首页 > 最新文献

Hec Forum最新文献

英文 中文
COVID-19 and the Authority of Science. COVID-19与科学权威。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09455-7
Griffin Trotter

In an attempt to respond effectively to the COVID-19 pandemic, policy makers and scientific experts who advise them have aspired to present a unified front. Leveraging the authority of science, they have at times portrayed politically favored COVID interventions, such as lockdowns, as strongly grounded in scientific evidence-even to the point of claiming that enacting such interventions is simply a matter of "following the science." Strictly speaking, all such claims are false, since facts alone never yield moral-political conclusions. More importantly, attempts to present a unified front have led to a number of other actions and statements by scientists and policy makers that erode the authority of science. These include actions and statements that: (1) mislead the public about epidemiological matters such as mortality rates, cause of death determinations, and computerized modeling, or fail to correct mainstream media sources that interpret such concepts in misleading ways; (2) incorporate moral-political opinions into ostensible statements of fact; and (3) misrepresent or misuse scientific expertise. The fundamental thesis of the paper is not primarily that such actions and statements have proliferated during the COVID-19 epidemic (though I think they have), but rather that they are unscientific and that presenting them as science undermines the authority of science. In the moral-political realm, the great power of science and the source of its authority derives from its agnosticism about fundamental moral-political claims. Science, for instance, has no built-in presumption that we should respect life, promote freedom, or practice toleration; nor does it tell us which of these values to prioritize when values conflict. Because of this agnosticism, science is recognized across a broad diversity perspectives as morally and politically impartial, and authoritative within its proper sphere. When it is infused with partisan bias, it loses that authority.

为了有效应对COVID-19大流行,政策制定者和为他们提供建议的科学专家渴望形成统一战线。他们利用科学的权威,有时将政治上支持的COVID干预措施(如封锁)描述为强有力的科学证据,甚至声称实施此类干预措施只是“遵循科学”的问题。严格地说,所有这些说法都是错误的,因为事实本身永远不会得出道德-政治结论。更重要的是,提出统一战线的尝试导致科学家和决策者采取了其他一些行动和声明,这些行动和声明削弱了科学的权威。这些行为和声明包括:(1)在流行病学问题上误导公众,如死亡率、死因确定和计算机化建模,或未能纠正以误导方式解释这些概念的主流媒体来源;(2)将道德-政治观点纳入表面上的事实陈述;(三)歪曲、误用科学专门知识的。这篇论文的基本论点主要不是这样的行为和声明在COVID-19流行期间激增(尽管我认为是这样),而是它们是不科学的,将它们作为科学呈现会破坏科学的权威。在道德-政治领域,科学的巨大力量及其权威来源于其对基本道德-政治主张的不可知论。例如,科学并没有固有的假设,即我们应该尊重生命、促进自由或实行宽容;当这些价值观发生冲突时,它也不会告诉我们优先考虑哪些价值观。由于这种不可知论,科学被公认为在道德和政治上是公正的,在其适当的领域内是权威的。当它被注入党派偏见时,它就失去了这种权威。
{"title":"COVID-19 and the Authority of Science.","authors":"Griffin Trotter","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09455-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09455-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In an attempt to respond effectively to the COVID-19 pandemic, policy makers and scientific experts who advise them have aspired to present a unified front. Leveraging the authority of science, they have at times portrayed politically favored COVID interventions, such as lockdowns, as strongly grounded in scientific evidence-even to the point of claiming that enacting such interventions is simply a matter of \"following the science.\" Strictly speaking, all such claims are false, since facts alone never yield moral-political conclusions. More importantly, attempts to present a unified front have led to a number of other actions and statements by scientists and policy makers that erode the authority of science. These include actions and statements that: (1) mislead the public about epidemiological matters such as mortality rates, cause of death determinations, and computerized modeling, or fail to correct mainstream media sources that interpret such concepts in misleading ways; (2) incorporate moral-political opinions into ostensible statements of fact; and (3) misrepresent or misuse scientific expertise. The fundamental thesis of the paper is not primarily that such actions and statements have proliferated during the COVID-19 epidemic (though I think they have), but rather that they are unscientific and that presenting them as science undermines the authority of science. In the moral-political realm, the great power of science and the source of its authority derives from its agnosticism about fundamental moral-political claims. Science, for instance, has no built-in presumption that we should respect life, promote freedom, or practice toleration; nor does it tell us which of these values to prioritize when values conflict. Because of this agnosticism, science is recognized across a broad diversity perspectives as morally and politically impartial, and authoritative within its proper sphere. When it is infused with partisan bias, it loses that authority.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 2","pages":"111-138"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s10730-021-09455-7","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9438610","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
CURA-An Ethics Support Instrument for Nurses in Palliative Care. Feasibility and First Perceived Outcomes. 姑息治疗护士伦理支持工具。可行性和第一感知结果。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09456-6
Malene Vera van Schaik, H Roeline Pasman, Guy Widdershoven, Bert Molewijk, Suzanne Metselaar

Evaluating the feasibility and first perceived outcomes of a newly developed clinical ethics support instrument called CURA. This instrument is tailored to the needs of nurses that provide palliative care and is intended to foster both moral competences and moral resilience. This study is a descriptive cross-sectional evaluation study. Respondents consisted of nurses and nurse assistants (n = 97) following a continuing education program (course participants) and colleagues of these course participants (n = 124). Two questionnaires with five-point Likert scales were used. The feasibility questionnaire was given to all respondents, the perceived outcomes questionnaire only to the course participants. Data collection took place over a period of six months. Respondents were predominantly positive on most items of the feasibility questionnaire. The steps of CURA are clearly described (84% of course participants agreed or strongly agreed, 94% of colleagues) and easy to apply (78-87%). The perceived outcomes showed that CURA helped respondents to reflect on moral challenges (71% (strongly) agreed), in perspective taking (67%), with being aware of moral challenges (63%) and in dealing with moral distress (54%). Respondents did experience organizational barriers: only half of the respondents (strongly) agreed that they could easily find time for using CURA. CURA is a feasible instrument for nurses and nurse assistants providing palliative care. However, reported difficulties in organizing and making time for reflections with CURA indicate organizational preconditions ought to be met in order to implement CURA in daily practice. Furthermore, these results indicate that CURA helps to build moral competences and fosters moral resilience.

评估新开发的临床伦理支持工具CURA的可行性和第一感知结果。该工具是根据提供姑息治疗的护士的需要量身定制的,旨在培养道德能力和道德复原力。本研究为描述性横断面评价研究。受访者包括护士和护士助理(n = 97)在继续教育计划(课程参与者)和这些课程参与者的同事(n = 124)。采用李克特五点量表进行问卷调查。可行性问卷发给所有被调查者,感知结果问卷只发给课程参与者。数据收集工作进行了六个月。受访者对可行性问卷的大部分项目持肯定态度。CURA的步骤描述清晰(84%的课程参与者同意或强烈同意,94%的同事同意),易于应用(78-87%)。感知结果显示,CURA帮助受访者反思道德挑战(71%(强烈)同意),采取观点(67%),意识到道德挑战(63%)和处理道德困境(54%)。受访者确实遇到了组织障碍:只有一半的受访者(强烈)同意他们可以很容易地找到时间使用CURA。CURA是护士和护士助理提供姑息治疗的可行工具。然而,据报道,在组织和抽出时间对CURA进行反思方面存在困难,这表明为了在日常实践中实施CURA,应该满足组织的先决条件。此外,这些结果表明,CURA有助于道德能力的建立和道德弹性的培养。
{"title":"CURA-An Ethics Support Instrument for Nurses in Palliative Care. Feasibility and First Perceived Outcomes.","authors":"Malene Vera van Schaik,&nbsp;H Roeline Pasman,&nbsp;Guy Widdershoven,&nbsp;Bert Molewijk,&nbsp;Suzanne Metselaar","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09456-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09456-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Evaluating the feasibility and first perceived outcomes of a newly developed clinical ethics support instrument called CURA. This instrument is tailored to the needs of nurses that provide palliative care and is intended to foster both moral competences and moral resilience. This study is a descriptive cross-sectional evaluation study. Respondents consisted of nurses and nurse assistants (n = 97) following a continuing education program (course participants) and colleagues of these course participants (n = 124). Two questionnaires with five-point Likert scales were used. The feasibility questionnaire was given to all respondents, the perceived outcomes questionnaire only to the course participants. Data collection took place over a period of six months. Respondents were predominantly positive on most items of the feasibility questionnaire. The steps of CURA are clearly described (84% of course participants agreed or strongly agreed, 94% of colleagues) and easy to apply (78-87%). The perceived outcomes showed that CURA helped respondents to reflect on moral challenges (71% (strongly) agreed), in perspective taking (67%), with being aware of moral challenges (63%) and in dealing with moral distress (54%). Respondents did experience organizational barriers: only half of the respondents (strongly) agreed that they could easily find time for using CURA. CURA is a feasible instrument for nurses and nurse assistants providing palliative care. However, reported difficulties in organizing and making time for reflections with CURA indicate organizational preconditions ought to be met in order to implement CURA in daily practice. Furthermore, these results indicate that CURA helps to build moral competences and fosters moral resilience.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 2","pages":"139-159"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10167118/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9444710","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
The Ethics Laboratory: A Dialogical Practice for Interdisciplinary Moral Deliberation. 伦理实验室:跨学科道德思考的对话实践。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09460-w
Jeanette Bresson Ladegaard Knox

Recent advancements in therapeutic and diagnostic medicine, along with the creation of large biobanks and methods for monitoring health technologies, have improved the prospects for preventing, treating, and curing illness. These same advancements, however, give rise to a plethora of ethical questions concerning good decision-making and best action. These ethical questions engage policymakers, practitioners, scientists, and researchers from a variety of fields in different ways. Collaborations between professionals in the medical and health sciences and the social sciences and humanities often take an asymmetrical form, as when social scientists use ethnographic approaches to study the moral issues and practices of physicians. The ethics laboratory described in this article is a cross-sectoral and inter-disciplinary forum for collaborative investigation on important moral topics. It offers an experimental way of unpacking implied assumptions, underlying values, and comparable notions from different professional healthcare fields. The aim of this article is to present the ethics laboratory's methodology. The article offers a model and a hermeneutical framework that rests on a dialogical approach to ethical questions. The model and the framework derive from a Danish research project, Personalized Medicine in the Welfare State. This article uses personalized medicine as a point of reference, though it offers an argument for the applicability of the model more broadly.

治疗和诊断医学的最新进展,以及大型生物库的创建和监测卫生技术的方法,改善了预防、治疗和治愈疾病的前景。然而,这些进步也带来了大量关于良好决策和最佳行动的伦理问题。这些伦理问题以不同的方式吸引了来自不同领域的决策者、实践者、科学家和研究人员。医学和健康科学、社会科学和人文科学专业人员之间的合作往往采取不对称的形式,如社会科学家使用民族志方法来研究医生的道德问题和实践。本文中描述的伦理实验室是一个跨部门和跨学科的论坛,用于合作研究重要的道德主题。它提供了一种实验性的方式来拆解来自不同专业医疗保健领域的隐含假设、潜在价值和可比概念。本文的目的是介绍伦理实验室的方法。本文提供了一个模型和解释学框架,它依赖于对伦理问题的对话方法。该模型和框架源自丹麦的一个研究项目,福利国家的个性化医疗。本文使用个性化医疗作为一个参考点,尽管它为更广泛的模型适用性提供了一个论点。
{"title":"The Ethics Laboratory: A Dialogical Practice for Interdisciplinary Moral Deliberation.","authors":"Jeanette Bresson Ladegaard Knox","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09460-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09460-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Recent advancements in therapeutic and diagnostic medicine, along with the creation of large biobanks and methods for monitoring health technologies, have improved the prospects for preventing, treating, and curing illness. These same advancements, however, give rise to a plethora of ethical questions concerning good decision-making and best action. These ethical questions engage policymakers, practitioners, scientists, and researchers from a variety of fields in different ways. Collaborations between professionals in the medical and health sciences and the social sciences and humanities often take an asymmetrical form, as when social scientists use ethnographic approaches to study the moral issues and practices of physicians. The ethics laboratory described in this article is a cross-sectoral and inter-disciplinary forum for collaborative investigation on important moral topics. It offers an experimental way of unpacking implied assumptions, underlying values, and comparable notions from different professional healthcare fields. The aim of this article is to present the ethics laboratory's methodology. The article offers a model and a hermeneutical framework that rests on a dialogical approach to ethical questions. The model and the framework derive from a Danish research project, Personalized Medicine in the Welfare State. This article uses personalized medicine as a point of reference, though it offers an argument for the applicability of the model more broadly.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 2","pages":"185-199"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9435045","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Addressing Clinical Misconduct: Resigning and Whistleblowing in Clinical Ethics Consultation. 解决临床不端行为:辞职和举报在临床伦理咨询。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09459-3
Etan Kuperberg, Michael S Dauber

Clinical ethics consultants occasionally encounter unethical and/or unprofessional behavior as part of their normal job functions. In this article, we explore whether resigning (i.e., threatening resignation or resigning) and whistleblowing are acceptable methods ethics consultants can use to address these situations. Per our analysis, whether one considers ethics consultants private or public employees, loyal to their employer or to patients, families, and the public, resigning and whistleblowing are all acceptable, if not obligatory, actions of ethics consultants in certain circumstances. In this article, we analyze salient characteristics of ethics consultation as a profession as they pertain to resignation and whistleblowing in the context of ethics consultation. We also present tentative criteria for when ethics consultants are justified, if not obligated, to resign or blow the whistle.

临床伦理顾问偶尔会遇到不道德和/或不专业的行为,作为他们正常工作职能的一部分。在本文中,我们探讨辞职(即,威胁辞职或辞职)和举报是否是道德顾问可以用来解决这些情况的可接受的方法。根据我们的分析,无论人们认为道德顾问是私人雇员还是公共雇员,忠于雇主还是忠于病人、家属和公众,在某些情况下,辞职和举报都是可以接受的,如果不是强制性的,道德顾问的行为。在本文中,我们分析了道德咨询作为一种职业的显著特征,因为它们与道德咨询背景下的辞职和举报有关。我们还提出了关于道德顾问何时有理由(如果没有义务)辞职或举报的暂定标准。
{"title":"Addressing Clinical Misconduct: Resigning and Whistleblowing in Clinical Ethics Consultation.","authors":"Etan Kuperberg,&nbsp;Michael S Dauber","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09459-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09459-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Clinical ethics consultants occasionally encounter unethical and/or unprofessional behavior as part of their normal job functions. In this article, we explore whether resigning (i.e., threatening resignation or resigning) and whistleblowing are acceptable methods ethics consultants can use to address these situations. Per our analysis, whether one considers ethics consultants private or public employees, loyal to their employer or to patients, families, and the public, resigning and whistleblowing are all acceptable, if not obligatory, actions of ethics consultants in certain circumstances. In this article, we analyze salient characteristics of ethics consultation as a profession as they pertain to resignation and whistleblowing in the context of ethics consultation. We also present tentative criteria for when ethics consultants are justified, if not obligated, to resign or blow the whistle.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 2","pages":"161-183"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9488343","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reflective Debriefs as a Response to Moral Distress: Two Case Study Examples. 反思汇报作为对道德困境的回应:两个案例研究例子。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09441-z
Georgina Morley, Cristie Cole Horsburgh

Within this paper, we discuss Moral Distress Reflective Debriefs as a promising approach to address and mitigate moral distress experienced by healthcare professionals. We briefly review the empirical and theoretical literature on critical incident stress debriefing and psychological debriefing to highlight the potential benefits of this modality. We then describe the approach that we take to facilitating reflective group discussions in response to morally distressing patient cases ("Moral Distress Reflective Debriefs"). We discuss how the debriefing literature and other clinical ethics activities influenced the development of our approach. In particular, we focus on the role of the clinical ethicist as a facilitator with particular emphasis on encouraging perspective-taking and nurturing ethical attunement in a supportive manner. We suggest that this approach reduces the narrowing effects of frustration and anger that are often reported when individuals experience moral-constraint distress. Finally, we provide an example of Moral Distress Reflective Debriefs, elucidating how this supportive process complements ethics consultation and can mitigate the negative effects of moral distress.

在这篇论文中,我们讨论道德困境反思汇报作为一个有前途的方法来解决和减轻医疗保健专业人员所经历的道德困境。我们简要回顾了关于关键事件压力汇报和心理汇报的经验和理论文献,以强调这种模式的潜在好处。然后,我们描述了我们采取的方法,以促进反思性小组讨论,以回应道德困扰患者的情况(“道德困扰反思性汇报”)。我们讨论述职文献和其他临床伦理活动如何影响我们方法的发展。特别是,我们关注临床伦理学家作为促进者的作用,特别强调以支持的方式鼓励换位思考和培养伦理协调。我们认为这种方法减少了当个人经历道德约束困扰时经常报道的沮丧和愤怒的缩小效应。最后,我们提供了一个道德困境反思汇报的例子,阐明了这种支持性过程如何补充伦理咨询并减轻道德困境的负面影响。
{"title":"Reflective Debriefs as a Response to Moral Distress: Two Case Study Examples.","authors":"Georgina Morley,&nbsp;Cristie Cole Horsburgh","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09441-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09441-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Within this paper, we discuss Moral Distress Reflective Debriefs as a promising approach to address and mitigate moral distress experienced by healthcare professionals. We briefly review the empirical and theoretical literature on critical incident stress debriefing and psychological debriefing to highlight the potential benefits of this modality. We then describe the approach that we take to facilitating reflective group discussions in response to morally distressing patient cases (\"Moral Distress Reflective Debriefs\"). We discuss how the debriefing literature and other clinical ethics activities influenced the development of our approach. In particular, we focus on the role of the clinical ethicist as a facilitator with particular emphasis on encouraging perspective-taking and nurturing ethical attunement in a supportive manner. We suggest that this approach reduces the narrowing effects of frustration and anger that are often reported when individuals experience moral-constraint distress. Finally, we provide an example of Moral Distress Reflective Debriefs, elucidating how this supportive process complements ethics consultation and can mitigate the negative effects of moral distress.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 1","pages":"1-20"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s10730-021-09441-z","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10716312","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 15
Effect of a Moral Distress Consultation Service on Moral Distress, Empowerment, and a Healthy Work Environment. 道德困境咨询服务对道德困境、赋权和健康工作环境的影响。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09449-5
Elizabeth G Epstein, Ruhee Shah, Mary Faith Marshall

Background:  Healthcare providers who are accountable for patient care safety and quality but who are not empowered to actualize them experience moral distress. Interventions to mitigate moral distress in the healthcare organization are needed.

Objective:  To evaluate the effect on moral distress and clinician empowerment of an established, health-system-wide intervention, Moral Distress Consultation.

Methods:  A quasi-experimental, mixed methods study using pre/post surveys, structured interviews, and evaluation of consult themes was used. Consults were requested by staff when moral distress was present. The purpose of consultation is to identify the causes of moral distress, barriers to action, and strategies to improve the situation. Intervention participants were those who attended a moral distress consult. Control participants were staff surveyed prior to the consult. Interviews were conducted after the consult with willing participants and unit managers. Moral distress was measured using the Moral Distress Thermometer. Empowerment was measured using the Global Empowerment Scale.

Results:  Twenty-one consults were conducted. Analysis included 116 intervention and 30 control surveys, and 11 interviews. A small but significant decrease was found among intervention participants, especially intensive care staff. Empowerment was unchanged. Interview themes support the consult service as an effective mode for open discussion of difficult circumstances and an important aspect of a healthy work environment.

Conclusions:  Moral distress consultation is an organization-wide mechanism for addressing moral distress. Consultation does not resolve moral distress but helps staff identify strategies to improve the situation. Further studies including follow up may elucidate consultation effectiveness.

背景:医疗保健提供者谁是负责病人护理的安全和质量,但谁没有权力去实现他们经历道德困境。干预措施,以减轻道德困扰在医疗保健组织是必要的。目的:评估道德困扰咨询这一已建立的卫生系统干预措施对道德困扰和临床医生赋权的影响。方法:采用准实验、混合方法研究,采用前后调查、结构化访谈和咨询主题评估。当出现道德上的困扰时,工作人员要求进行咨询。咨询的目的是确定道德困境的原因、行动障碍和改善情况的策略。干预参与者是那些参加过道德困扰咨询的人。对照参与者是咨询前接受调查的工作人员。在咨询后,与有意愿的参与者和单位经理进行了访谈。使用道德压力温度计测量道德压力。赋权是用全球赋权量表来衡量的。结果:共问诊21例。分析包括116项干预调查和30项对照调查,以及11次访谈。在干预参与者中,尤其是重症监护人员,发现了小但显著的下降。授权没有改变。面谈主题支持咨询服务是公开讨论困难情况的有效模式,也是健康工作环境的一个重要方面。结论:道德困境咨询是解决道德困境的全组织机制。咨询不能解决道德困境,但可以帮助工作人员确定改善情况的策略。进一步的研究,包括随访,可以阐明咨询的有效性。
{"title":"Effect of a Moral Distress Consultation Service on Moral Distress, Empowerment, and a Healthy Work Environment.","authors":"Elizabeth G Epstein,&nbsp;Ruhee Shah,&nbsp;Mary Faith Marshall","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09449-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09449-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p><strong>Background: </strong> Healthcare providers who are accountable for patient care safety and quality but who are not empowered to actualize them experience moral distress. Interventions to mitigate moral distress in the healthcare organization are needed.</p><p><strong>Objective: </strong> To evaluate the effect on moral distress and clinician empowerment of an established, health-system-wide intervention, Moral Distress Consultation.</p><p><strong>Methods: </strong> A quasi-experimental, mixed methods study using pre/post surveys, structured interviews, and evaluation of consult themes was used. Consults were requested by staff when moral distress was present. The purpose of consultation is to identify the causes of moral distress, barriers to action, and strategies to improve the situation. Intervention participants were those who attended a moral distress consult. Control participants were staff surveyed prior to the consult. Interviews were conducted after the consult with willing participants and unit managers. Moral distress was measured using the Moral Distress Thermometer. Empowerment was measured using the Global Empowerment Scale.</p><p><strong>Results: </strong> Twenty-one consults were conducted. Analysis included 116 intervention and 30 control surveys, and 11 interviews. A small but significant decrease was found among intervention participants, especially intensive care staff. Empowerment was unchanged. Interview themes support the consult service as an effective mode for open discussion of difficult circumstances and an important aspect of a healthy work environment.</p><p><strong>Conclusions: </strong> Moral distress consultation is an organization-wide mechanism for addressing moral distress. Consultation does not resolve moral distress but helps staff identify strategies to improve the situation. Further studies including follow up may elucidate consultation effectiveness.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 1","pages":"21-35"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s10730-021-09449-5","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10733461","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Affirming the Existence and Legitimacy of Secular Bioethical Consensus, and Rejecting Engelhardt's Alternative: A Reply to Nick Colgrove and Kelly Kate Evans. 肯定世俗生命伦理共识的存在和合法性,拒绝恩格尔哈特的替代——对尼克·科尔格罗夫和凯利·凯特·埃文斯的回答。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09452-w
Abram Brummett

One of the most significant and persistent debates in secular clinical ethics is the question of ethics expertise, which asks whether ethicists can make justified moral recommendations in active patient cases. A critical point of contention in the ethics expertise debate is whether there is, in fact, a bioethical consensus upon which secular ethicists can ground their recommendations and whether there is, in principle, a way of justifying such a consensus in a morally pluralistic context. In a series of recent articles in this journal, Janet Malek defends a positive view of ethics expertise, claiming that secular ethicists should comport their recommendations with bioethical consensus. In response, Nick Colgrove and Kelly Kate Evans deny the existence of a secular bioethical consensus; question why, even if it did exist, consensus should be considered a reliable way of resolving bioethical questions; and recommend a friendlier approach to clinical ethics based on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt Jr. In this article, I respond to Colgrove and Evans on all three points. In part one, I show there is a secular bioethical consensus but note it could be better consolidated and created through a more systematic and inclusive process. In part two, I argue that bioethical consensus is morally justified but note that this justification cannot be plausibly based upon claims that it only invokes moral principles available to or shared by all. In part three, I argue Engelhardt's approach cannot be described as "friendlier" to clinical ethics because it is incompatible with many current healthcare laws and policies.

世俗临床伦理学中最重要和持久的争论之一是伦理专家问题,即伦理学家是否可以在活跃的患者病例中提出合理的道德建议。伦理专家辩论中争论的一个关键点是,事实上是否存在一种生物伦理共识,世俗伦理学家可以以此为基础提出他们的建议,以及原则上是否存在一种在道德多元化背景下证明这种共识的方法。在本刊最近的一系列文章中,Janet Malek为伦理学专家的积极观点进行了辩护,声称世俗伦理学家应该将他们的建议与生物伦理学共识相一致。作为回应,尼克·科尔格罗夫和凯利·凯特·埃文斯否认世俗生物伦理共识的存在;质疑为什么,即使它确实存在,共识应该被认为是解决生物伦理问题的可靠方法;并推荐一种基于小H. Tristram Engelhardt的思想的更友好的临床伦理学方法。在这篇文章中,我对Colgrove和Evans的这三点做出了回应。在第一部分中,我展示了一种世俗的生物伦理共识,但注意到它可以通过一个更系统、更包容的过程更好地巩固和创造。在第二部分中,我认为生物伦理共识在道德上是合理的,但请注意,这种理由不能合理地建立在声称它只援引所有人都可以获得或共享的道德原则的基础上。在第三部分,我认为恩格尔哈特的方法不能被描述为对临床伦理“更友好”,因为它与许多现行的医疗法律和政策不相容。
{"title":"Affirming the Existence and Legitimacy of Secular Bioethical Consensus, and Rejecting Engelhardt's Alternative: A Reply to Nick Colgrove and Kelly Kate Evans.","authors":"Abram Brummett","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09452-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09452-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>One of the most significant and persistent debates in secular clinical ethics is the question of ethics expertise, which asks whether ethicists can make justified moral recommendations in active patient cases. A critical point of contention in the ethics expertise debate is whether there is, in fact, a bioethical consensus upon which secular ethicists can ground their recommendations and whether there is, in principle, a way of justifying such a consensus in a morally pluralistic context. In a series of recent articles in this journal, Janet Malek defends a positive view of ethics expertise, claiming that secular ethicists should comport their recommendations with bioethical consensus. In response, Nick Colgrove and Kelly Kate Evans deny the existence of a secular bioethical consensus; question why, even if it did exist, consensus should be considered a reliable way of resolving bioethical questions; and recommend a friendlier approach to clinical ethics based on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt Jr. In this article, I respond to Colgrove and Evans on all three points. In part one, I show there is a secular bioethical consensus but note it could be better consolidated and created through a more systematic and inclusive process. In part two, I argue that bioethical consensus is morally justified but note that this justification cannot be plausibly based upon claims that it only invokes moral principles available to or shared by all. In part three, I argue Engelhardt's approach cannot be described as \"friendlier\" to clinical ethics because it is incompatible with many current healthcare laws and policies.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 1","pages":"95-109"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s10730-021-09452-w","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10716367","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The Experience of Moral Distress in an Academic Family Medicine Clinic. 一个学术性家庭医学诊所的道德困境体验。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09453-9
Dawn Worsham Bourne, Elizabeth Epstein

Background and objectives: Primary care providers (PCPs) report decreased job satisfaction and high levels of burnout, yet little is known about their experience of moral distress. The aim of this study was to gain insight into the experiences of PCPs regarding moral distress including causative factors and proposed mitigation strategies.

Methods: This qualitative pilot study used semi-structured interviews to identify causes of moral distress in PCPs in an academic family medicine department. Interviews were analyzed using conventional content analysis.

Results: Of 35 eligible participants, 12 completed the study (34% participation rate). Most were white, female, and had practiced for less than 10 years. Four PCPs had considered leaving their position due to moral distress. Participants identified five causes of moral distress: policies and procedures that conflict with patient needs, the unpredictable nature of primary care, need to "bend the rules," lack of accountability, and lack of support staff. Six internal conflicts made resolving morally distressing situations difficult: perceived powerlessness, sense of responsibility, socialization to follow orders, emotional toll of the job, competing obligations, and fear of mistakes.

Conclusions: These findings matched themes in the current literature and identified an unbending infrastructure. This, coupled with the chaotic nature of primary care, resulted in frequent moral distress. Participants offered solutions to reduce and mitigate moral distress (also similar with current literature) and suggested moral distress and burnout are closely linked.

背景和目的:初级保健提供者(pcp)报告工作满意度下降和高度倦怠,但对他们的道德痛苦经历知之甚少。本研究的目的是深入了解pcp在道德困境方面的经验,包括病因和建议的缓解策略。方法:本定性初步研究采用半结构化访谈来确定学术家庭医学部门pcp道德困扰的原因。访谈采用传统的内容分析法进行分析。结果:在35名符合条件的参与者中,12名完成了研究(34%的参与率)。大多数是白人,女性,并且练习不到10年。四名pcp曾考虑因道德困境而离职。与会者确定了道德困境的五个原因:与患者需求相冲突的政策和程序,初级保健的不可预测性,需要“变通”,缺乏问责制,以及缺乏支持人员。六种内部冲突使得解决道德困境变得困难:感知到的无力感、责任感、服从命令的社会化、工作的情感代价、竞争性义务和对错误的恐惧。结论:这些发现与当前文献的主题相匹配,并确定了一个不弯曲的基础结构。这一点,再加上初级保健的混乱性质,导致了频繁的道德困境。参与者提出了减少和减轻道德困境的解决方案(与当前文献相似),并认为道德困境与倦怠密切相关。
{"title":"The Experience of Moral Distress in an Academic Family Medicine Clinic.","authors":"Dawn Worsham Bourne,&nbsp;Elizabeth Epstein","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09453-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09453-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p><strong>Background and objectives: </strong>Primary care providers (PCPs) report decreased job satisfaction and high levels of burnout, yet little is known about their experience of moral distress. The aim of this study was to gain insight into the experiences of PCPs regarding moral distress including causative factors and proposed mitigation strategies.</p><p><strong>Methods: </strong>This qualitative pilot study used semi-structured interviews to identify causes of moral distress in PCPs in an academic family medicine department. Interviews were analyzed using conventional content analysis.</p><p><strong>Results: </strong>Of 35 eligible participants, 12 completed the study (34% participation rate). Most were white, female, and had practiced for less than 10 years. Four PCPs had considered leaving their position due to moral distress. Participants identified five causes of moral distress: policies and procedures that conflict with patient needs, the unpredictable nature of primary care, need to \"bend the rules,\" lack of accountability, and lack of support staff. Six internal conflicts made resolving morally distressing situations difficult: perceived powerlessness, sense of responsibility, socialization to follow orders, emotional toll of the job, competing obligations, and fear of mistakes.</p><p><strong>Conclusions: </strong>These findings matched themes in the current literature and identified an unbending infrastructure. This, coupled with the chaotic nature of primary care, resulted in frequent moral distress. Participants offered solutions to reduce and mitigate moral distress (also similar with current literature) and suggested moral distress and burnout are closely linked.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 1","pages":"37-54"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s10730-021-09453-9","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10723905","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Psychiatric Hospital Ethics Committee Discussions Over a Span of Nearly Three Decades. 精神病院伦理委员会近三十年的讨论。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09454-8
Michall Ferencz-Kaddari, Abira Reizer, Meni Koslowsky, Ora Nakash, Shai Konas

Various types of health settings use clinical ethics committees (CEC) to deal with the ethical issues that confront both healthcare providers and their patients. Although these committees are now more common than ever, changes in the content of ethical dilemmas through the years is still a relatively unexplored area of research. The current study examines the major topics brought to the CEC of a psychiatric hospital in Israel and explores whether there were changes in their frequency across nearly three decades. The present paper reports on a thematic analysis of the written verbatim transcripts from 466 ethical topics brought to the CEC between the years 1991 and 2016. The following major topics related to ethical dilemmas were identified: confidentiality (30%), patient autonomy (23%), health records (14%), dual relationship (12%), allocation of resources (11%), inappropriate professional and personal conduct (9%), and multicultural sensitivity (1%). Topics related to confidentiality increased significantly over the years, as did inappropriate professional and personal conduct. In addition, the analysis showed that the content of the ethical cases and the resolutions suggested by the CEC also varied over the years. In conclusion, although most ethical topics have remained relatively stable over time, the discourse around them has evolved, requiring a dynamic assessment and reflection by the mental health practitioners serving as members of a CEC.

各种类型的医疗机构使用临床伦理委员会(CEC)来处理医疗保健提供者及其患者所面临的伦理问题。尽管这些委员会现在比以往任何时候都更普遍,但这些年来伦理困境内容的变化仍然是一个相对未被探索的研究领域。目前的研究检查了以色列一家精神病院CEC的主要主题,并探讨了近三十年来它们的频率是否有变化。本文报告了对1991年至2016年期间提交CEC的466个伦理主题的逐字书面记录的专题分析。确定了与道德困境相关的以下主要主题:保密性(30%)、患者自主权(23%)、健康记录(14%)、双重关系(12%)、资源分配(11%)、不当的职业和个人行为(9%)和多元文化敏感性(1%)。多年来,与保密相关的话题显著增加,不恰当的职业和个人行为也在增加。此外,分析表明,伦理案件的内容和CEC建议的决议也在逐年变化。总之,尽管大多数伦理主题随着时间的推移保持相对稳定,但围绕它们的论述已经发生了变化,需要作为CEC成员的精神卫生从业人员进行动态评估和反思。
{"title":"Psychiatric Hospital Ethics Committee Discussions Over a Span of Nearly Three Decades.","authors":"Michall Ferencz-Kaddari,&nbsp;Abira Reizer,&nbsp;Meni Koslowsky,&nbsp;Ora Nakash,&nbsp;Shai Konas","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09454-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09454-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Various types of health settings use clinical ethics committees (CEC) to deal with the ethical issues that confront both healthcare providers and their patients. Although these committees are now more common than ever, changes in the content of ethical dilemmas through the years is still a relatively unexplored area of research. The current study examines the major topics brought to the CEC of a psychiatric hospital in Israel and explores whether there were changes in their frequency across nearly three decades. The present paper reports on a thematic analysis of the written verbatim transcripts from 466 ethical topics brought to the CEC between the years 1991 and 2016. The following major topics related to ethical dilemmas were identified: confidentiality (30%), patient autonomy (23%), health records (14%), dual relationship (12%), allocation of resources (11%), inappropriate professional and personal conduct (9%), and multicultural sensitivity (1%). Topics related to confidentiality increased significantly over the years, as did inappropriate professional and personal conduct. In addition, the analysis showed that the content of the ethical cases and the resolutions suggested by the CEC also varied over the years. In conclusion, although most ethical topics have remained relatively stable over time, the discourse around them has evolved, requiring a dynamic assessment and reflection by the mental health practitioners serving as members of a CEC.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 1","pages":"55-71"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s10730-021-09454-8","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10723906","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Primary Care Ethics is Just Medical Ethics: A Philosophical Argument for the Feasibility of Transitioning Acute Care Ethics to the Primary Care Setting. 初级保健伦理就是医学伦理:急症护理伦理过渡到初级保健环境可行性的哲学论证。
IF 1.5 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1007/s10730-021-09451-x
Stephen Perinchery-Herman

Whether practiced by ethics committees or clinical ethicists, medical ethics enjoys a solid foundation in acute care hospitals. However, medical ethics fails to have a strong presence in the primary care setting. Recently, some ethicists have argued that the reason for this disparity between ethics in the acute and primary care setting is that primary care ethics is distinct from acute care ethics: the failure to translate ethics to the primary care setting stems from the incorrect belief that acute care ethics can be applied to the primary care setting. In this paper, I argue that primary care ethics and acute care ethics are species of the same ethical genus, and that the ethical differences are not ones of kind but of circumstance. I do this by appealing to the role obligations that underlie acute care and primary care clinicians' medical ethical obligations and the shared institutions that ground those obligations.

无论是伦理委员会还是临床伦理学家,急诊医院的医学伦理都有着坚实的基础。然而,医学伦理在初级保健环境中没有很强的存在感。最近,一些伦理学家认为,这种差异的原因在急诊和初级保健设置的伦理是不同的,初级保健伦理不同于急性护理伦理:未能将伦理转化为初级保健设置源于错误的信念,即急性护理伦理可以应用于初级保健设置。在本文中,我认为初级保健伦理学和急性护理伦理学是同一伦理属的物种,并且伦理差异不是种类而是环境的差异。我通过呼吁作为急症护理和初级保健临床医生医学道德义务基础的角色义务以及作为这些义务基础的共同机构来做到这一点。
{"title":"Primary Care Ethics is Just Medical Ethics: A Philosophical Argument for the Feasibility of Transitioning Acute Care Ethics to the Primary Care Setting.","authors":"Stephen Perinchery-Herman","doi":"10.1007/s10730-021-09451-x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-021-09451-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Whether practiced by ethics committees or clinical ethicists, medical ethics enjoys a solid foundation in acute care hospitals. However, medical ethics fails to have a strong presence in the primary care setting. Recently, some ethicists have argued that the reason for this disparity between ethics in the acute and primary care setting is that primary care ethics is distinct from acute care ethics: the failure to translate ethics to the primary care setting stems from the incorrect belief that acute care ethics can be applied to the primary care setting. In this paper, I argue that primary care ethics and acute care ethics are species of the same ethical genus, and that the ethical differences are not ones of kind but of circumstance. I do this by appealing to the role obligations that underlie acute care and primary care clinicians' medical ethical obligations and the shared institutions that ground those obligations.</p>","PeriodicalId":46160,"journal":{"name":"Hec Forum","volume":"35 1","pages":"73-94"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s10730-021-09451-x","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10723890","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Hec Forum
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1