首页 > 最新文献

Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology最新文献

英文 中文
How to Measure Depression: Looking Back on the Making of Psychiatric Assessment 如何测量抑郁症:回顾精神病学评估的制定
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908275
Philippe Le Moigne
Abstract: This article discusses the way how change in depressed patients included in clinical trials was both conceptualized and measured in the 1970s to decide on the efficacy of the first candidate drugs for the treatment of depression. Understanding how this issue was resolved is of major interest as the protocol designed to distinguish the diagnosis of the depressive syndrome from the measurement of its evolution over time built the contours of the methodological device to which the whole of standardized evaluation in psychiatry has since referred. This paper draws on the debates in nascent psychopharmacology in both the United States and Europe and examines the protocols and findings of the research programs on depression the National Institute of Mental Health (NIMH) has developed in the United States at the same time, as well as on the writings of the main authors of the standardized evaluation. This investigation suggests that measurement of patients’ improvement could not be characterized on the basis of psychiatric inventories that were not well-suited to quantification, nor on the basis of psychometric tests which were intended for the evaluation of psychological invariants. This is why the answer given to the characterization of change in depression under therapy rather reveals a syncretism both conceptual and technical, mixing classificatory and psychometric traditions, a syncretism that the distinction endorsed by the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders , 3rd edition,between syndromes and personality disorders no longer allows us to perceive.
摘要:本文讨论了20世纪70年代临床试验中抑郁症患者的变化是如何被概念化和测量的,以确定第一批治疗抑郁症的候选药物的疗效。理解这个问题是如何解决的是一个重要的兴趣,因为该协议旨在区分抑郁综合征的诊断与测量其随时间的演变,建立了方法学设备的轮廓,整个精神病学的标准化评估从此被提及。本文借鉴了美国和欧洲新兴精神药理学的争论,并考察了美国国家精神卫生研究所(NIMH)同时在美国开展的抑郁症研究项目的协议和发现,以及标准化评估主要作者的著作。这项调查表明,对患者改善的测量不能基于不适合量化的精神病学调查,也不能基于旨在评估心理不变量的心理测量测试。这就是为什么对治疗下抑郁症变化特征的回答揭示了一种概念和技术上的融合,混合了分类和心理测量传统,这种融合被第三版《精神疾病诊断和统计手册》所认可,综合症和人格障碍之间的区别不再允许我们感知。
{"title":"How to Measure Depression: Looking Back on the Making of Psychiatric Assessment","authors":"Philippe Le Moigne","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908275","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908275","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract: This article discusses the way how change in depressed patients included in clinical trials was both conceptualized and measured in the 1970s to decide on the efficacy of the first candidate drugs for the treatment of depression. Understanding how this issue was resolved is of major interest as the protocol designed to distinguish the diagnosis of the depressive syndrome from the measurement of its evolution over time built the contours of the methodological device to which the whole of standardized evaluation in psychiatry has since referred. This paper draws on the debates in nascent psychopharmacology in both the United States and Europe and examines the protocols and findings of the research programs on depression the National Institute of Mental Health (NIMH) has developed in the United States at the same time, as well as on the writings of the main authors of the standardized evaluation. This investigation suggests that measurement of patients’ improvement could not be characterized on the basis of psychiatric inventories that were not well-suited to quantification, nor on the basis of psychometric tests which were intended for the evaluation of psychological invariants. This is why the answer given to the characterization of change in depression under therapy rather reveals a syncretism both conceptual and technical, mixing classificatory and psychometric traditions, a syncretism that the distinction endorsed by the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders , 3rd edition,between syndromes and personality disorders no longer allows us to perceive.","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588171","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Psychodramatic Psychotherapy for Schizophrenic Individuals 精神分裂症患者的心理戏剧心理治疗
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908273
John Nolte
Psychodramatic Psychotherapy for Schizophrenic Individuals John Nolte, MD, PhD (bio) As a long-time student, practitioner, trainer, author and advocate of J. L. Moreno, MD,’s works and specifically the psychodramatic method, I am always appreciative of efforts, like Chapy’s, to commend and advocate for psychodrama. This is especially so because for a time, Moreno and psychodrama were heavily criticized, even maligned in the mental health professions. At the same time, considering how poorly Moreno and his methods have been understood as well as the difficulty of accessing his original material, I feel an obligation to set the record straight when confronted with incomplete, inadequate, or sometimes incompetent expositions of Moreno’s psychodrama. Chapy’s article recommends psychodrama as a treatment method for schizophrenic people by calling upon existentialist and phenomenological concepts. Psychodrama, he proposes, opens up existence by allowing “schizophrenic patients to incorporate the experience of an ‘absolutely other.’” There are major flaws in Chapy’s presentation. His “clinical illustration,” the presentation of a psychodrama with a schizophrenic patient, while it may be considered psychodrama under the broadest definition of the term, hardly fulfills the requirements of a psychotherapeutic psychodrama. We must question the competence of the psychodramatist in Chapy’s example. Chapy’s description of the drama itself falls short of being an adequate account of a psychodrama, failing to convey the emotional intensity and realness which a well directed and reported psychodrama achieves. We do not learn, for example, if Damien’s perception of his father is introduced through role reversal with the father, a standard psychodramatic technique which is done in order to give the auxiliary ego taking that role an understanding how Damien experiences his father. We do not know if role reversals are made throughout the drama so that Damien can experience how he is perceived by father, can feel the force of his confrontation in the role of father, and is required to reply as his father to his confrontation. We are given little information about the psychodramatic techniques employed by the director other than the scene setting of the studio in which the psychodramatic [End Page 227] encounter takes place, and the soliloquy in which Damien expresses his worry and hopes for the outcome of the confrontation. It should be clear in the description of the drama whether the father’s statements in the drama were produced by Damien in role reversal, or by the auxiliary ego playing the role. There is a difference and it is significant. Although we are told that Damien “evokes a systematic relationship between him and his father” during the psychodrama, we do not see how this happens. Every psychodrama is an existential experience and its description should fully communicate its meaning and emotion. A more serious problem, however, is that this drama does not
约翰·诺尔特,医学博士,生物博士作为j.l.莫雷诺医学博士的长期学生、实践者、培训师、作者和倡导者,尤其是心理戏剧方法,我一直很欣赏像查皮那样赞扬和倡导心理戏剧的努力。这一点尤其重要,因为有一段时间,莫雷诺和心理剧在心理健康专业领域受到了严厉的批评,甚至是诽谤。与此同时,考虑到莫雷诺和他的方法被理解得多么糟糕,以及获取他的原始材料的难度,当面对莫雷诺心理剧不完整、不充分或有时不称职的解释时,我觉得有义务澄清事实。Chapy的文章通过调用存在主义和现象学概念,推荐心理剧作为精神分裂症患者的治疗方法。他提出,心理剧通过允许“精神分裂症患者融入‘绝对的他者’的经历”来打开存在。’”查皮的陈述存在重大缺陷。他的“临床例证”,一个精神分裂症患者的心理剧的呈现,虽然在最广泛的术语定义下它可能被认为是心理剧,但很难满足心理治疗心理剧的要求。我们必须质疑查皮的例子中心理剧作家的能力。查皮对这部剧本身的描述不够充分,未能传达出一部导演精良、报道良好的心理剧所达到的情感强度和真实性。例如,我们不知道,达米恩对父亲的看法是否通过与父亲的角色互换来引入,这是一种标准的心理戏剧技巧,它的目的是让扮演这个角色的辅助自我理解达米恩对父亲的看法。我们不知道整部戏剧是否进行了角色转换,以便达米安能够体验到父亲是如何看待他的,能够感受到他在父亲角色中对抗的力量,并被要求以父亲的身份回应他的对抗。除了心理戏剧(End Page 227)相遇发生的工作室场景设置,以及达米安表达他对冲突结果的担忧和希望的独白之外,我们几乎没有得到关于导演所使用的心理戏剧技巧的信息。在对戏剧的描述中,应该明确戏剧中父亲的陈述是由达米安在角色反转中产生的,还是由扮演角色的辅助自我产生的。这是有区别的,而且是显著的。虽然我们被告知,在心理剧中,达米安“唤起了他和他父亲之间的系统关系”,但我们没有看到这是如何发生的。每一部心理剧都是一种存在体验,它的描述应该充分传达它的意义和情感。然而,一个更严重的问题是,这部剧并没有处理达米安的精神病。虽然达米安可能被诊断为精神分裂症,但他的疾病明显处于缓解期,或受到精神药物的控制。这部剧没有表现出精神分裂症所特有的幻觉、妄想或紊乱。这可能是任何一个抱怨父亲的年轻人的心理剧。精神分裂症患者可以通过心理剧成功治疗的观点并不新鲜。莫雷诺在1936年建立的比肯山疗养院开始发展心理戏剧心理疗法。他和心理剧获得了一些名声,因为他成功地治疗了精神分裂症患者,而当时人们认为精神分裂症患者无法从心理治疗中获益。莫雷诺治疗精神分裂症患者的方法比查皮描述的心理剧要有力得多。在精神病发作期间,个体对世界和自我的感知被扭曲,使传统现实世界中的行动和互动变得不可能。此外,精神病发作使精神病患者无法被其他人理解,包括精神科医生。莫雷诺的解决方案是,在心理戏剧舞台的过剩现实中,让混乱、困惑、有时暴力、总是可怕的内心世界变得可见和有形。在精神病发作后的清醒时刻,他让他的精神分裂症患者重现他们的精神病经历。结果是,“在心理戏剧舞台上想象的现实中,……
{"title":"Psychodramatic Psychotherapy for Schizophrenic Individuals","authors":"John Nolte","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908273","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908273","url":null,"abstract":"Psychodramatic Psychotherapy for Schizophrenic Individuals John Nolte, MD, PhD (bio) As a long-time student, practitioner, trainer, author and advocate of J. L. Moreno, MD,’s works and specifically the psychodramatic method, I am always appreciative of efforts, like Chapy’s, to commend and advocate for psychodrama. This is especially so because for a time, Moreno and psychodrama were heavily criticized, even maligned in the mental health professions. At the same time, considering how poorly Moreno and his methods have been understood as well as the difficulty of accessing his original material, I feel an obligation to set the record straight when confronted with incomplete, inadequate, or sometimes incompetent expositions of Moreno’s psychodrama. Chapy’s article recommends psychodrama as a treatment method for schizophrenic people by calling upon existentialist and phenomenological concepts. Psychodrama, he proposes, opens up existence by allowing “schizophrenic patients to incorporate the experience of an ‘absolutely other.’” There are major flaws in Chapy’s presentation. His “clinical illustration,” the presentation of a psychodrama with a schizophrenic patient, while it may be considered psychodrama under the broadest definition of the term, hardly fulfills the requirements of a psychotherapeutic psychodrama. We must question the competence of the psychodramatist in Chapy’s example. Chapy’s description of the drama itself falls short of being an adequate account of a psychodrama, failing to convey the emotional intensity and realness which a well directed and reported psychodrama achieves. We do not learn, for example, if Damien’s perception of his father is introduced through role reversal with the father, a standard psychodramatic technique which is done in order to give the auxiliary ego taking that role an understanding how Damien experiences his father. We do not know if role reversals are made throughout the drama so that Damien can experience how he is perceived by father, can feel the force of his confrontation in the role of father, and is required to reply as his father to his confrontation. We are given little information about the psychodramatic techniques employed by the director other than the scene setting of the studio in which the psychodramatic [End Page 227] encounter takes place, and the soliloquy in which Damien expresses his worry and hopes for the outcome of the confrontation. It should be clear in the description of the drama whether the father’s statements in the drama were produced by Damien in role reversal, or by the auxiliary ego playing the role. There is a difference and it is significant. Although we are told that Damien “evokes a systematic relationship between him and his father” during the psychodrama, we do not see how this happens. Every psychodrama is an existential experience and its description should fully communicate its meaning and emotion. A more serious problem, however, is that this drama does not ","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"65 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588250","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
About the Authors 关于作者
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908281
{"title":"About the Authors","authors":"","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908281","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908281","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"8 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588253","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Close Enemies: The Relationship of Psychiatry and Psychology in the Assessment of Mental Disorders 亲密的敌人:精神病学和心理学在精神障碍评估中的关系
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908278
Philippe Le Moigne
A s Peter Zachar rightly points out in his comment, the assessment of mental disorders underwent new developments with the release of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders-V in 2013 (American Psychiatric Association , 2013). Whereas in 1980, the manual had been thought of in a rigorously categorical way, on the basis of distinct and closed syndromic entities, this new version advocated the development of a radically dimensionalist approach, with the diagnosis aiming this time to restore the whole symptomatological picture of the patient on a spectrum of ratings are supposed to cover the entirety of psychiatric semiology (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). For its part, my article aimed to show how standardized assessment, guided by the return of psychiatry’s authority and the assertion of its legitimacy in the diagnostic field, gave the ascendancy in the 1980s to the classificatory tradition and thus to the categorical model, to the detriment of personality approach and test psychology which offered a competing solution here. This perspective, historically dated, may have led the reader to think that there is an antagonism that cannot be overcome here. Rather, it should be seen as a form of structuring opposition, or even a “complementarity inscribed in rivalry,” between psychiatry and psychology, which is naturally susceptible to change over time. Indeed, the reversal operated by the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders-V is not total because it cannot be total. The defense of the dimensionalist approach, dear to the psychological testing tradition, was intended here to allow the identification of co-morbidities, present in most patients but poorly apprehended by the categorical approach, and to open up diagnosis to prevention by screening for minor manifestations of psychopathology when they suggest the
正如Peter Zachar在他的评论中正确指出的那样,随着2013年《精神障碍诊断与统计手册- v》(美国精神病学协会,2013)的发布,精神障碍的评估经历了新的发展。而在1980年,该手册被认为是以严格的分类方式,基于不同的和封闭的综合征实体,这个新版本提倡一种激进的维度方法的发展,这次的诊断旨在恢复患者的整体症状,在一个应该涵盖整个精神病学符号学的评分范围内(美国精神病学协会,2013)。就其本身而言,我的文章旨在展示标准化评估是如何在精神病学权威的回归及其在诊断领域的合法性的主张的指导下,在20世纪80年代给分类传统带来了优势,从而给分类模型带来了优势,损害了人格方法和测试心理学,后者在这里提供了一个竞争性的解决方案。从历史的角度来看,这种观点可能会让读者认为这里存在着一种无法克服的对抗。相反,它应该被视为精神病学和心理学之间结构性对立的一种形式,甚至是一种“镌刻在竞争中的互补性”,它自然会随着时间的推移而改变。事实上,《精神疾病诊断与统计手册》(Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders-V)所做的逆转并非全部,因为它不可能是全部。对维度方法的辩护,对心理测试传统来说是很重要的,在这里,它的目的是允许识别共存的疾病,存在于大多数患者中,但被分类方法所忽视,并通过筛选精神病理学的轻微表现来打开诊断的预防,当它们表明[endpage 259]在或多或少的长期内发展为明显的疾病发作。这里的风险是,我们最终会过度诊断,从而导致假阳性的过度呈现(Wakefield, 2015)。换句话说,这种类型的方法并没有逃避确定阈值分数的义务,这可能表明障碍的下限,从而诉诸于分类方法。除了原则上的分歧之外,这两种观点之间有一种最初的亲缘关系,这是一种技术要求。但当我们审视它们的认识论背景时,这两种方法甚至有更多的共同点:它们都认为,用Ian Hacking(1983)的话来说,对精神障碍的表征和干预必须基于物理和自然科学提出的模型。正如Greta Kaluzeviciute在她的评论中恰当地指出的那样,这种取向导致了测量精神障碍的想法,特别是进行详细的量化操作,以确定,例如,两个实体在统计上是否不同,或者一种药物是否对病理学的演变有重大影响。事实上,这是一个古老的问题,可以用心理测量学家乔尔·米歇尔(1999)的表述表述如下:心理维度是度量的吗?换句话说,如果我们想将数字语言应用于精神障碍,它们必须共享其属性,其中两个似乎是必不可少的:必须有可能确定每种精神障碍,就像可归因于长度的品质一样,都有一个零,并且可以通过间隔为常数的梯度(或强度度)来划分(Le Moigne, 2018;米歇尔,1999)。由于篇幅有限,让我们只讨论第二个条件。从十九世纪末(1889年)柏格森开始,这一观点已经被许多人否定了。他不相信从感觉开始的心理表达的量化。他写道,感觉轻微的疼痛,就像感觉僵硬一样,和感觉一根针扎进你的肉里,这两者之间的共同点是什么?对他来说,这些强度中的一种和另一种是无法比较的,所以它们不属于一个类似的感觉记录,一个人可以从0到……
{"title":"Close Enemies: The Relationship of Psychiatry and Psychology in the Assessment of Mental Disorders","authors":"Philippe Le Moigne","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908278","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908278","url":null,"abstract":"A s Peter Zachar rightly points out in his comment, the assessment of mental disorders underwent new developments with the release of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders-V in 2013 (American Psychiatric Association , 2013). Whereas in 1980, the manual had been thought of in a rigorously categorical way, on the basis of distinct and closed syndromic entities, this new version advocated the development of a radically dimensionalist approach, with the diagnosis aiming this time to restore the whole symptomatological picture of the patient on a spectrum of ratings are supposed to cover the entirety of psychiatric semiology (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). For its part, my article aimed to show how standardized assessment, guided by the return of psychiatry’s authority and the assertion of its legitimacy in the diagnostic field, gave the ascendancy in the 1980s to the classificatory tradition and thus to the categorical model, to the detriment of personality approach and test psychology which offered a competing solution here. This perspective, historically dated, may have led the reader to think that there is an antagonism that cannot be overcome here. Rather, it should be seen as a form of structuring opposition, or even a “complementarity inscribed in rivalry,” between psychiatry and psychology, which is naturally susceptible to change over time. Indeed, the reversal operated by the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders-V is not total because it cannot be total. The defense of the dimensionalist approach, dear to the psychological testing tradition, was intended here to allow the identification of co-morbidities, present in most patients but poorly apprehended by the categorical approach, and to open up diagnosis to prevention by screening for minor manifestations of psychopathology when they suggest the","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"139 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588254","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Diagnostic Wannabes 诊断崇拜者
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908280
Jennifer Radden
Diagnostic Wannabes Jennifer Radden, PhD (bio) Saunders explores challenges for the clinician faced with self-styled sufferers from attention deficit hyperactivity disorder, post-traumatic stress disorder, bipolar disorder, autism spectrum disorder (ASD), and fibromyalgia. The diagnostic system was not meant to be used as “a scaffold for identity,” she points out. Yet wannabe patients now step into the clinic wielding self-proclaimed diagnoses as social identities. Saunders explains the context where such phenomena arise, and offers guidelines for clinicians addressing this new reality. To do so, she enlists Rashed’s innovative normative approach to the so-called boundary problem of assigning, and providing justification for, the contested line between normal and disordered. The boundary problem itself seems to rise to prominence during our current era of increasingly dimensional thinking, it is worth noting, with psychiatric diagnoses taken to refer to points on a continuum, rather than to discrete categorical disease entities. On the likely sources of these ‘diagnostic’ social identities, as well as reasons why certain diagnoses attach to them more commonly than others, Saunders points to social trends (including what she asserts to be a “post-stigma” cultural environment), the failure of efforts to identify neurobiological markers for psychiatric disorder, the ubiquity of social media, the algorithms themselves, and the hyperconnected existence of contemporary times. Such narratives also offer the comforts of a sense of belonging and explanations for perceived inadequacies, she rightly observes. Despite today’s virtual and other inducements, the problem introduced here is not an entirely new one. The first part of the seventeenth century in Europe saw an apparent “epidemic” of what was known as “melancholy,” a condition associated with the spleen, whose symptoms loosely resembled those of today’s depression and anxiety. Much of this suffering was undeniably real, but much was a fashionable, identity-conferring pose. “Every distemper of the body now is complicated with spleen,” the poet John Donne ironically observes in a letter dated 1622, “and when we were young men we scarce ever heard of the spleen. In our declinations now, every accident is accompanied with heavy clouds of melancholy”1 (Gosse, 2019). By then, the Melancholic Man (or homo melancholicus), with his surfeit of spleen, was an unmistakable character type—or social identity, as we would now say. Recognized and saluted in centuries-long literary and illustrative traditions, the type was an anchoring element of the humoral medicine which, despite the gradual emergence of more empirical science, had endured since Galenic times. Melancholy’s closest descendants, affective depressive and anxiety disorders, are today less evident among the troubling identities Saunders discusses—somewhat preempted, she points out, by more cognitively-based diagnoses such as ASD. [End Page 279] This is
詹妮弗·拉登博士(生物)桑德斯探讨了临床医生面临的挑战,这些患者自称患有注意力缺陷多动障碍、创伤后应激障碍、双相情感障碍、自闭症谱系障碍(ASD)和纤维肌痛。她指出,诊断系统并不是用来作为“身份的脚手架”。然而,想要成为患者的人现在走进诊所,把自己宣称的诊断作为社会身份。桑德斯解释了这种现象产生的背景,并为临床医生提供了解决这一新现实的指导方针。为了做到这一点,她采用了拉希德的创新规范方法来解决所谓的边界问题,即分配正常与无序之间有争议的界限,并为其提供理由。值得注意的是,边界问题本身似乎在我们当前这个维度思维日益增加的时代变得突出,精神病学诊断被认为是指连续体上的点,而不是离散的分类疾病实体。关于这些“诊断性”社会身份的可能来源,以及为什么某些诊断比其他诊断更常见的原因,桑德斯指出了社会趋势(包括她所说的“后耻辱”文化环境),识别精神障碍神经生物学标记的努力失败,无处不在的社交媒体,算法本身,以及当代的超连接存在。她正确地观察到,这样的叙述也提供了一种归属感和对感知不足的解释的安慰。尽管今天有虚拟的和其他的诱因,这里介绍的问题并不是一个全新的问题。17世纪上半叶,欧洲出现了一种被称为“忧郁”的明显“流行病”,这是一种与脾脏有关的疾病,其症状与今天的抑郁和焦虑有些相似。不可否认,这些苦难中有很多是真实的,但也有很多是一种时髦的、赋予身份的姿态。诗人约翰·多恩(John Donne)在1622年的一封信中讽刺地写道:“现在身体的每一种热症都与脾脏有关,而我们年轻时几乎从未听说过脾脏。”在我们现在的衰落中,每一次事故都伴随着沉重的忧郁的云”(Gosse, 2019)。到那时,“忧郁的人”(或“忧郁症人”),因为他的脾脏过多,是一种明确无误的性格类型——或者像我们现在所说的,是一种社会身份。在长达几个世纪的文学和插图传统中,这种类型被认可和致敬,是体液医学的一个锚定元素,尽管越来越多的经验科学逐渐出现,但自盖伦时代以来一直存在。忧郁症的近亲,情感抑郁症和焦虑症,今天在桑德斯讨论的令人不安的特征中不那么明显——她指出,在某种程度上,被更多基于认知的诊断,如ASD,所取代。这本身就是一个讽刺的提醒,提醒我们文化态度的变幻莫测,提醒我们要记住更广泛的背景,在这个背景下,这些特定的社会身份被选择为模仿和采用。忧郁的人的社会身份的诱惑是很容易理解的:在体液系统中,大约四分之一的人患有过量的黑胆汁,它已经被正常化了,几个世纪以来一直被重视——可以说是由亚里士多德的作品(在可疑的“问题”中),文艺复兴时期的菲西诺和莎士比亚,甚至是弗洛伊德在1916年的《哀悼与忧郁》中。纵观西方历史,忧郁的阴暗情绪的积极属性和好处无需进一步解释或证明。他们散发着迷人的光芒。运用Rashed的条件来适当地承认和识别一个人所选择的社会身份的适合性,桑德斯对临床医生的指导澄清了边界问题。它说明了如何理解、规范和传达适当的规范,以阻止那些声称这样的身份无助于个人成长和心理健康的人。至少有了桑德斯所描述的一些流行的社会身份,我认为我们可以继续与忧郁症人进行比较。因为我们这个时代的“神经多样性”修辞包含了促进自闭症等综合症正常化和增值的力量。神经多样性理论以性别、种族和文化的差异为类比,主张尊重和欣赏差异。心理或认知的变化同样自然和有价值,它是……
{"title":"Diagnostic Wannabes","authors":"Jennifer Radden","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908280","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908280","url":null,"abstract":"Diagnostic Wannabes Jennifer Radden, PhD (bio) Saunders explores challenges for the clinician faced with self-styled sufferers from attention deficit hyperactivity disorder, post-traumatic stress disorder, bipolar disorder, autism spectrum disorder (ASD), and fibromyalgia. The diagnostic system was not meant to be used as “a scaffold for identity,” she points out. Yet wannabe patients now step into the clinic wielding self-proclaimed diagnoses as social identities. Saunders explains the context where such phenomena arise, and offers guidelines for clinicians addressing this new reality. To do so, she enlists Rashed’s innovative normative approach to the so-called boundary problem of assigning, and providing justification for, the contested line between normal and disordered. The boundary problem itself seems to rise to prominence during our current era of increasingly dimensional thinking, it is worth noting, with psychiatric diagnoses taken to refer to points on a continuum, rather than to discrete categorical disease entities. On the likely sources of these ‘diagnostic’ social identities, as well as reasons why certain diagnoses attach to them more commonly than others, Saunders points to social trends (including what she asserts to be a “post-stigma” cultural environment), the failure of efforts to identify neurobiological markers for psychiatric disorder, the ubiquity of social media, the algorithms themselves, and the hyperconnected existence of contemporary times. Such narratives also offer the comforts of a sense of belonging and explanations for perceived inadequacies, she rightly observes. Despite today’s virtual and other inducements, the problem introduced here is not an entirely new one. The first part of the seventeenth century in Europe saw an apparent “epidemic” of what was known as “melancholy,” a condition associated with the spleen, whose symptoms loosely resembled those of today’s depression and anxiety. Much of this suffering was undeniably real, but much was a fashionable, identity-conferring pose. “Every distemper of the body now is complicated with spleen,” the poet John Donne ironically observes in a letter dated 1622, “and when we were young men we scarce ever heard of the spleen. In our declinations now, every accident is accompanied with heavy clouds of melancholy”1 (Gosse, 2019). By then, the Melancholic Man (or homo melancholicus), with his surfeit of spleen, was an unmistakable character type—or social identity, as we would now say. Recognized and saluted in centuries-long literary and illustrative traditions, the type was an anchoring element of the humoral medicine which, despite the gradual emergence of more empirical science, had endured since Galenic times. Melancholy’s closest descendants, affective depressive and anxiety disorders, are today less evident among the troubling identities Saunders discusses—somewhat preempted, she points out, by more cognitively-based diagnoses such as ASD. [End Page 279] This is ","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"32 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588424","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Epistemic Style in OCD 强迫症的认知风格
IF 2.3 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a899943
C. Flores
* University of California, Irvine floreshc@uci.edu The author reports no conflict of interest. P ablo Hubacher Haerle’s excellent paper argues that there are cases of obsessivecompulsive disorder (OCD) (sexual OCD [S-OCD], specifically) in which people inquire in rational ways. If his analysis is correct, then OCD is not uniformly characterized by epistemic irrationality. The analysis of the cases is compelling, and it offers valuable new resources for understanding why (some) subjects with OCD persist in their inquiries. But I want to raise some questions about whether subjects really inquire rationally. To do so, I suggest a more comprehensive assessment of how these agents set different epistemic parameters. More generally, I will argue that by focusing on epistemic parameter settings and epistemic styles, we can clarify different loci of irrationality while de-stigmatizing OCD.
*加州大学欧文分校floreshc@uci.edu作者报告无利益冲突。P ablo Hubacher Haerle的优秀论文认为,有些强迫症(特别是性强迫症)患者会以理性的方式进行询问。如果他的分析是正确的,那么强迫症并不是统一地以认知非理性为特征。对这些案例的分析是令人信服的,它为理解为什么(一些)强迫症患者坚持询问提供了宝贵的新资源。但我想提出一些问题,关于受试者是否真的理性地询问。为此,我建议对这些代理如何设置不同的认知参数进行更全面的评估。更一般地说,我认为通过关注认知参数设置和认知风格,我们可以在去污名化强迫症的同时澄清不同的非理性位点。
{"title":"Epistemic Style in OCD","authors":"C. Flores","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a899943","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a899943","url":null,"abstract":"* University of California, Irvine floreshc@uci.edu The author reports no conflict of interest. P ablo Hubacher Haerle’s excellent paper argues that there are cases of obsessivecompulsive disorder (OCD) (sexual OCD [S-OCD], specifically) in which people inquire in rational ways. If his analysis is correct, then OCD is not uniformly characterized by epistemic irrationality. The analysis of the cases is compelling, and it offers valuable new resources for understanding why (some) subjects with OCD persist in their inquiries. But I want to raise some questions about whether subjects really inquire rationally. To do so, I suggest a more comprehensive assessment of how these agents set different epistemic parameters. More generally, I will argue that by focusing on epistemic parameter settings and epistemic styles, we can clarify different loci of irrationality while de-stigmatizing OCD.","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"33 1","pages":"147 - 150"},"PeriodicalIF":2.3,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74795173","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Critical Psychiatry in the Context of Critical Medicine 批判医学背景下的批判精神病学
IF 2.3 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a899939
S. Steingard
{"title":"Critical Psychiatry in the Context of Critical Medicine","authors":"S. Steingard","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a899939","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a899939","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"41 1","pages":"121 - 123"},"PeriodicalIF":2.3,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"76298119","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Narcissism A Focal Point for Examining the Interrelatedness of Psychology and Philosophy 自恋:检视心理学与哲学相互关系的焦点
IF 2.3 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a899947
Lydia Amir
{"title":"Narcissism A Focal Point for Examining the Interrelatedness of Psychology and Philosophy","authors":"Lydia Amir","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a899947","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a899947","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"1 1","pages":"169 - 172"},"PeriodicalIF":2.3,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75830387","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Four Ways of Going “Right” Functions in Mental Disorder 精神障碍中“正确”功能的四种方法
IF 2.3 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a899950
A. Plutynski
Abstract:In this paper, I distinguish four ways in which aspects or features of mental illness may be said to be functional. I contend that discussion of teleological perspectives on mental illness has unfortunately tended to conflate these senses. The latter two senses have played important practical roles both in predicting and explaining patterns of behavior, cognition, and affective response, atnd relatedly, in developing successful interventions. I further argue that functional talk in this context is neither inconsistent with viewing some disorders as dysfunctional in one of several senses, nor inappropriately adaptationist, provided we keep these senses of function distinct, and are precise about which is in play in a given context.
摘要:在本文中,我区分了精神疾病的方面或特征可能被称为功能的四种方式。我认为,关于精神疾病的目的论观点的讨论不幸地倾向于将这些感觉混为一谈。后两种感觉在预测和解释行为、认知和情感反应模式方面发挥了重要的实际作用,并在开发成功的干预措施方面发挥了相关作用。我进一步认为,在这种情况下,功能论既不与将某些障碍视为几种意义上的功能失调相矛盾,也不符合不适当的适应主义,前提是我们保持这些功能意义的区别,并准确地确定在给定的环境中哪一种功能在起作用。
{"title":"Four Ways of Going “Right” Functions in Mental Disorder","authors":"A. Plutynski","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a899950","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a899950","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:In this paper, I distinguish four ways in which aspects or features of mental illness may be said to be functional. I contend that discussion of teleological perspectives on mental illness has unfortunately tended to conflate these senses. The latter two senses have played important practical roles both in predicting and explaining patterns of behavior, cognition, and affective response, atnd relatedly, in developing successful interventions. I further argue that functional talk in this context is neither inconsistent with viewing some disorders as dysfunctional in one of several senses, nor inappropriately adaptationist, provided we keep these senses of function distinct, and are precise about which is in play in a given context.","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"37 1","pages":"181 - 191"},"PeriodicalIF":2.3,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89442515","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Narcissism as a Moral Incompetence 自恋是道德上的无能
IF 2.3 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a899946
A. Fatic
Abstract:In this paper, I suggest that the moral incompetence in narcissism is associated with a particular type of emotional incompetence, namely the incompetence to experience the moral emotions, such as empathy, solidarity, loyalty, or love. I then move on to discussing the ethical ramifications of this incompetence, primarily from the point of view of sentimentalist ethics, and conclude that emotional incompetence does not in fact reduce the moral responsibility of a narcissist person, whether diagnosed with Narcissistic Personality Disorder or not. My argument is based on the three criteria of moral responsibility proposed by Philip Pettit, namely those of value relevance, value judgment, and value sensitivity. I suggest that a sentimentalist ethical perspective entails that the satisfaction of two of the mentioned criteria (awareness of the social meaning of one’s choices and sufficient control of one’s actions) constitutes a moral obligation for the agent to satisfy the third criterion, namely to develop the appropriate moral sensibility and competence to actually choose morally correctly. This type of structure of obligation elucidates why narcissism is at the same time a moral failure and a psychopathology. At the same time, my argument portrays narcissism as a particular type of personality disturbance that almost uniquely reaffirms the role of moral re-education as the psychotherapeutic approach. This conclusion points to a potential revival of some of the precepts of Pinel’s affective psycho-pathology, dating back to the very beginnings of the psychotherapeutic clinic.
摘要:本文认为自恋者的道德无能与一种特殊类型的情感无能有关,即无法体验移情、团结、忠诚或爱等道德情感。然后我继续讨论这种无能的伦理后果,主要是从感伤主义伦理学的角度出发,并得出结论,情感无能实际上并没有减少自恋者的道德责任,无论是否被诊断为自恋型人格障碍。我的论点是基于菲利普·佩蒂特提出的道德责任的三个标准,即价值相关性、价值判断和价值敏感性。我认为,情感主义的伦理观点认为,满足上述两个标准(意识到自己选择的社会意义和对自己行为的充分控制)构成了行为人满足第三个标准的道德义务,即发展适当的道德敏感性和能力,从而在道德上正确地做出选择。这种义务结构解释了为什么自恋同时是一种道德失败和精神病理。与此同时,我的论点将自恋描述为一种特殊类型的人格障碍,几乎独特地重申了道德再教育作为心理治疗方法的作用。这个结论指出了皮内尔情感心理病理学的一些戒律的潜在复兴,这些戒律可以追溯到心理治疗诊所的最初阶段。
{"title":"Narcissism as a Moral Incompetence","authors":"A. Fatic","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a899946","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a899946","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:In this paper, I suggest that the moral incompetence in narcissism is associated with a particular type of emotional incompetence, namely the incompetence to experience the moral emotions, such as empathy, solidarity, loyalty, or love. I then move on to discussing the ethical ramifications of this incompetence, primarily from the point of view of sentimentalist ethics, and conclude that emotional incompetence does not in fact reduce the moral responsibility of a narcissist person, whether diagnosed with Narcissistic Personality Disorder or not. My argument is based on the three criteria of moral responsibility proposed by Philip Pettit, namely those of value relevance, value judgment, and value sensitivity. I suggest that a sentimentalist ethical perspective entails that the satisfaction of two of the mentioned criteria (awareness of the social meaning of one’s choices and sufficient control of one’s actions) constitutes a moral obligation for the agent to satisfy the third criterion, namely to develop the appropriate moral sensibility and competence to actually choose morally correctly. This type of structure of obligation elucidates why narcissism is at the same time a moral failure and a psychopathology. At the same time, my argument portrays narcissism as a particular type of personality disturbance that almost uniquely reaffirms the role of moral re-education as the psychotherapeutic approach. This conclusion points to a potential revival of some of the precepts of Pinel’s affective psycho-pathology, dating back to the very beginnings of the psychotherapeutic clinic.","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"23 1","pages":"159 - 167"},"PeriodicalIF":2.3,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85263353","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1