首页 > 最新文献

The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series最新文献

英文 中文
Morality and Everyday Life 道德与日常生活
Pub Date : 2000-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA201396
Barbara Herman
{"title":"Morality and Everyday Life","authors":"Barbara Herman","doi":"10.5840/APAPA201396","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA201396","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2000-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"116238318","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 23
We Can Act Only Under the Idea of Freedom 我们只有在自由的理念下才能行动
Pub Date : 1997-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA201372
H. Allison
In his address to the Pacific Division last year, Barry Stroud called attention both to the ubiquity of appeals to naturalism in the contemporary philosophical arena and the lack of anything approaching a consensus concerning the meaning of the term.' As he noted, the varieties of naturalism run the gamut from highly restrictive forms, such as physicalism and naturalized epistemology, which are exceedingly controversial, to more inclusive forms, which preserve their popularity by avoiding a commitment to anything recognizably "naturalistic" beyond the rejection of appeals to the super-natural. In the case of the latter forms, Stroud remarks sensibly, the term 'naturalism' is often reduced to an empty slogan, which could more appropriately be rendered by 'open-mindedness.'2 There is, however, at least one central area of philosophical inquiry where naturalism is not only alive and well but has a fairly determinate sense, namely the question of free will or agency. In spite of an ongoing debate around the edges of this topic, for some time the ruling orthodoxy has been a form of compatibilism that is naturalistic in the sense that it dismisses any account of agency that is not positively related to the framework of nomological explanation operative in the natural sciences. For upholders of this point of view, action descriptions may have their own language (that of reasons) and need not be reducible to physicalistic or neurophysiological accounts; but at the end of the day these descriptions must be mappable on to the causal order of nature, which, in contemporary terms, is usually thought to involve either token-token identity or supervenience.3 Moreover, there appears to be much in favor of this approach, since human beings are parts of nature and their intentional actions can be regarded as events in the natural order, even if, considered as actions, they are taken under different descriptions. Nevertheless, not all philosophers have been willing to accept this naturalized conception of agency, which, in one form or another, has been with us at least since the 17th century. One who did not is Immanuel Kant, and it is his views that I shall discuss tonight. My main text will be Kant's famous remark in the Groundwork that "to every rational being possessed of a will we must also lend the Idea of freedom as the only one under which he can act."4 In his metaphysical lectures he makes essentially the same point by claiming that, "Freedom is a mere Idea and to act according to this Idea is what it means to be free in the practical sense." And he adds that, "Freedom...is practically necessary-man must therefore act according to an Idea of freedom, and he cannot act otherwise."5
在去年的太平洋分部演讲中,巴里·斯特劳德(Barry Stroud)呼吁人们注意当代哲学舞台上对自然主义的普遍诉求,以及对该术语的含义缺乏任何接近共识的东西。正如他所指出的,自然主义的各种形式从高度限制的形式,如物理主义和自然化认识论,这些形式极具争议,到更包容的形式,这些形式通过避免承诺任何可识别的“自然主义”而保持其受欢迎程度,除了拒绝对超自然的呼吁。斯特劳德明智地指出,在后一种形式中,“自然主义”一词经常被简化为空洞的口号,可以更恰当地用“开放思想”来表达。然而,至少有一个哲学研究的中心领域,自然主义不仅活跃,而且具有相当确定的意义,即自由意志或能动性的问题。尽管围绕这一主题的边缘存在着持续的争论,但一段时间以来,主流的正统观点一直是一种自然主义的相容主义形式,即它否定了任何与自然科学中运作的法理学解释框架没有积极联系的代理解释。对于持这种观点的人来说,行为描述可能有自己的语言(理由的语言),不需要简化为物理主义或神经生理学的描述;但在一天结束时,这些描述必须映射到自然的因果秩序,这在当代术语中通常被认为涉及标记-标记身份或监督此外,似乎有很多人赞成这种方法,因为人类是自然的一部分,他们的有意行为可以被视为自然秩序中的事件,即使被视为行动,它们是在不同的描述下发生的。然而,并不是所有的哲学家都愿意接受这种自然化的代理概念,这种概念至少从17世纪以来就以这样或那样的形式出现在我们身边。伊曼努尔·康德不这么认为,今晚我将讨论他的观点。我的主要文本将是康德在《基础》中的著名评论,“对于每一个拥有意志的理性个体,我们也必须赋予自由的理念,作为他唯一能够行动的理念。”在他的形而上学讲座中,他在本质上也提出了同样的观点,他说:“自由不过是一种理念,按照这种理念行动,即是实践意义上的自由。”他还补充道:“自由……因此,人必须按照自由的理念行动,否则他就不能行动。“5
{"title":"We Can Act Only Under the Idea of Freedom","authors":"H. Allison","doi":"10.5840/APAPA201372","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA201372","url":null,"abstract":"In his address to the Pacific Division last year, Barry Stroud called attention both to the ubiquity of appeals to naturalism in the contemporary philosophical arena and the lack of anything approaching a consensus concerning the meaning of the term.' As he noted, the varieties of naturalism run the gamut from highly restrictive forms, such as physicalism and naturalized epistemology, which are exceedingly controversial, to more inclusive forms, which preserve their popularity by avoiding a commitment to anything recognizably \"naturalistic\" beyond the rejection of appeals to the super-natural. In the case of the latter forms, Stroud remarks sensibly, the term 'naturalism' is often reduced to an empty slogan, which could more appropriately be rendered by 'open-mindedness.'2 There is, however, at least one central area of philosophical inquiry where naturalism is not only alive and well but has a fairly determinate sense, namely the question of free will or agency. In spite of an ongoing debate around the edges of this topic, for some time the ruling orthodoxy has been a form of compatibilism that is naturalistic in the sense that it dismisses any account of agency that is not positively related to the framework of nomological explanation operative in the natural sciences. For upholders of this point of view, action descriptions may have their own language (that of reasons) and need not be reducible to physicalistic or neurophysiological accounts; but at the end of the day these descriptions must be mappable on to the causal order of nature, which, in contemporary terms, is usually thought to involve either token-token identity or supervenience.3 Moreover, there appears to be much in favor of this approach, since human beings are parts of nature and their intentional actions can be regarded as events in the natural order, even if, considered as actions, they are taken under different descriptions. Nevertheless, not all philosophers have been willing to accept this naturalized conception of agency, which, in one form or another, has been with us at least since the 17th century. One who did not is Immanuel Kant, and it is his views that I shall discuss tonight. My main text will be Kant's famous remark in the Groundwork that \"to every rational being possessed of a will we must also lend the Idea of freedom as the only one under which he can act.\"4 In his metaphysical lectures he makes essentially the same point by claiming that, \"Freedom is a mere Idea and to act according to this Idea is what it means to be free in the practical sense.\" And he adds that, \"Freedom...is practically necessary-man must therefore act according to an Idea of freedom, and he cannot act otherwise.\"5","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"138 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1997-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127015919","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 21
Voluntarism and the Foundations of Ethics 唯意志论与伦理学基础
Pub Date : 1996-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA201357
J. Schneewind
{"title":"Voluntarism and the Foundations of Ethics","authors":"J. Schneewind","doi":"10.5840/APAPA201357","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA201357","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"47 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1996-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127885739","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 33
EMPATHY, MIND, AND MORALS 同理心,心智和道德
Pub Date : 1992-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA201321
A. Goldman
Early Greek philosophers doubled as natural scientists; that is a commonplace. It is equally true, though less often remarked, that numerous historical philosophers doubled as cognitive scientists. They constructed models of mental faculties in much the spirit of modern cognitive science, for which they are widely cited as precursors in the cognitive science literature. Today, of course, there is more emphasis on experiment, and greater division of labor. Philosophers focus on theory, foundations, and methodology, while cognitive scientists are absorbed by experimental techniques and findings. Nonetheless, there are sound reasons for massive communication between philosophy and cognitive science, which happily proceeds apace. On this occasion I shall not try to enumerate or delineate these lines of communication in any comprehensive fashion. I just wish to illustrate the benefits to philosophy in two domains: the theory of mind and moral theory. Though this may sound like an ambitious agenda, I shall in fact examine just a single phenomenon: empathy. Using that term first broadly and later narrowly, I shall argue that empathy may be the key to one sector of the philosophy of mind and to several sectors of moral theory. But whether empathy can in fact unlock any doors depends heavily on the outcome of empirical research in cognitive science.
早期希腊哲学家兼做自然科学家;这是老生常谈。同样真实的是,尽管很少有人注意到,许多历史哲学家兼做认知科学家。他们在很大程度上以现代认知科学的精神构建了心智能力模型,因此他们被广泛引用为认知科学文献中的先驱。当然,今天更强调实验,分工也更大。哲学家专注于理论、基础和方法论,而认知科学家则专注于实验技术和发现。尽管如此,哲学和认知科学之间有充分的理由进行大规模的交流,这种交流令人愉快地迅速进行。在此,我不打算以任何全面的方式列举或描述这些交流方式。我只想说明哲学在两个领域的好处:心智理论和道德理论。虽然这听起来像是一个雄心勃勃的议程,但我实际上只会研究一个现象:同理心。先从广义上,后从狭义上使用这个术语,我认为移情可能是心灵哲学的一个领域和道德理论的几个领域的关键。但同理心是否真的能打开任何一扇门,在很大程度上取决于认知科学实证研究的结果。
{"title":"EMPATHY, MIND, AND MORALS","authors":"A. Goldman","doi":"10.5840/APAPA201321","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA201321","url":null,"abstract":"Early Greek philosophers doubled as natural scientists; that is a commonplace. It is equally true, though less often remarked, that numerous historical philosophers doubled as cognitive scientists. They constructed models of mental faculties in much the spirit of modern cognitive science, for which they are widely cited as precursors in the cognitive science literature. Today, of course, there is more emphasis on experiment, and greater division of labor. Philosophers focus on theory, foundations, and methodology, while cognitive scientists are absorbed by experimental techniques and findings. Nonetheless, there are sound reasons for massive communication between philosophy and cognitive science, which happily proceeds apace. On this occasion I shall not try to enumerate or delineate these lines of communication in any comprehensive fashion. I just wish to illustrate the benefits to philosophy in two domains: the theory of mind and moral theory. Though this may sound like an ambitious agenda, I shall in fact examine just a single phenomenon: empathy. Using that term first broadly and later narrowly, I shall argue that empathy may be the key to one sector of the philosophy of mind and to several sectors of moral theory. But whether empathy can in fact unlock any doors depends heavily on the outcome of empirical research in cognitive science.","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"102 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1992-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"117271178","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 220
A Naturalist View of Persons 自然主义者对人的看法
Pub Date : 1991-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA201310
A. Baier
{"title":"A Naturalist View of Persons","authors":"A. Baier","doi":"10.5840/APAPA201310","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA201310","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"23 2","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1991-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132364255","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 15
Is the Brain a Digital Computer 大脑是一台数字计算机吗
Pub Date : 1990-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA2013194
J. Searle
I will be addressing 1 and not 2 or 3. I think 2 can be decisively answered in the negative. Since programs are defined purely formally or syntactically and since minds have an intrinsic mental content, it follows immediately that the program by itself cannot constitute the mind. The formal syntax of the program does not by itself guarantee the presence of mental contents. I showed this a decade ago in the Chinese Room Argument (Searle,1980). A computer, me for example, could run the steps in the program for some mental capacity, such as understanding Chinese, without understanding a word of Chinese. The argument rests on the simple logical truth that syntax is not the same as, nor is it by itself sufficient for, semantics. So the answer to the second question is obviously "No".
我将处理1,而不是2或3。我认为可以肯定地回答是否定的。既然程序是纯粹形式上或句法上定义的,既然心灵有内在的精神意旨,那么立即可以得出结论,程序本身不能构成心灵。程序的形式语法本身并不能保证心智内容的存在。我在十年前的“中文房间论证”(Searle,1980)中展示了这一点。以我为例,一台电脑可以在不懂中文的情况下运行程序中的步骤,以提高一些脑力,比如理解中文。这个论点建立在一个简单的逻辑真理之上,即语法不等同于语义,它本身也不足以满足语义。所以第二个问题的答案显然是否定的。
{"title":"Is the Brain a Digital Computer","authors":"J. Searle","doi":"10.5840/APAPA2013194","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA2013194","url":null,"abstract":"I will be addressing 1 and not 2 or 3. I think 2 can be decisively answered in the negative. Since programs are defined purely formally or syntactically and since minds have an intrinsic mental content, it follows immediately that the program by itself cannot constitute the mind. The formal syntax of the program does not by itself guarantee the presence of mental contents. I showed this a decade ago in the Chinese Room Argument (Searle,1980). A computer, me for example, could run the steps in the program for some mental capacity, such as understanding Chinese, without understanding a word of Chinese. The argument rests on the simple logical truth that syntax is not the same as, nor is it by itself sufficient for, semantics. So the answer to the second question is obviously \"No\".","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"12 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1990-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115358738","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 273
Freedom of Will and Freedom of Action 意志自由与行动自由
Pub Date : 1985-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA2013150
Rogers Albritton
Descartes held that the will is perfectly free, "so free in its nature that it cannot be constrained."2 "Let everyone just go down deep into himself," he is reported to have said to Frans Burman, "and find out whether or not he has a perfect and absolute will, and whether he can conceive of anything which surpasses him in freedom of the will. I am sure that everyone will find that it is as I say."3 Not everyone has so found, and one might think: "No wonder! We aren't gods. How could our wills not have their limits, like our digestions? Don't we quite often--or occasionally, at a minimum-have no freedom of will, in some matter or other? And mustn't it be like that? Whatever the will is, or was, mustn't it, under whatever name or names, be good for something? And in our case, mustn't it be something in the world that the will is good for? But if so, its freedom can't be perfect and unconditional. What in the world, that might reasonably be called a freedom, could be so absolute? If the will in the world were some faculty, say, of never mind what, wouldn't it be possible somehow to restrict its exercise? How could that be impossible? No doubt we're free as birds. We know it, God knows how, or as good as know it. Or better than know it, as perhaps we better than know that twice two is four. But how free are birds? Let no bird preen itself on its freedom. There are cages. There are tamers of birds. There's a lesson in birds, namely that a certain modesty about our famous freedom is very much in order, in the order of nature to which we so palpably belong." One might think something like that. Nevertheless, I am inclined to agree with Descartes. And of course I have some company. Foreigners, mostly, but there it is. Not much company, however, as far as I know. Most philosophers seem to think it quite easy to rob the will of some freedom. Thus Elizabeth Anscombe, in an essay called "Soft Determinism," appears to suppose that a man who can't walk because he is chained up has lost some freedom of will. He "has no 'freedom of will' to walk," she says, or, again; no "freedom of the will in respect of walking."4 "Everyone will allow," she says, "that 'A can walk, i.e. has freedom of the will in respect of walking' would be gainsaid by A's being chained up."5 And again, "External constraint is generally agreed to be incompatible with freedom",6 by which she seems to mean: incompatible with perfect freedom of will, because incompatible with freedom of will to do, or freedom of the will in respect of doing, whatever the constraint prevents.
笛卡尔认为,意志是完全自由的,“其本质是如此自由,以至于不能受到约束。”据报道,他曾对弗朗斯·伯曼(Frans Burman)说:“让每个人都深入自己的内心,看看自己是否有一个完美的、绝对的意志,以及他是否能想象出任何超越他的自由意志。”我相信每个人都会发现这就是我所说的。并不是每个人都有这样的发现,有人可能会想:“难怪!”我们不是神。我们的意志怎么可能没有极限,就像我们的消化系统一样?我们不是经常——或者至少偶尔——在某些事情上没有意志的自由吗?难道不应该是这样吗?不管遗嘱是什么,或者曾经是什么,它一定不能以任何名义,做点好事吗?在我们的例子中,难道意志不应该是对世界有益的吗?但如果是这样,它的自由就不可能是完美和无条件的。世界上有什么可以合理地称为自由的东西,可以如此绝对?如果世界上的意志是某种能力,不管它是什么,难道不可能以某种方式限制它的行使吗?这怎么可能呢?毫无疑问,我们像鸟儿一样自由。我们知道,天知道是怎么知道的,或者就像知道一样。或者比知道它更好,就像我们不知道2乘以2等于4一样。但是鸟类有多自由呢?不要让鸟儿以自由来炫耀自己。有笼子。有驯兽师。从鸟类身上我们可以得到一个教训,那就是对我们著名的自由保持一定的谦虚,这是很有必要的,在我们显然属于的自然秩序中。”有人可能会这样想。然而,我倾向于同意笛卡尔的观点。当然我也有同伴。大部分是外国人,但就是这样。不过,据我所知,并没有多少同伴。大多数哲学家似乎认为剥夺意志的某种自由是很容易的。因此,伊丽莎白·安斯库姆在一篇名为《软决定论》的文章中似乎认为,一个因为被锁住而不能走路的人已经失去了一些意志自由。他“没有行走的‘自由意志’,”她又说;没有"行走的意志自由"“每个人都会承认,”她说,“‘A可以行走,也就是说,A有行走的自由意志’会因为A被锁起来而被否定。”5再一次,"外界约束被普遍认为与自由不相容" 6她的意思似乎是:与完全的意志自由不相容,因为与行动的意志自由不相容,或与行动的意志自由不相容,无论约束阻止什么。
{"title":"Freedom of Will and Freedom of Action","authors":"Rogers Albritton","doi":"10.5840/APAPA2013150","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA2013150","url":null,"abstract":"Descartes held that the will is perfectly free, \"so free in its nature that it cannot be constrained.\"2 \"Let everyone just go down deep into himself,\" he is reported to have said to Frans Burman, \"and find out whether or not he has a perfect and absolute will, and whether he can conceive of anything which surpasses him in freedom of the will. I am sure that everyone will find that it is as I say.\"3 Not everyone has so found, and one might think: \"No wonder! We aren't gods. How could our wills not have their limits, like our digestions? Don't we quite often--or occasionally, at a minimum-have no freedom of will, in some matter or other? And mustn't it be like that? Whatever the will is, or was, mustn't it, under whatever name or names, be good for something? And in our case, mustn't it be something in the world that the will is good for? But if so, its freedom can't be perfect and unconditional. What in the world, that might reasonably be called a freedom, could be so absolute? If the will in the world were some faculty, say, of never mind what, wouldn't it be possible somehow to restrict its exercise? How could that be impossible? No doubt we're free as birds. We know it, God knows how, or as good as know it. Or better than know it, as perhaps we better than know that twice two is four. But how free are birds? Let no bird preen itself on its freedom. There are cages. There are tamers of birds. There's a lesson in birds, namely that a certain modesty about our famous freedom is very much in order, in the order of nature to which we so palpably belong.\" One might think something like that. Nevertheless, I am inclined to agree with Descartes. And of course I have some company. Foreigners, mostly, but there it is. Not much company, however, as far as I know. Most philosophers seem to think it quite easy to rob the will of some freedom. Thus Elizabeth Anscombe, in an essay called \"Soft Determinism,\" appears to suppose that a man who can't walk because he is chained up has lost some freedom of will. He \"has no 'freedom of will' to walk,\" she says, or, again; no \"freedom of the will in respect of walking.\"4 \"Everyone will allow,\" she says, \"that 'A can walk, i.e. has freedom of the will in respect of walking' would be gainsaid by A's being chained up.\"5 And again, \"External constraint is generally agreed to be incompatible with freedom\",6 by which she seems to mean: incompatible with perfect freedom of will, because incompatible with freedom of will to do, or freedom of the will in respect of doing, whatever the constraint prevents.","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1985-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133575575","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 30
Things in Themselves 事物本身
Pub Date : 1983-09-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA2013135
Manley Thompson
You may guess from my title that I am going to talk a good deal this evening about the philosophy of Immanuel Kant. While the guess is correct in that I will make frequent reference to Kant's writings and occasionally quote some of his remarks, I want to emphasize at the start that my primary concern is not that of a Kant scholar urging an interpretation of Kant. My concern is rather with epistemology and the approach to it that gives rise to the Kantian notion of a thing in itself. In my efforts to clarify this approach I will contrast it with others, and I will say quite a bit about the views of C.S. Peirce. When I speak of the approach as Kantian, I am not concerned to argue that it is the approach Kant himself always followed, but only that it is the one we should follow if we begin in epistemology as Kant did. For those of you who have a special interest in Kant's moral philosophy, let me add now that I distinguish sharply between the role of a thing in itself in epistemology and its role in Kant's moral philosophy. I comment briefly on this distinction near the end of my paper.
你们可以从我的题目中猜到,今晚我要讲很多关于伊曼努尔·康德哲学的内容。虽然我的猜测是正确的,因为我将经常引用康德的著作,偶尔引用他的一些评论,但我想在一开始就强调,我主要关心的不是康德学者对康德的解释。我更关心的是认识论和它的方法,它产生了康德的物自体概念。在我努力阐明这一观点的过程中,我会将其与其他观点进行对比,并且我会对C.S.皮尔斯的观点进行相当多的阐述。当我说康德的方法时,我并不是说这是康德自己一直遵循的方法,而只是说,如果我们像康德那样从认识论开始,这是我们应该遵循的方法。对于那些对康德道德哲学特别感兴趣的人,我想补充一点,我对认识论中事物本身的作用和康德道德哲学中的作用有明确的区分。我在论文的末尾简要地评论了这一区别。
{"title":"Things in Themselves","authors":"Manley Thompson","doi":"10.5840/APAPA2013135","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA2013135","url":null,"abstract":"You may guess from my title that I am going to talk a good deal this evening about the philosophy of Immanuel Kant. While the guess is correct in that I will make frequent reference to Kant's writings and occasionally quote some of his remarks, I want to emphasize at the start that my primary concern is not that of a Kant scholar urging an interpretation of Kant. My concern is rather with epistemology and the approach to it that gives rise to the Kantian notion of a thing in itself. In my efforts to clarify this approach I will contrast it with others, and I will say quite a bit about the views of C.S. Peirce. When I speak of the approach as Kantian, I am not concerned to argue that it is the approach Kant himself always followed, but only that it is the one we should follow if we begin in epistemology as Kant did. For those of you who have a special interest in Kant's moral philosophy, let me add now that I distinguish sharply between the role of a thing in itself in epistemology and its role in Kant's moral philosophy. I comment briefly on this distinction near the end of my paper.","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"14 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1983-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114780654","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The New Need for a Recovery of Philosophy 哲学复兴的新需要
Pub Date : 1982-09-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA2013120
J. Smith
{"title":"The New Need for a Recovery of Philosophy","authors":"J. Smith","doi":"10.5840/APAPA2013120","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA2013120","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"53 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1982-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132138402","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Epistemic Merit, Intrinsic and Instrumental 认识价值,内在的和工具的
Pub Date : 1981-09-01 DOI: 10.5840/APAPA2013111
R. Firth
Philosophers today are deeply divided by issues of a kind that can be described as "metaepistemological" -issues concerning the concepts and methodology appropriate for a philosophical investigation of human knowledge. In thinking about some of these controversial issues it seems to me helpful to draw a distinction between two kinds of epistemic merit intrinsic and instrumental. There are many things that can possess epistemic merit: educational practices, methods of scientific inquiry, moral and religious doctrines, constitutional provisions for freedom of speech and inquiry, and so on indefinitely. But I shall be talking today about the epistemic merit of propositional attitudes; and for simplicity I shall concentrate attention on just one of these, the attitude we have toward a proposition in believing it. What I shall have to say about the epistemic merit of believing can easily be extended to other attitudes like disbelieving, suspending judgment, assuming for the sake of the argument, accepting subject to further investigation, and so
今天的哲学家被一种可以被描述为“元认识论”的问题深深地分裂了,这些问题涉及对人类知识进行哲学研究的概念和方法论。在思考这些有争议的问题时,对我来说,区分两种认知价值是有帮助的内在价值和工具价值。有许多东西可以具有认识论的价值:教育实践、科学探究的方法、道德和宗教教义、关于言论和探究自由的宪法规定等等。但今天我要讲的是命题态度的认识论价值;为了简单起见,我将把注意力集中在其中的一个,即我们在相信一个命题时对它所持的态度。我要说的关于相信的认识论价值可以很容易地扩展到其他的态度,比如不相信,暂停判断,为了论证而假设,接受进一步调查的对象,等等
{"title":"Epistemic Merit, Intrinsic and Instrumental","authors":"R. Firth","doi":"10.5840/APAPA2013111","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA2013111","url":null,"abstract":"Philosophers today are deeply divided by issues of a kind that can be described as \"metaepistemological\" -issues concerning the concepts and methodology appropriate for a philosophical investigation of human knowledge. In thinking about some of these controversial issues it seems to me helpful to draw a distinction between two kinds of epistemic merit intrinsic and instrumental. There are many things that can possess epistemic merit: educational practices, methods of scientific inquiry, moral and religious doctrines, constitutional provisions for freedom of speech and inquiry, and so on indefinitely. But I shall be talking today about the epistemic merit of propositional attitudes; and for simplicity I shall concentrate attention on just one of these, the attitude we have toward a proposition in believing it. What I shall have to say about the epistemic merit of believing can easily be extended to other attitudes like disbelieving, suspending judgment, assuming for the sake of the argument, accepting subject to further investigation, and so","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"81 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1981-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128799386","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 24
期刊
The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1