the former. In the latter hypothesis, we posit a mental state of the deceiver as a cause of each of the apparently real things that seem to exist in the external world, but the deceiver himself also exists as an entity who is not merely the sum of all of these mental states. McGrew argues, further, that any time we conditionalize on some particular mental state of our own that we normally take to be caused by real objects in the external world, the gap in probability between realism and the deceiver hypothesis grows larger. He bases this argument on the probabilistic fact that if one theory is strictly simpler than some other theory, the confirmation a given piece of evidence affords to the simpler theory is always greater than the confirmation it affords to the more complex theory— the difference between the old probability of the simpler theory and its new probability is always greater than the comparable difference between the old and new probabilities of the more complex theory.2 McGrew’s argument thus shows, if we take it to be successful, that the prior probability of a deceiver scenario is lower than the prior probability of realism and also that, as we gradually conditionalize on more and more everyday evidence, the gap in probability between the two will continue to grow. This set of conclusions would seem to mean (since we have a great deal of sensory evidence that we normally
在《知识的基础》的附录中,蒂莫西·麦克格鲁提供了一个解决外部世界问题的大纲麦克格鲁认为存在一个让我们看起来生活在真实外部世界的骗子的概率一定低于真实外部世界本身存在的概率因为后一种假设的本体论承诺总是必然大于前一种假设的本体论承诺。在后一种假设中,我们假定欺诈者的心理状态是外部世界中似乎存在的每一件明显真实事物的原因,但欺诈者本身也作为一个实体存在,他不仅仅是所有这些心理状态的总和。麦克格鲁进一步指出,每当我们把自己的某种心理状态作为条件,而我们通常认为这种心理状态是由外部世界的真实物体引起的时候,现实主义和欺骗假设之间的概率差距就会变得更大。他的论点基于一个概率论的事实,即如果一个理论严格地比另一个理论简单,那么一个给定的证据对较简单理论的证实总是大于对较复杂理论的证实——较简单理论的旧概率与其新概率之间的差异总是大于较复杂理论的旧概率与新概率之间的类似差异因此,麦克格鲁的论证表明,如果我们认为它是成功的,那么骗子情景的先验概率低于现实主义情景的先验概率,而且,随着我们逐渐将越来越多的日常证据作为条件,两者之间的概率差距将继续扩大。这组结论似乎意味着(因为我们有大量的感官证据表明我们通常。
{"title":"The World, the Deceiver, and The Face in the Frost","authors":"L. McGrew","doi":"10.5840/QD2018827","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD2018827","url":null,"abstract":"In an appendix to The Foundations of Knowledge, Timothy McGrew provides the outline of a solution to the problem of the external world.1 McGrew argues that the probability of the existence of a deceiver who makes it appear that we live in a real external world must be lower than the probability of a real external world itself because the ontological commitments of the latter hypothesis will always necessarily be greater than those of the former. In the latter hypothesis, we posit a mental state of the deceiver as a cause of each of the apparently real things that seem to exist in the external world, but the deceiver himself also exists as an entity who is not merely the sum of all of these mental states. McGrew argues, further, that any time we conditionalize on some particular mental state of our own that we normally take to be caused by real objects in the external world, the gap in probability between realism and the deceiver hypothesis grows larger. He bases this argument on the probabilistic fact that if one theory is strictly simpler than some other theory, the confirmation a given piece of evidence affords to the simpler theory is always greater than the confirmation it affords to the more complex theory— the difference between the old probability of the simpler theory and its new probability is always greater than the comparable difference between the old and new probabilities of the more complex theory.2 McGrew’s argument thus shows, if we take it to be successful, that the prior probability of a deceiver scenario is lower than the prior probability of realism and also that, as we gradually conditionalize on more and more everyday evidence, the gap in probability between the two will continue to grow. This set of conclusions would seem to mean (since we have a great deal of sensory evidence that we normally","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-09-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85286853","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Proper Functionalism and the Metalevel: A Friendly Reply to Timothy and Lydia McGrew 适当的功能主义与金属层面:对蒂莫西和莉迪亚·麦克格鲁的友好答复
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/QD2018829
T. McNabb
Over the years, Alvin Plantinga has developed an epistemological system that allows beliefs to be warranted1 without requiring the subject to have internal access to those properties conferring warrant. Plantinga’s epistemology, known as proper functionalism, allows a subject’s belief to be warranted, insofar as the right conditions relating to cognitive proper function are in place.2 Plantinga’s theory of warrant can be summarized as follows:
多年来,阿尔文·普兰廷加发展了一套认识论体系,该体系允许信念是有根据的,而不要求主体有内部访问那些赋予证据的属性。Plantinga的认识论,被称为适当的功能主义,允许主体的信念得到保证,只要与认知适当功能相关的正确条件存在Plantinga的权证理论可以概括如下:
{"title":"Proper Functionalism and the Metalevel: A Friendly Reply to Timothy and Lydia McGrew","authors":"T. McNabb","doi":"10.5840/QD2018829","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD2018829","url":null,"abstract":"Over the years, Alvin Plantinga has developed an epistemological system that allows beliefs to be warranted1 without requiring the subject to have internal access to those properties conferring warrant. Plantinga’s epistemology, known as proper functionalism, allows a subject’s belief to be warranted, insofar as the right conditions relating to cognitive proper function are in place.2 Plantinga’s theory of warrant can be summarized as follows:","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80511710","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Preemptionism and Epistemic Authority 先发制人主义和认知权威
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/QD2018824
Donald J. Bungum
{"title":"Preemptionism and Epistemic Authority","authors":"Donald J. Bungum","doi":"10.5840/QD2018824","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD2018824","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79102892","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Unassertability of Contextualism 语境主义的不可断言性
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/QD2018825
M. Blaauw, J. Ridder
{"title":"The Unassertability of Contextualism","authors":"M. Blaauw, J. Ridder","doi":"10.5840/QD2018825","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD2018825","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73729133","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Fine-Tuning and the Search for an Archimedean Point 微调和寻找阿基米德点
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/QD2018828
T. McGrew
{"title":"Fine-Tuning and the Search for an Archimedean Point","authors":"T. McGrew","doi":"10.5840/QD2018828","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD2018828","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74630588","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Can Experience Fulfill the Many Roles of Evidence? 经验能代替证据的多重作用吗?
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/QD2018826
L. Gage
It is still a live question in epistemology and philosophy of science as to what exactly evidence is. In my view, evidence consists in experiences called “seemings.” This view is a version of the phenomenal conception of evidence, the position that evidence consists in nonfactive mental states with propositional content.1 This conception is opposed by sensedata theorists, disjunctivists, and those who think evidence consists in physical objects or publicly observable states of affairs (what I call the courtroom conception of evidence). Thomas Kelly has recently argued that the phenomenal conception cannot play all the roles evidence plays and is thus inadequate.2 Having first explained the nature of seemings, in this essay I utilize Kelly’s own understanding of the four major roles of evidence and argue that the phenomenal conception can play each one. Experience is a good candidate for evidence.
证据究竟是什么,在认识论和科学哲学中仍然是一个活跃的问题。在我看来,证据存在于被称为“似乎”的体验中。这种观点是现象性证据概念的一个版本,这种观点认为证据存在于具有命题内容的非活动的心理状态中这一概念遭到了感觉材料理论家、分离论者和那些认为证据存在于物理对象或可公开观察到的事件状态(我称之为法庭证据概念)的人的反对。托马斯·凯利最近提出,现象概念不能扮演证据所扮演的所有角色,因此是不充分的首先解释了表象的本质,在本文中,我利用凯利自己对证据的四个主要角色的理解,论证现象概念可以扮演每一个角色。经验是很好的证据。
{"title":"Can Experience Fulfill the Many Roles of Evidence?","authors":"L. Gage","doi":"10.5840/QD2018826","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD2018826","url":null,"abstract":"It is still a live question in epistemology and philosophy of science as to what exactly evidence is. In my view, evidence consists in experiences called “seemings.” This view is a version of the phenomenal conception of evidence, the position that evidence consists in nonfactive mental states with propositional content.1 This conception is opposed by sensedata theorists, disjunctivists, and those who think evidence consists in physical objects or publicly observable states of affairs (what I call the courtroom conception of evidence). Thomas Kelly has recently argued that the phenomenal conception cannot play all the roles evidence plays and is thus inadequate.2 Having first explained the nature of seemings, in this essay I utilize Kelly’s own understanding of the four major roles of evidence and argue that the phenomenal conception can play each one. Experience is a good candidate for evidence.","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74170922","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Complexly Based Beliefs and the Generality Problem for Reliabilism 基于复杂的信念与可靠性的一般性问题
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/QD2018823
Max Baker-Hytch
This essay argues that certain cases involving what I shall term complexly based belief, where a belief is formed via complex inference to the best explanation, pose a serious difficulty for reliabilist theories of epistemic justification or warrant. Many of our most important beliefs appear to be of this character. The problem, in short, is that in such cases we cannot identify any beliefforming process type that is such as to yield an intuitively correct verdict on the epistemic status of the agent’s belief. If this is correct, then no proposed solution to the generality problem can succeed.
本文认为,涉及到我称之为基于复杂的信念的某些情况,即通过对最佳解释的复杂推理形成的信念,给可靠主义的认识论证明或保证理论带来了严重的困难。我们许多最重要的信念似乎都具有这种特征。简而言之,问题在于,在这种情况下,我们无法识别任何信念形成过程类型,从而对主体信念的认知状态产生直觉上正确的判断。如果这是正确的,那么针对普遍性问题的任何解决方案都不会成功。
{"title":"Complexly Based Beliefs and the Generality Problem for Reliabilism","authors":"Max Baker-Hytch","doi":"10.5840/QD2018823","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD2018823","url":null,"abstract":"This essay argues that certain cases involving what I shall term complexly based belief, where a belief is formed via complex inference to the best explanation, pose a serious difficulty for reliabilist theories of epistemic justification or warrant. Many of our most important beliefs appear to be of this character. The problem, in short, is that in such cases we cannot identify any beliefforming process type that is such as to yield an intuitively correct verdict on the epistemic status of the agent’s belief. If this is correct, then no proposed solution to the generality problem can succeed.","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81077371","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Newman on the Grounds of Faith 纽曼论信仰的理由
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2018-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/QD2018822
F. Aquino
An epistemological issue that preoccupied John Henry Newman was the conditions under which Christian belief can be considered rational. As he sought to offer a broader and more refined account of faith and reason, he focused, for example, on the informal nature of reasoning and on the role of personal judgment in assessing evidence. In particular, his approach homed in on how the mind actually works and the conditions under which people reason within various contexts and fields of knowledge. Along these lines, an important, though complex, issue involves clarifying Newman’s position on the grounds of faith. In this respect, Anthony Kenny says the University Sermons contain some of Newman’s “very best work on the nature and justification of faith.”1 However, Newman’s position on the grounds of faith in some of the University Sermons is difficult to capture and, perhaps, prone to misunderstanding (e.g., serm. 10). As I hope to show, Newman provides greater clarification of his own position on the grounds of faith in sermon 13 (see also serm. 14). Accordingly, I will structure this essay in the following way. First, I will identify some potential misunderstandings in the University Sermons concerning Newman’s position on the grounds of faith. Second, I will show how the distinction between implicit and explicit reason in sermon 13 shapes both his rejection of a particular kind of hard rationalism (a religious belief is rational if and only if it can be articulated or demonstrated formally) and his alternative understanding of the grounds of faith. Implicit reason, for Newman, is a spontaneous, unconscious, or unargumentative process of reasoning by which people form beliefs without appealing to explicitly stated grounds; explicit reason is a secondorder activity that works out whether beliefs are true rather than false; the former is unreflective, while the latter has a reflective component.2 Third, I will argue constructively that Newman
约翰·亨利·纽曼关注的一个认识论问题是,在什么条件下基督教信仰可以被认为是理性的。当他试图对信仰和理性提供更广泛、更精细的描述时,他关注了推理的非正式性质,以及个人判断在评估证据中的作用。特别是,他的研究方法关注的是大脑是如何工作的,以及人们在不同的背景和知识领域中进行推理的条件。沿着这些思路,一个重要而复杂的问题涉及澄清纽曼在信仰基础上的立场。在这方面,安东尼·肯尼(Anthony Kenny)说,《大学讲道》包含了纽曼“在信仰的本质和称义方面的一些最好的作品”。1然而,纽曼在一些大学布道中基于信仰的立场是很难捕捉的,也许,容易被误解(例如,serm。10)。正如我希望展示的那样,纽曼在第13篇讲道中更明确地阐述了他自己在信仰基础上的立场。14)。因此,我将以以下方式组织这篇文章。首先,我将找出一些潜在的误解,在大学讲道纽曼的立场在信仰的基础上。其次,我将展示在第13篇讲道中,隐性理性和显性理性之间的区别如何塑造了他对一种特定类型的硬理性主义(一种宗教信仰当且仅当它可以被正式地表达或证明时才是理性的)的拒绝,以及他对信仰基础的另一种理解。对纽曼来说,隐性理性是一种自发的、无意识的或无争议的推理过程,人们通过这种推理过程形成信仰,而无需诉诸明确陈述的依据;外显推理是一种二级活动,用于判断信念是真的还是假的;前者无反思性,后者有反思性第三,我将建设性地论证纽曼
{"title":"Newman on the Grounds of Faith","authors":"F. Aquino","doi":"10.5840/QD2018822","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/QD2018822","url":null,"abstract":"An epistemological issue that preoccupied John Henry Newman was the conditions under which Christian belief can be considered rational. As he sought to offer a broader and more refined account of faith and reason, he focused, for example, on the informal nature of reasoning and on the role of personal judgment in assessing evidence. In particular, his approach homed in on how the mind actually works and the conditions under which people reason within various contexts and fields of knowledge. Along these lines, an important, though complex, issue involves clarifying Newman’s position on the grounds of faith. In this respect, Anthony Kenny says the University Sermons contain some of Newman’s “very best work on the nature and justification of faith.”1 However, Newman’s position on the grounds of faith in some of the University Sermons is difficult to capture and, perhaps, prone to misunderstanding (e.g., serm. 10). As I hope to show, Newman provides greater clarification of his own position on the grounds of faith in sermon 13 (see also serm. 14). Accordingly, I will structure this essay in the following way. First, I will identify some potential misunderstandings in the University Sermons concerning Newman’s position on the grounds of faith. Second, I will show how the distinction between implicit and explicit reason in sermon 13 shapes both his rejection of a particular kind of hard rationalism (a religious belief is rational if and only if it can be articulated or demonstrated formally) and his alternative understanding of the grounds of faith. Implicit reason, for Newman, is a spontaneous, unconscious, or unargumentative process of reasoning by which people form beliefs without appealing to explicitly stated grounds; explicit reason is a secondorder activity that works out whether beliefs are true rather than false; the former is unreflective, while the latter has a reflective component.2 Third, I will argue constructively that Newman","PeriodicalId":40384,"journal":{"name":"Quaestiones Disputatae","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79180013","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Quaestiones Disputatae
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1