首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research最新文献

英文 中文
An Introduction to Food Ethics: A Philosophical Pursuit 食品伦理导论》:哲学追求
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-07-13 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00338-z
Shivani Sharma

The relation between food and morality is not a novel concern in Philosophy. There have been discussions about the same in traditions as early as the Vedic and Buddhist traditions in Indian philosophy. While food has always been a significant topic of discussion in ethics, there has been the upcoming of a new understanding of the relation between food and morality in the twenty-first century, namely—food ethics.

食物与道德之间的关系在哲学中并不是一个新问题。早在印度哲学的吠陀传统和佛教传统中,就有关于食物与道德关系的讨论。虽然食物一直是伦理学讨论的一个重要话题,但在二十一世纪,人们开始对食物与道德之间的关系有了新的认识,即食物伦理学。
{"title":"An Introduction to Food Ethics: A Philosophical Pursuit","authors":"Shivani Sharma","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00338-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00338-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The relation between food and morality is not a novel concern in Philosophy. There have been discussions about the same in traditions as early as the Vedic and Buddhist traditions in Indian philosophy. While food has always been a significant topic of discussion in ethics, there has been the upcoming of a new understanding of the relation between food and morality in the twenty-first century, namely—food ethics.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"63 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-07-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141613863","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Metaphysical Integration of Upāya in the Trika Philosophy and Bhoja’s Model Based on Triguṇa-Puruṣārtha to Understand the Concepts of Śivatva, Self-Realisation and Consciousness 三卡哲学中 Upāya 的形而上学整合与基于 Triguṇa-Puruṣārtha 的 Bhoja 模式,以理解 Śivatva、自我实现和意识的概念
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-06-18 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00337-0
Niharika Sharma, Shankar Rajaraman, Sangeetha Menon

The Trika school, which is popularly known as Pratyabhijñā-darśana or Kashmir Śaivism is an absolutist and theistic school of Śaivism in the 9th Century. For the Trika school, the self is synonymous with pure consciousness, equated with Śiva. The path elaborated by the school is from self-ignorance to the realisation of pure consciousness. The Trika philosophy strives to answer two fundamental and interrelated questions. Firstly, understanding oneself as a reduced form of Śiva? Secondly, how does an individual attain “Śivatva”? In this study, we explicate answers to these queries by resorting to the metaphysics of the Trika school along with interpretative textual analysis and present a model proposed by Bhoja Raja based on the three guṇas. This model attributed to Sāṅkhya philosophy and puruṣārtha could help to place the metaphysics of upāya in Trika philosophy in the context of the question of attaining “Śivatva”.

Trika 派,俗称 Pratyabhijñā-darśana 或克什米尔圣西瓦教,是 9 世纪圣西瓦教的一个绝对主义和有神论学派。在特里卡学派看来,自我是纯粹意识的同义词,等同于希瓦。该学派所阐述的道路是从自我否定到纯粹意识的实现。Trika 哲学致力于回答两个相互关联的基本问题。首先,如何理解自己是圣神的简化形式?其次,个人如何实现 "Śivatva"?在本研究中,我们通过三卡学派的形而上学和文本诠释分析来阐述这些问题的答案,并提出了博迦-拉贾基于三犍陀提出的模型。这个归因于萨迦哲学和普鲁沙哲学的模型有助于将三卡哲学中的形而上学置于达到 "圣智"(Śivatva)这一问题的背景中。
{"title":"The Metaphysical Integration of Upāya in the Trika Philosophy and Bhoja’s Model Based on Triguṇa-Puruṣārtha to Understand the Concepts of Śivatva, Self-Realisation and Consciousness","authors":"Niharika Sharma, Shankar Rajaraman, Sangeetha Menon","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00337-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00337-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The Trika school, which is popularly known as Pratyabhijñā-darśana or Kashmir Śaivism is an absolutist and theistic school of Śaivism in the 9th Century. For the Trika school, the self is synonymous with pure consciousness, equated with <i>Śiva</i>. The path elaborated by the school is from self-ignorance to the realisation of pure consciousness. The Trika philosophy strives to answer two fundamental and interrelated questions. Firstly, understanding oneself as a reduced form of <i>Śiva</i>? Secondly, how does an individual attain “<i>Śivatva”</i>? In this study, we explicate answers to these queries by resorting to the metaphysics of the Trika school along with interpretative textual analysis and present a model proposed by Bhoja Raja based on the three <i>guṇas</i>. This model attributed to Sāṅkhya philosophy and <i>puruṣārtha</i> could help to place the metaphysics of <i>upāya</i> in Trika philosophy in the context of the question of attaining “<i>Śivatva”</i>.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"27 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-06-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141507561","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An Exposition of the Notion Self and Identity in the Philosophy of Rāmānuja: A Critical Study 拉马努贾哲学中的 "自我 "和 "同一性 "概念阐释:批判性研究
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-05-30 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00332-5
Deepak Kumar Sethy

The proposed study endeavors to delve into the philosophical concepts of self and identity as elucidated by the eminent Indian philosopher Rāmānujachārya. This critical examination aims to underscore Rāmānuja’s perspective on the self, surpassing the limitations inherent in both physical and mentalist accounts of human existence. The study specifically directs attention to queries surrounding self-ownership, the constancy of identity amidst change, consciousness, and its interconnection with the self. Unlike explanations that reduce the notion of self to either the body or the mind, this study seeks to explicate Rāmānuja's accounts of self and identity by recognizing that merely equating the self with the body or mind fails to address the profound sense of ownership or possession we experience. In the vast landscape of Indian philosophical thought, the self is traditionally viewed as inherently eternal, temporarily associated with the body for the purpose of navigating accumulated karma across multiple lifetimes. However, this study diverges from moralistic and eschatological discussions, concentrating instead on the metaphysical aspects articulated by Rāmānuja. Central to Rāmānuja's philosophy is the juxtaposition of Brahman, the ultimate reality, with ātman, the individual self present in all living beings. Distinctions among beings are attributed to the nature of the bodies they inhabit. The crux of the matter lies in understanding the relationship between the individual self and Brahman, conceptualized as a part–whole relationship. Consequently, the inquiry emerges: How does the part relate to the whole? What is the nature of the self in the context of Brahman? This paper undertakes a dual-level philosophical analysis of the notion self. It explores the metaphysical level, seeking to comprehend the general meaning and significance of the self. Simultaneously, it delves into the contextual and particular dimensions, unraveling the specific conceptualizations that the individual self undergoes contingent upon its situations. Further questions pertaining to self and identity come to the forefront. How does the self relate to its identity—is it pre-given or constructed? Is there an intrinsic essence to the identity of the self? Addressing these questions inevitably draws attention to the intertwined issues of caste and gender within this philosophical discourse.

拟议的研究试图深入探讨印度著名哲学家拉马努贾所阐明的自我和身份的哲学概念。本批判性研究旨在强调 Rāmānuja 对自我的看法,超越了对人类存在的物理和心理论述所固有的局限性。本研究特别关注围绕自我所有权、变化中身份的不变性、意识及其与自我的相互联系等问题。与将自我概念简化为身体或心灵的解释不同,本研究试图通过认识到仅仅将自我等同于身体或心灵并不能解决我们所体验到的深刻的所有权或拥有感,来阐释拉玛努贾关于自我和身份的论述。在印度哲学思想的广阔版图中,自我历来被视为内在永恒的,只是暂时与身体联系在一起,以便穿越多生多世累积的业力。然而,本研究偏离了道德论和末世论的讨论,而是集中于拉斯马努贾所阐述的形而上学方面。拉玛努贾哲学的核心是将终极实在梵(Brahman)与存在于众生中的个体自我 "ātman "并列。众生之间的区别归因于他们所居住的身体的性质。问题的关键在于理解个体自我与梵之间的关系,即概念上的部分-整体关系。因此,出现了这样一个问题:部分与整体之间的关系是怎样的?部分与整体的关系如何?在梵的背景下,自我的本质是什么?本文从两个层面对 "自我 "这一概念进行了哲学分析。它从形而上学的层面进行探讨,试图理解自我的一般含义和意义。与此同时,它还深入研究了背景和特定层面,揭示了个体自我因其所处环境而经历的特定概念化。与自我和身份有关的更多问题浮出水面。自我与其身份的关系如何--是预先赋予的还是建构的?自我身份是否有内在本质?探讨这些问题不可避免地会引起人们对这一哲学论述中相互交织的种姓和性别问题的关注。
{"title":"An Exposition of the Notion Self and Identity in the Philosophy of Rāmānuja: A Critical Study","authors":"Deepak Kumar Sethy","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00332-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00332-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The proposed study endeavors to delve into the philosophical concepts of self and identity as elucidated by the eminent Indian philosopher Rāmānujachārya. This critical examination aims to underscore Rāmānuja’s perspective on the self, surpassing the limitations inherent in both physical and mentalist accounts of human existence. The study specifically directs attention to queries surrounding self-ownership, the constancy of identity amidst change, consciousness, and its interconnection with the self. Unlike explanations that reduce the notion of self to either the body or the mind, this study seeks to explicate Rāmānuja's accounts of self and identity by recognizing that merely equating the self with the body or mind fails to address the profound sense of ownership or possession we experience. In the vast landscape of Indian philosophical thought, the self is traditionally viewed as inherently eternal, temporarily associated with the body for the purpose of navigating accumulated karma across multiple lifetimes. However, this study diverges from moralistic and eschatological discussions, concentrating instead on the metaphysical aspects articulated by Rāmānuja. Central to Rāmānuja's philosophy is the juxtaposition of <i>Brahman</i>, the ultimate reality, with <i>ātman</i>, the individual self present in all living beings. Distinctions among beings are attributed to the nature of the bodies they inhabit. The crux of the matter lies in understanding the relationship between the individual self and <i>Brahman</i>, conceptualized as a part–whole relationship. Consequently, the inquiry emerges: How does the part relate to the whole? What is the nature of the self in the context of <i>Brahman</i>? This paper undertakes a dual-level philosophical analysis of the notion self. It explores the metaphysical level, seeking to comprehend the general meaning and significance of the self. Simultaneously, it delves into the contextual and particular dimensions, unraveling the specific conceptualizations that the individual self undergoes contingent upon its situations. Further questions pertaining to self and identity come to the forefront. How does the self relate to its identity—is it pre-given or constructed? Is there an intrinsic essence to the identity of the self? Addressing these questions inevitably draws attention to the intertwined issues of caste and gender within this philosophical discourse.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"48 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-05-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141191875","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Searle’s Refutation of Locke’s Representationalist Theory of Perception 塞尔对洛克表象主义知觉理论的反驳
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-05-25 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00330-7
S. Sreenish

John. R. Searle’s account of perception is often called the intentionality theory of perception (ITP). ITP maintains direct realism. According to direct realism, physical objects are directly perceived. Searle denies Locke's representational theory of perception since the latter is an antithesis of direct realism. Searle's contention is that, first, according to the representational theory of perception, subjective ideas (mind-dependent entities) are the only object of perception, we do not perceive physical objects at all. Second, Searle says that on the face of the resemblance thesis, the representational theory of perception is not secured because the former is insufficient to explain the latter. This paper is an attempt to reflect on these two charges raised by Searle. First, I will try to show how we can conceive physical objects are objects (indirect) of perception within Locke’s representational theory of perception. Then, it will be argued that Locke’s representationalist theory of perception can be upheld without the support of the resemblance thesis.

约翰.塞尔(R. Searle)的知觉理论通常被称为知觉的意向性理论(ITP)。ITP坚持直接现实主义。根据直接现实主义,物理对象是直接被感知的。塞尔否认洛克的表象知觉理论,因为后者是直接现实主义的对立面。塞尔的论点是:首先,根据表象知觉理论,主观观念(依赖于心灵的实体)是知觉的唯一对象,我们根本不知觉物理对象。其次,塞尔说,从相似论的表面上看,知觉的表象理论是不牢靠的,因为前者不足以解释后者。本文试图对塞尔提出的这两项指控进行反思。首先,我将试图说明我们如何在洛克的表象知觉理论中设想物理对象是知觉的对象(间接)。然后,我将论证洛克的表象主义知觉理论在没有相似论的支持下是可以成立的。
{"title":"Searle’s Refutation of Locke’s Representationalist Theory of Perception","authors":"S. Sreenish","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00330-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00330-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>John. R. Searle’s account of perception is often called the intentionality theory of perception (ITP). ITP maintains direct realism. According to direct realism, physical objects are directly perceived. Searle denies Locke's representational theory of perception since the latter is an antithesis of direct realism. Searle's contention is that, first, according to the representational theory of perception, subjective ideas (mind-dependent entities) are the only object of perception, we do not perceive physical objects at all. Second, Searle says that on the face of the resemblance thesis, the representational theory of perception is not secured because the former is insufficient to explain the latter. This paper is an attempt to reflect on these two charges raised by Searle. First, I will try to show how we can conceive physical objects are objects (indirect) of perception within Locke’s representational theory of perception. Then, it will be argued that Locke’s representationalist theory of perception can be upheld without the support of the resemblance thesis.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"18 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-05-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141146387","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Date of Ādi Śaṅkarācārya and Emergence of Śaivism as a Popular Religion in South India 阿迪-圣十字架的年代以及圣十字架作为南印度流行宗教的兴起
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-05-14 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-023-00301-4
R. Saraswati Sainath

The date of Ādi Śaṅkarācārya has been one of the unsolved problems of Indian Philosophy. He is generally accepted to have lived from 788 to 820 CE and is thus assigned from the end of the eighth century to the beginning of the ninth century. So far scholars who have worked on this problem have consulted his hagiographies and his works to determine his date. However, they have not studied the date of Ādi Śaṅkarācārya by placing him in the context of the development of religion in South India. Nor have they consulted South Indian sources, especially Tamiḻ texts, to see if there are any references to his philosophy. In this paper, I study the problem of the date of Ādi Śaṅkarācārya by consulting Tamiḻ sources and the hitherto less consulted epic Śivarahasya. I also connect his date with the emergence of Śaivism as a popular religion in South India. Based on my study, I place Ādi Śaṅkarācārya in the fifth century BCE and as a result, I emphasize the importance of redating Hindu scriptures, especially the Vedas, as Ādi Śaṅkarācārya is the earliest commentator.

阿底Śaṅkarācārya的年代一直是印度哲学中悬而未决的问题之一。人们普遍认为他生活在公元 788 年至 820 年之间,因此将他的年代定为八世纪末至九世纪初。迄今为止,研究这一问题的学者们都是通过查阅他的传记和作品来确定他的年代。但是,他们并没有将阿底Śaṅkarācārya 放在南印度宗教发展的背景下研究他的年代。他们也没有查阅过南印度的资料,尤其是塔米(Tamiḻ)典籍,以了解是否有关于他的哲学的记载。在本文中,我通过查阅塔米(Tamiḻ)文献和迄今为止较少查阅的史诗《希瓦拉哈夏》(Śivarahasya),研究了阿底Śaṅkarācārya 的年代问题。我还将他的出生日期与Śaivism 成为南印度流行宗教的时间联系起来。根据我的研究,我将Ādi Śaṅkarācārya的年代定为公元前五世纪,因此,我强调了重新注释印度教经文,尤其是《吠陀经》的重要性,因为Ādi Śaṅkarācārya是最早的注释者。
{"title":"The Date of Ādi Śaṅkarācārya and Emergence of Śaivism as a Popular Religion in South India","authors":"R. Saraswati Sainath","doi":"10.1007/s40961-023-00301-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-023-00301-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The date of Ādi Śaṅkarācārya has been one of the unsolved problems of Indian Philosophy. He is generally accepted to have lived from 788 to 820 CE and is thus assigned from the end of the eighth century to the beginning of the ninth century. So far scholars who have worked on this problem have consulted his hagiographies and his works to determine his date. However, they have not studied the date of Ādi Śaṅkarācārya by placing him in the context of the development of religion in South India. Nor have they consulted South Indian sources, especially Tamiḻ texts, to see if there are any references to his philosophy. In this paper, I study the problem of the date of Ādi Śaṅkarācārya by consulting Tamiḻ sources and the hitherto less consulted epic <i>Śivarahasya</i>. I also connect his date with the emergence of Śaivism as a popular religion in South India. Based on my study, I place Ādi Śaṅkarācārya in the fifth century BCE and as a result, I emphasize the importance of redating Hindu scriptures, especially the <i>Vedas</i>, as Ādi Śaṅkarācārya is the earliest commentator.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"58 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-05-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140929459","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Berkeley’s Theory of Perception: Searle Versus Pappas 伯克利的知觉理论:塞尔与帕帕斯
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-05-11 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00334-3
S. Sreenish

In Seeing Things as They Are (Searle 2015), Searle developed a direct realist’s theory of perception. According to direct realism, physical objects are directly and immediately perceived. Searle claims that Berkeley’s theory of perception goes against direct realism. For Searle, Berkeley’s theory suggests that only subjective experiences (ideas) are directly and immediately perceived, not physical objects. Contrary to Searle, G. S. Pappas claims that Berkeley’s theory of perception is consistent with the view that physical objects are immediately perceivable (Pappas 1982; Pappas 1987). Given the conflicting interpretations of Berkeley’s theory of perception, this paper attempts to defend Searle’s position on Berkeley’s theory of perception. It refutes Pappas’ interpretation by arguing that he is inconsistent with Berkeley’s theses of ontological phenomenalism and heterogeneity thesis.

在《看见事物的本来面目》(Searle 2015)一书中,塞尔提出了直接现实主义的感知理论。根据直接现实主义,物理对象是直接和立即被感知的。塞尔声称,伯克利的知觉理论与直接现实主义背道而驰。在塞尔看来,伯克利的理论表明,只有主观经验(观念)才能被直接和立即感知,而不是物理对象。与塞尔相反,帕帕斯(G. S. Pappas)认为伯克利的知觉理论与物理对象可立即被感知的观点是一致的(帕帕斯,1982 年;帕帕斯,1987 年)。鉴于对伯克利知觉理论的解释相互冲突,本文试图捍卫塞尔对伯克利知觉理论的立场。本文驳斥了帕帕斯的解释,认为他与伯克利的本体论现象论和异质性论不一致。
{"title":"Berkeley’s Theory of Perception: Searle Versus Pappas","authors":"S. Sreenish","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00334-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00334-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In <i>Seeing Things as They Are</i> (Searle 2015), Searle developed a direct realist’s theory of perception. According to direct realism, physical objects are directly and immediately perceived. Searle claims that Berkeley’s theory of perception goes against direct realism. For Searle, Berkeley’s theory suggests that only subjective experiences (ideas) are directly and immediately perceived, not physical objects. Contrary to Searle, G. S. Pappas claims that Berkeley’s theory of perception is consistent with the view that physical objects are immediately perceivable (Pappas 1982; Pappas 1987). Given the conflicting interpretations of Berkeley’s theory of perception, this paper attempts to defend Searle’s position on Berkeley’s theory of perception. It refutes Pappas’ interpretation by arguing that he is inconsistent with Berkeley’s theses of ontological phenomenalism and heterogeneity thesis.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"5 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-05-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140929128","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Pritchard on Veritism and Trivial Truths 普里查德谈唯实主义和琐碎真理
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-04-03 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00329-0
Anumita Shukla, Mayank Bora

Proponents of Veritism believe that truth is the sole non-instrumental epistemic good. This view is often taken to entail that all truths should be of equal epistemic value. Hence, it is put under stress by the presence of trivial truths: truths to which we attach relatively little or no epistemic value. Pritchard, in the defense of Veritism, has tried to argue that the best way to understand the implications of Veritism is to think in terms of how an intellectually virtuous inquirer would pursue truth. Furthermore, he thinks that such an inquirer would prefer weighty truths and set aside trivial ones. As such, he thinks that our epistemic disregard for trivial truths is just to be expected given Veritism. We argue that Pritchard’s defense of Veritism fails, and the problem of trivial truths remains a significant challenge for Veritism.

真理论的支持者认为,真理是唯一的非工具性认识论之善。这种观点通常被认为意味着所有真理都具有同等的认识论价值。因此,琐碎真理的存在(我们对其赋予的认识论价值相对较低或没有)使这一观点受到了压力。普里查德在为唯理论辩护时曾试图论证,理解唯理论含义的最佳方式是从一个智力上良善的探究者如何追求真理的角度来思考。此外,他认为这样的探究者会偏爱重要的真理,而将琐碎的真理搁置一旁。因此,他认为,鉴于唯理论,我们在认识论上无视琐碎的真理是意料之中的。我们认为,普里查德对唯理论的辩护是失败的,琐碎真理的问题仍然是唯理论面临的一个重大挑战。
{"title":"Pritchard on Veritism and Trivial Truths","authors":"Anumita Shukla, Mayank Bora","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00329-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00329-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Proponents of Veritism believe that truth is the sole non-instrumental epistemic good. This view is often taken to entail that all truths should be of equal epistemic value. Hence, it is put under stress by the presence of trivial truths: truths to which we attach relatively little or no epistemic value. Pritchard, in the defense of Veritism, has tried to argue that the best way to understand the implications of Veritism is to think in terms of how an intellectually virtuous inquirer would pursue truth. Furthermore, he thinks that such an inquirer would prefer weighty truths and set aside trivial ones. As such, he thinks that our epistemic disregard for trivial truths is just to be expected given Veritism. We argue that Pritchard’s defense of Veritism fails, and the problem of trivial truths remains a significant challenge for Veritism.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"25 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140599864","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Sri Aurobindo: Cosmology, Psychology and Integral Experience 斯里-奥罗宾多宇宙论、心理学和综合体验
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-04-02 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00328-1
Bhawani Shankar
<p>Sri Aurobindo is one of the most prominent figures in the Indian Philosophy of twentieth century and yet we barely find any mention of his work in the philosophy circles. He has written extensively on metaphysics, aesthetics, and ethics. Sri Aurobindo’s work is all-encompassing and carries marks of a deep yogic insight into both the individual self (with all its parts and their integrated working) and the universe that ultimately shares a relation of identity with the individual in secret. He talks about a world-process that contains evolution qualified with involution. It is one of the most unique features of Sri Aurobindo’s philosophy. He deals with the questions of ignorance also in the most satisfying way. Sri Aurobindo has an integral vision that sees everything in the movement of one and develops the methods and practices of Integral Yoga. In his yogic vision, he not only tries to solve the problems of humanity but also attempts to make a very bold move of transforming the whole earthly existence into a divine existence through one large stride. The epistemological discussion we find in his work is deeply connected with his metaphysics. He articulates the limits and extents of reason and senses and attempts to surpass them. Sri Aurobindo is not an armchair philosopher; he attempts to salvage the human condition by empowering humanity to consciously guide the march of human evolution towards a divine future. The boldness of his vision, the originality of his philosophical work is spectacular. In this paper, I will discuss his World-process, i.e. the evolution qualified with involution. I will also discuss the epistemological foundation of his philosophy, cosmology and integral yoga psychology. For the sake of clarity in understanding, the paper is divided into five major sections starting with an introduction. Integralism is a central idea in Sri Aurobindo’s philosophy and I have tried to do justice with it throughout this paper. In the end, the paper attempts to deals with three main themes—cosmology, integral yoga psychology and integral experience. All these three themes shall bring out—The integral experience of Sri Aurobindo is deeply intertwined with his cosmology and yogic psychology and shall not be seen in isolation. Integral experience of reality is also intertwined and works in tandem with his Integral Yoga. There is a yogic exploration of oneness between the self and world that informs and shapes both his philosophical and yogic endeavors. The rationale behind undertaking this study is to question whether the observations of the physical world from the standpoint of yogic experience could suggest some new theoretical framework for the metaphysical ontology of the world. Taking perspectives from the states of consciousness described by Sri Aurobindo may furnish us with a deeper understanding of the material and metaphysical character of physical categories, such as matter, energy, force, space, and time. This paper however is a
斯里-奥罗宾多是二十世纪印度哲学界最杰出的人物之一,但我们在哲学界几乎找不到关于他作品的任何提及。他在形而上学、美学和伦理学方面著述颇丰。斯里-奥罗宾多的著作包罗万象,既有对个体自我(包括其所有部分及其综合作用)的深刻瑜珈洞察,也有对宇宙的深刻洞察。他谈到了一个包含进化与内敛的世界进程。这是斯里兰卡奥罗宾多哲学最独特的特征之一。他还以最令人满意的方式论述了无知问题。斯里-奥罗宾多具有一种整体观,从 "一 "的运动中看待一切,并发展了整体瑜伽的方法和实践。在他的瑜伽观中,他不仅试图解决人类的问题,而且还试图采取非常大胆的行动,通过大步迈进,将整个尘世的存在转化为神圣的存在。我们在他的著作中看到的认识论讨论与他的形而上学有着深刻的联系。他阐明了理性和感官的局限和范围,并试图超越它们。斯里-奥罗宾多不是一个坐而论道的哲学家;他试图通过增强人类的能力来拯救人类的境况,有意识地引导人类向着神圣的未来进化。他的远见卓识和哲学著作的独创性令人叹为观止。在本文中,我将讨论他的 "世界进程",即以 "内卷 "为条件的进化论。我还将讨论他的哲学、宇宙论和整体瑜伽心理学的认识论基础。为便于理解,本文从导言开始分为五大部分。整体论是斯里-奥罗宾多哲学的核心思想,我试图在本文中对其进行公正的阐述。最后,本文试图论述三大主题--宇宙论、整体瑜伽心理学和整体体验。所有这三个主题都将揭示--斯里-奥罗宾多的整体体验与他的宇宙论和瑜伽心理学深深地交织在一起,不应被孤立地看待。对现实的整体体验也与他的整体瑜伽相互交织和配合。他对自我与世界合一的瑜伽探索,为他的哲学和瑜伽事业提供了信息,并塑造了他的哲学和瑜伽事业。进行这项研究的理由是质疑从瑜伽体验的角度观察物质世界是否能为世界的形而上学本体论提出一些新的理论框架。从斯里-奥罗宾多描述的意识状态的角度出发,或许能让我们更深入地理解物质、能量、力量、空间和时间等物理范畴的物质和形而上学特性。然而,本文只是对奥罗宾多与宇宙学、心理学和整体经验相关性的介绍性概述,为重新诠释和达成合成形而上学提供了一个哲学框架。
{"title":"Sri Aurobindo: Cosmology, Psychology and Integral Experience","authors":"Bhawani Shankar","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00328-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00328-1","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Sri Aurobindo is one of the most prominent figures in the Indian Philosophy of twentieth century and yet we barely find any mention of his work in the philosophy circles. He has written extensively on metaphysics, aesthetics, and ethics. Sri Aurobindo’s work is all-encompassing and carries marks of a deep yogic insight into both the individual self (with all its parts and their integrated working) and the universe that ultimately shares a relation of identity with the individual in secret. He talks about a world-process that contains evolution qualified with involution. It is one of the most unique features of Sri Aurobindo’s philosophy. He deals with the questions of ignorance also in the most satisfying way. Sri Aurobindo has an integral vision that sees everything in the movement of one and develops the methods and practices of Integral Yoga. In his yogic vision, he not only tries to solve the problems of humanity but also attempts to make a very bold move of transforming the whole earthly existence into a divine existence through one large stride. The epistemological discussion we find in his work is deeply connected with his metaphysics. He articulates the limits and extents of reason and senses and attempts to surpass them. Sri Aurobindo is not an armchair philosopher; he attempts to salvage the human condition by empowering humanity to consciously guide the march of human evolution towards a divine future. The boldness of his vision, the originality of his philosophical work is spectacular. In this paper, I will discuss his World-process, i.e. the evolution qualified with involution. I will also discuss the epistemological foundation of his philosophy, cosmology and integral yoga psychology. For the sake of clarity in understanding, the paper is divided into five major sections starting with an introduction. Integralism is a central idea in Sri Aurobindo’s philosophy and I have tried to do justice with it throughout this paper. In the end, the paper attempts to deals with three main themes—cosmology, integral yoga psychology and integral experience. All these three themes shall bring out—The integral experience of Sri Aurobindo is deeply intertwined with his cosmology and yogic psychology and shall not be seen in isolation. Integral experience of reality is also intertwined and works in tandem with his Integral Yoga. There is a yogic exploration of oneness between the self and world that informs and shapes both his philosophical and yogic endeavors. The rationale behind undertaking this study is to question whether the observations of the physical world from the standpoint of yogic experience could suggest some new theoretical framework for the metaphysical ontology of the world. Taking perspectives from the states of consciousness described by Sri Aurobindo may furnish us with a deeper understanding of the material and metaphysical character of physical categories, such as matter, energy, force, space, and time. This paper however is a","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"4 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-04-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140599840","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Identity, Difference and Diversity: A Journey from the Bṛhadāraṇyaka-Upaniṣad to Mukund Lath 身份、差异与多样性:从《布达拉乌帕尼藏》到《穆孔德-拉特》之旅
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-26 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00327-2
Daniel Raveh

In this paper, I offer a close comparative reading of a creation myth from chapter 1 of the Bṛhadāraṇyaka-Upaniṣad, which opens with the startling statement “ātmaivedam agra āsīt”, “in the beginning there was the self (ātman)”. I read this classical text with Śaṅkara, its foremost commentator, in dialogue with an ensemble of Indologists (Wilhelm Halbfass, Greg Bailey and Frederick Smith) and theorists (Walter Benjamin, Ramchandra Gandhi and Hélène Cixous), and vis-à-vis, the creation myth narrated in chapter 1 of the Book of Genesis. My aim is to decipher the intrinsic relation between identity, difference and diversity underlying the Upaniṣadic myth, and the ambivalent relationship (fear and desire) between self and other depicted here. The Upaniṣad presents a narrative of “the self first”, and implied is the aspiration to retrieve and rediscover this first self, the ātman, which precedes and encompasses everything else. I challenge this narrative drawing on Mukund Lath’s paper (J World Philos 4:6–23, 2003/2018). According to Lath, being is becoming, and change is a precondition of identity-formation. Identity, he argues, does not only accommodate but also invites change and plurality. Identity for Lath is a matter of creation, not restoration. It is pregnant with the future, not obsessed with premordiality. Lath’s unique case study for his counter-Upaniṣadic discussion of identity and self is classical Indian music, rāga music.

在本文中,我将对《乌帕尼藏》(Bṛhadāraṇyaka-Upaniṣad)第 1 章中的创世神话进行近距离比较阅读,该章以 "ātmaivedam agra āsīt"("起初有自我(ātman)")这一惊人语句开篇。我在与印度学家(威廉-哈尔布法斯、格雷格-贝利和弗雷德里克-史密斯)和理论家(沃尔特-本雅明、拉姆昌德拉-甘地和埃莱娜-西绪斯)的对话中,与《创世纪》第一章中叙述的创世神话相对照,与该书最重要的注释者Śaṅkara一起解读了这一经典文本。我的目的是解读奥帕尼藏神话所蕴含的身份、差异和多样性之间的内在关系,以及其中所描绘的自我与他人之间的矛盾关系(恐惧与欲望)。奥帕尼藏》展现了 "自我第一 "的叙事,隐含着找回和重新发现第一自我--"阿特曼"--的愿望,它先于并涵盖了其他一切。我借鉴穆昆德-拉特的论文(《世界哲学》4:6-23,2003/2018),对这一叙事提出质疑。拉特认为,存在即成为,变化是身份形成的先决条件。他认为,身份不仅能容纳变化和多元性,而且还邀请变化和多元性。对 Lath 来说,身份是一个创造而非恢复的问题。它孕育着未来,而不是沉迷于先验性。拉特对身份与自我的反乌帕尼藏式讨论的独特案例研究是印度古典音乐--拉加音乐。
{"title":"Identity, Difference and Diversity: A Journey from the Bṛhadāraṇyaka-Upaniṣad to Mukund Lath","authors":"Daniel Raveh","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00327-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00327-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In this paper, I offer a close comparative reading of a creation myth from chapter 1 of the <i>Bṛhadāraṇyaka-Upaniṣad</i>, which opens with the startling statement “ātmaivedam agra āsīt”, “in the beginning there was the self (ātman)”. I read this classical text with Śaṅkara, its foremost commentator, in dialogue with an ensemble of Indologists (Wilhelm Halbfass, Greg Bailey and Frederick Smith) and theorists (Walter Benjamin, Ramchandra Gandhi and Hélène Cixous), and vis-à-vis, the creation myth narrated in chapter 1 of the <i>Book of Genesis</i>. My aim is to decipher the intrinsic relation between identity, difference and diversity underlying the Upaniṣadic myth, and the ambivalent relationship (fear and desire) between self and other depicted here. The Upaniṣad presents a narrative of “the self first”, and implied is the aspiration to retrieve and rediscover this first self, the ātman, which precedes and encompasses everything else. I challenge this narrative drawing on Mukund Lath’s paper (J World Philos 4:6–23, 2003/2018). According to Lath, being is becoming, and change is a precondition of identity-formation. Identity, he argues, does not only accommodate but also invites change and plurality. Identity for Lath is a matter of creation, not restoration. It is pregnant with the future, not obsessed with premordiality. Lath’s unique case study for his counter-Upaniṣadic discussion of identity and self is classical Indian music, rāga music.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"19 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-02-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139979894","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Swami Vivekananda: An Epitome of Nationalism 斯瓦米-维韦卡南达民族主义的缩影
IF 0.1 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-13 DOI: 10.1007/s40961-024-00324-5
Lakshman Patra

What we understand by nationalism is the idea of supporting one’s country, people, culture and sovereignty of the nation. It believes in self-rule, with an objective to maintain the national unity and solidarity. It also encourages pride in national achievements and is closely linked with patriotism. One who dedicates his life to promoting the above objectives for the glory of his nation is considered as a nationalist. Swami Vivekananda who has dedicated his short, but meaningful life for the upliftment of his fellow country-men and worked hard for the freedom of his motherland from political, religious, economic and cultural bondage, for which he can rightly be called an epitome of nationalism or a true nationalist. In this article, I shall focus on his dedications and contributions for his nation and human race at large and justify him to be called a true nationalist.

我们所理解的民族主义是支持自己的国家、人民、文化和国家主权的思想。它信奉自治,以维护国家统一和团结为目标。它还鼓励为民族成就感到自豪,并与爱国主义紧密相连。为了民族的荣耀而献身于促进上述目标的人被视为民族主义者。斯瓦米-维韦卡南达(Swami Vivekananda)为提高同胞的地位奉献了短暂而有意义的一生,并为祖国摆脱政治、宗教、经济和文化束缚而努力奋斗,因此,他可以被正确地称为民族主义的缩影或真正的民族主义者。在本文中,我将重点介绍他为国家和全人类所做的奉献和贡献,并证明他是一名真正的民族主义者。
{"title":"Swami Vivekananda: An Epitome of Nationalism","authors":"Lakshman Patra","doi":"10.1007/s40961-024-00324-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-024-00324-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>What we understand by nationalism is the idea of supporting one’s country, people, culture and sovereignty of the nation. It believes in self-rule, with an objective to maintain the national unity and solidarity. It also encourages pride in national achievements and is closely linked with patriotism. One who dedicates his life to promoting the above objectives for the glory of his nation is considered as a nationalist. Swami Vivekananda who has dedicated his short, but meaningful life for the upliftment of his fellow country-men and worked hard for the freedom of his motherland from political, religious, economic and cultural bondage, for which he can rightly be called an epitome of nationalism or a true nationalist. In this article, I shall focus on his dedications and contributions for his nation and human race at large and justify him to be called a true nationalist.</p>","PeriodicalId":41227,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research","volume":"15 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2024-02-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139771018","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1