首页 > 最新文献

PHILOSOPHIA最新文献

英文 中文
Editorial Letter for Volume 52 (2024) 第 52 卷(2024 年)编辑信
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-26 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00723-7
Mitchell Green
{"title":"Editorial Letter for Volume 52 (2024)","authors":"Mitchell Green","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00723-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00723-7","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-02-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140431094","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Williamson’s Epistemicism and Properties Accounts of Predicates 威廉姆森的认识论与谓词的属性说明
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-26 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00716-6
Paul Teller

If the semantic values of predicates are, as Williamson assumes (Philsophical Perspectives, 13, 505–517, 1999, 509) properties in the intensional sense, then epistemicism is immediate. Epistemicism fails, so also this properties account of predicates. I deploy examination of Williamson’s account as a foil against properties as semantic values, showing that his two positive arguments for bivalence fail, as do his efforts to rescue epistemicism from obvious problems. In Part II I argue that, despite the properties account’s problems, it has an important role to play in compositional semantics. We may separate the problem of how smallest parts of language get attached to the world from the problem of how those parts compose to form complex semantic values. For the latter problem we idealize and treat the smallest semantic values as properties (and referents). So doing functions to put to one side how the smallest parts get worldly attachment, a problem that would just get in the way of understanding composition. Attachment to the world must be studied separately, and I review some of the options. As a bonus we see why the requirement of higher order vagueness is an artifact of taking properties as semantic values literally instead of as a simplifying idealization.

如果谓词的语义值正如威廉姆森所假定的(《哲学视角》,13, 505-517, 1999, 509)是内维意义上的属性,那么认识论就是直接的。认识论失败了,那么关于谓词属性的解释也就失败了。我将对威廉姆森的解释进行研究,以衬托作为语义值的属性,表明他对二元性的两个正面论证是失败的,正如他努力将认识论从明显的问题中解救出来一样。在第二部分中,我将论证,尽管属性说存在问题,但它在构成语义学中仍可发挥重要作用。我们可以把语言的最小部分如何附着于世界的问题与这些部分如何组成复杂语义值的问题分开。对于后一个问题,我们将最小的语义值理想化并视为属性(和所指)。这样做的作用是把最小的部分如何获得对世界的依附放到一边,而这个问题只会妨碍对构成的理解。对世界的依附必须单独研究,我将回顾其中的一些选择。作为额外的收获,我们还可以看到为什么高阶模糊性的要求是把属性作为语义值而不是简化理想化的产物。
{"title":"Williamson’s Epistemicism and Properties Accounts of Predicates","authors":"Paul Teller","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00716-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00716-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p>If the semantic values of predicates are, as Williamson assumes (<i>Philsophical Perspectives,</i> <i>13</i>, 505–517, 1999, 509) properties in the intensional sense, then epistemicism is immediate. Epistemicism fails, so also this properties account of predicates. I deploy examination of Williamson’s account as a foil against properties as semantic values, showing that his two positive arguments for bivalence fail, as do his efforts to rescue epistemicism from obvious problems. In Part II I argue that, despite the properties account’s problems, it has an important role to play in compositional semantics. We may separate the problem of how smallest parts of language get attached to the world from the problem of how those parts compose to form complex semantic values. For the latter problem we idealize and treat the smallest semantic values as properties (and referents). So doing functions to put to one side how the smallest parts get worldly attachment, a problem that would just get in the way of understanding composition. Attachment to the world must be studied separately, and I review some of the options. As a bonus we see why the requirement of higher order vagueness is an artifact of taking properties as semantic values literally instead of as a simplifying idealization.</p>","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-02-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140010475","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophy as a Science and as a Humanity? 哲学是科学还是人性?
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-23 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00720-w
Michael Strevens

This commentary on Philip Kitcher’s book What’s the Use of Philosophy? addresses two questions. First, must philosophers be methodologically self-conscious to do good work? Second, is there value in the questions pursued in the traditional areas of analytic philosophy?

这篇对 Philip Kitcher 的《哲学有什么用》一书的评论探讨了两个问题。首先,哲学家必须具有方法论上的自觉才能做好工作吗?其次,在分析哲学的传统领域中所追求的问题是否有价值?
{"title":"Philosophy as a Science and as a Humanity?","authors":"Michael Strevens","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00720-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00720-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This commentary on Philip Kitcher’s book <i>What’s the Use of Philosophy?</i> addresses two questions. First, must philosophers be methodologically self-conscious to do good work? Second, is there value in the questions pursued in the traditional areas of analytic philosophy?</p>","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-02-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139954966","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Analysis and Reexamination of Functionalism from the Perspective of Artificial Intelligence 从人工智能的角度分析和重新审视功能主义
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-01 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00719-3
Strahinja Đorđević, Goran Ružić

This paper examines the role of machine functionalism, as one of the most popular positions within the philosophy of mind, in the context of the development of artificial intelligence. Our analysis starts from the idea that machine functionalism is a theory that is largely consistent with the principles behind the strong AI thesis. However, we will see that there is a convincing counter-argument against such claims, and we will problematize this issue. Also, by testing ChatGPT, as the most popular publicly available AI tool, we will make an effort to figure out whether the strong AI thesis could currently even be considered a potentially sustainable principle. Since ChatGPT fails the Turing test our conclusion is that the strong AI thesis cannot be upheld even in principle, implying that the current state of this AI tool does not yet provide strong enough arguments in favor of machine functionalism.

机器功能主义是心智哲学中最流行的立场之一,本文探讨了机器功能主义在人工智能发展中的作用。我们分析的出发点是,机器功能主义是一种与强人工智能理论背后的原则基本一致的理论。然而,我们将看到,有一个令人信服的反驳理由来反对这种说法,我们将对这一问题进行论证。此外,通过测试 ChatGPT(最流行的公开人工智能工具),我们将努力弄清强人工智能理论目前是否可以被视为一个潜在的可持续原则。由于 ChatGPT 未能通过图灵测试,我们的结论是强人工智能理论即使在原则上也无法得到支持,这意味着该人工智能工具的现状还不能为机器功能主义提供足够有力的论据。
{"title":"The Analysis and Reexamination of Functionalism from the Perspective of Artificial Intelligence","authors":"Strahinja Đorđević, Goran Ružić","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00719-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00719-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper examines the role of machine functionalism, as one of the most popular positions within the philosophy of mind, in the context of the development of artificial intelligence. Our analysis starts from the idea that machine functionalism is a theory that is largely consistent with the principles behind the strong AI thesis. However, we will see that there is a convincing counter-argument against such claims, and we will problematize this issue. Also, by testing ChatGPT, as the most popular publicly available AI tool, we will make an effort to figure out whether the strong AI thesis could currently even be considered a potentially sustainable principle. Since ChatGPT fails the Turing test our conclusion is that the strong AI thesis cannot be upheld even in principle, implying that the current state of this AI tool does not yet provide strong enough arguments in favor of machine functionalism.</p>","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139677652","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How to Read How to Do Things with Words: On Sbisà’s Proof by Contradiction 如何阅读《如何用文字做事》:论斯比萨的矛盾证明
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-01-23 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00714-8
Jeremy Wanderer, Leo Townsend

Midway through How to Do Things With Words, J.L. Austin’s announces a “fresh start” in his efforts to characterize the ways in which speech is action, and introduces a new conceptual framework from the one he has been using up to that point. Against a common reading that portrays this move as simply abandoning the framework so far developed, Marina Sbisà contends that the text takes the argumentative form of a proof by contradiction, such that the initial framework plays an instrumental role as part of a proof in favour of the subsequent one. Despite agreeing with Sbisà’s broad instrumentalist approach, we argue that her regimentation of Austin’s narrative into a proof by contradiction ultimately fails - both as a proof and as an interpretation of Austin. Instead, we suggest that a better way of interpreting the peculiar structure of How to Do Things With Words is as a pedagogical exercise whose point is to bring a concealed alternative into view in a manner that also explains its initial concealment, and that this approach provides richer resources for supporting Sbisà’s own conventionalist understanding of illocution than that afforded by reading the text as a proof by contradiction.

在《如何用言语做事》一书的中段,J.L. 奥斯汀宣布 "重新开始 "他描述言语行动方式的努力,并引入了一个新的概念框架,而不是他在此之前一直使用的框架。玛丽娜-斯比萨(Marina Sbisà)认为,文本采用了矛盾证明的论证形式,因此最初的框架在证明中发挥了工具性作用,有利于后来的框架。尽管我们同意斯比萨广义的工具论方法,但我们认为,她将奥斯汀的叙述规范化为矛盾证明最终是失败的--无论是作为证明还是作为对奥斯汀的解释。相反,我们认为,将《如何用语言做事》的奇特结构解释为一种教学实践是更好的方法,其意义在于以一种也能解释其最初隐藏的方式将隐藏的替代方案呈现在人们面前,这种方法比将文本解读为矛盾证明提供了更丰富的资源,以支持斯比萨自己对惯用法的理解。
{"title":"How to Read How to Do Things with Words: On Sbisà’s Proof by Contradiction","authors":"Jeremy Wanderer, Leo Townsend","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00714-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00714-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Midway through <i>How to Do Things With Words</i>, J.L. Austin’s announces a “fresh start” in his efforts to characterize the ways in which speech is action, and introduces a new conceptual framework from the one he has been using up to that point. Against a common reading that portrays this move as simply abandoning the framework so far developed, Marina Sbisà contends that the text takes the argumentative form of a proof by contradiction, such that the initial framework plays an instrumental role as part of a proof in favour of the subsequent one. Despite agreeing with Sbisà’s broad instrumentalist approach, we argue that her regimentation of Austin’s narrative into a proof by contradiction ultimately fails - both as a proof and as an interpretation of Austin. Instead, we suggest that a better way of interpreting the peculiar structure of <i>How to Do Things With Words</i> is as a pedagogical exercise whose point is to bring a concealed alternative into view in a manner that also explains its initial concealment, and that this approach provides richer resources for supporting Sbisà’s own conventionalist understanding of illocution than that afforded by reading the text as a proof by contradiction.</p>","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-01-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139551720","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Normative Error Theory and No Self-Defeat: A Reply to Case 规范错误理论与不自毁:对案例的答复
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-01-19 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00718-4
Mustafa Khuramy, Erik Schulz

Many philosophers have claimed that normative error theorists are committed to the claim ‘Error theory is true, but I have no reason to believe it’, which to some appears paradoxical. Case (2019) has claimed that the normative error theorist cannot avoid this paradox. In this paper, we argue that there is no paradox in the first place, that is once we clear up the ambiguity of the word ‘reason’, both on the error theorist’s side and those that claim that there is a self-defeat problem. Upon clarification, we also raise scepticism to what exactly the nature of self-defeat is meant to be.

许多哲学家声称,规范性错误理论家致力于 "错误理论是真的,但我没有理由相信它 "的主张,这在一些人看来是自相矛盾的。凯斯(2019)声称,规范性错误理论家无法避免这一悖论。在本文中,我们认为首先不存在悖论,也就是说,一旦我们澄清了 "理由 "一词的歧义,无论是错误论者一方还是那些声称存在自我挫败问题的一方,都不存在悖论。在澄清之后,我们也会对自我挫败的本质究竟是什么提出怀疑。
{"title":"Normative Error Theory and No Self-Defeat: A Reply to Case","authors":"Mustafa Khuramy, Erik Schulz","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00718-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00718-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Many philosophers have claimed that normative error theorists are committed to the claim ‘Error theory is true, but I have no reason to believe it’, which to some appears paradoxical. Case (2019) has claimed that the normative error theorist cannot avoid this paradox. In this paper, we argue that there is no paradox in the first place, that is once we clear up the ambiguity of the word ‘reason’, both on the error theorist’s side and those that claim that there is a self-defeat problem. Upon clarification, we also raise scepticism to what exactly the nature of self-defeat is meant to be.</p>","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-01-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139515594","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What Counts as Cheating? Deducibility, Imagination, and the Mary Case 什么算作弊?可推导性、想象力和玛丽案例
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-01-18 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00717-5
Amy Kind

In The Matter of Consciousness, in the course of his extended discussion and defense of Frank Jackson’s famous knowledge argument, Torin Alter dismisses some objections on the grounds that they are cases of cheating. Though some opponents of the knowledge argument offer various scenarios in which Mary might come to know what seeing red is like while still in the room, Alter argues that the proposed scenarios are irrelevant. In his view, the Mary case is offered to defend the claim that phenomenal facts cannot be a priori deduced from physical facts. Thus, a proposed scenario constitutes an objection to the knowledge argument only if it presents a case in which Mary’s learning inside the room comes about via a priori deduction from physical facts. Call this the deducibility standard. In what follows, I’ll explore a series of relevant cases in an effort to clarify this standard. Doing so enables us to better understand how cheating should be assessed in this context and thereby also to get clearer on the argumentative dialectic surrounding the Mary case.

在《意识的问题》一书中,托林-阿尔特在对弗兰克-杰克逊著名的知识论进行深入讨论和辩护时,驳斥了一些反对意见,理由是它们是作弊的案例。虽然知识论证的一些反对者提出了各种玛丽可能在房间里就知道看到红色是什么样子的情况,但阿尔特认为,提出的这些情况都是无关紧要的。他认为,提出玛丽的案例是为了捍卫现象事实不能先验地从物理事实中推导出来的说法。因此,只有在提出玛丽在房间里的学习是通过对物理事实的先验推导而产生的情况下,提议的情景才构成对知识论证的反对。这就是可演绎性标准。在下文中,我将探讨一系列相关案例,以澄清这一标准。这样做能让我们更好地理解在这种情况下应该如何评估作弊行为,从而也能更清楚地了解围绕玛丽案的争论辩证法。
{"title":"What Counts as Cheating? Deducibility, Imagination, and the Mary Case","authors":"Amy Kind","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00717-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00717-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In <i>The Matter of Consciousness</i>, in the course of his extended discussion and defense of Frank Jackson’s famous knowledge argument, Torin Alter dismisses some objections on the grounds that they are cases of cheating. Though some opponents of the knowledge argument offer various scenarios in which Mary might come to know what seeing red is like while still in the room, Alter argues that the proposed scenarios are irrelevant. In his view, the Mary case is offered to defend the claim that phenomenal facts cannot be <i>a priori</i> deduced from physical facts. Thus, a proposed scenario constitutes an objection to the knowledge argument only if it presents a case in which Mary’s learning inside the room comes about via <i>a priori</i> deduction from physical facts. Call this <i>the deducibility standard</i>. In what follows, I’ll explore a series of relevant cases in an effort to clarify this standard. Doing so enables us to better understand how cheating should be assessed in this context and thereby also to get clearer on the argumentative dialectic surrounding the Mary case.</p>","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-01-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139515784","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Replies to Vendrell Ferran, Piercey, Schechtman, and Collins 对 Vendrell Ferran、Piercey、Schechtman 和 Collins 的答复
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-01-17 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00713-9
Jukka Mikkonen
{"title":"Replies to Vendrell Ferran, Piercey, Schechtman, and Collins","authors":"Jukka Mikkonen","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00713-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00713-9","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-01-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139616211","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Selves, Persons, and the Neo-Lucretian Symmetry Problem 自我、人格与新卢克莱修对称问题
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-01-16 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-023-00710-4
Patrick Stokes

The heavily discussed (neo-)Lucretian symmetry argument holds that as we are indifferent to nonexistence before birth, we should also be indifferent to nonexistence after death. An important response to this argument insists that prenatal nonexistence differs from posthumous nonexistence because we could not have been born earlier and been the same ‘thick’ psychological self. As a consequence, we can’t properly ask whether it would be better for us to have had radically different lives either. Against this, it’s been claimed we can form preferences as to which ‘thick’ (psychological) self our ‘thin’ (metaphysical) self would be better off ‘associated’ with. I argue that these discussions draw the right distinction, but do so in the wrong place: understanding the ‘thin’ self phenomenally instead of metaphysically allows us to understand how we can rationally form preferences to have been somebody else.

讨论较多的(新)卢克莱修对称论证认为,既然我们对出生前的不存在漠不关心,那么我们也应该对死后的不存在漠不关心。对这一论点的一个重要回应坚持认为,出生前的不存在不同于死后的不存在,因为我们不可能更早出生,也不可能是同一个 "厚重的 "心理自我。因此,我们也无法正确地追问,如果我们拥有截然不同的人生,是否会更好。针对这一点,有人声称我们可以形成偏好,即我们的 "薄"(形而上学)自我最好与哪个 "厚"(心理)自我 "联系 "在一起。我认为,这些讨论做出了正确的区分,但却搞错了地方:从现象学而非形而上学的角度理解 "单薄 "的自我,可以让我们理解我们如何能够理性地选择成为另一个人。
{"title":"Selves, Persons, and the Neo-Lucretian Symmetry Problem","authors":"Patrick Stokes","doi":"10.1007/s11406-023-00710-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-023-00710-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The heavily discussed (neo-)Lucretian symmetry argument holds that as we are indifferent to nonexistence before birth, we should also be indifferent to nonexistence after death. An important response to this argument insists that prenatal nonexistence differs from posthumous nonexistence because we could not have been born earlier and been the same ‘thick’ psychological self. As a consequence, we can’t properly ask whether it would be better for us to have had radically different lives either. Against this, it’s been claimed we can form preferences as to which ‘thick’ (psychological) self our ‘thin’ (metaphysical) self would be better off ‘associated’ with. I argue that these discussions draw the right distinction, but do so in the wrong place: understanding the ‘thin’ self phenomenally instead of metaphysically allows us to understand how we can rationally form preferences to have been somebody else.</p>","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-01-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139499068","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Heterophenomenology: A Limited Critique 异现象学:有限的批判
IF 0.5 4区 哲学 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-01-15 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-024-00711-x

Abstract

Dennett (Synthese, 53(2), 159–180, 1982, 1991, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 19–30, 2003, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 247–270, 2007) proposes and defends a method called heterophenomenology. Heterophenomenology is a method to study consciousness from a third-person objective point of view as opposed to a first-person subjective point of view or (auto)-phenomenology. The method of heterophenomenology serves a necessary role in Dennett’s schema of bridging the gap between the manifest and the scientific image of the world. In this paper, I attempt to present a limited critique of the method of heterophenomenology. The objection raised in this paper is limited to one of the steps involved in the method, i.e., the interpretation of the heterophenomenological text as analogous to novelist fiction. I attempt to show that the assumptions made by Dennett about the interpretation of fiction are contradictory in nature and therefore the same cannot be applied to the interpretation of a heterophenomenological text. The assumptions fail in justifying the interpretation of fiction itself and hence exporting them by analogy to interpret a heterophenomenological text is a mistake.

摘要 邓尼特(《综合》,53(2),159-180,1982,1991,《意识研究杂志》,10(9-10),19-30,2003,《现象学与认知科学》,6,247-270,2007)提出并捍卫了一种名为 "异现象学"(heterophenomenology)的方法。相对于第一人称主观视角或(自)现象学,异现象学是一种从第三人称客观视角研究意识的方法。在丹尼特弥合世界的显象与科学形象之间差距的图式中,异相现象学方法发挥了必要的作用。在本文中,我试图对异现象学的方法提出有限的批评。本文提出的反对意见仅限于该方法中的一个步骤,即把异相现象学文本解释为类似于小说家的虚构。我试图说明,丹尼特对小说解释所做的假设在本质上是矛盾的,因此同样的假设不能适用于异现象学文本的解释。这些假设无法证明对小说本身的解释是合理的,因此通过类比输出这些假设来解释异相学文本是错误的。
{"title":"Heterophenomenology: A Limited Critique","authors":"","doi":"10.1007/s11406-024-00711-x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00711-x","url":null,"abstract":"<h3>Abstract</h3> <p>Dennett (<em>Synthese,</em> <em>53</em>(2), 159–180, <span>1982</span>, <span>1991</span>, <em>Journal of Consciousness Studies,</em> <em>10</em>(9–10), 19–30, <span>2003</span>, <em>Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,</em> <em>6</em>, 247–270, <span>2007</span>) proposes and defends a method called <em>heterophenomenology</em>. Heterophenomenology is a method to study consciousness <em>from a third-person objective point of view</em> as opposed to a first-person subjective point of view or (auto)-phenomenology. The method of heterophenomenology serves a necessary role in Dennett’s schema of bridging the gap between the manifest and the scientific image of the world. In this paper, I attempt to present a limited critique of the method of heterophenomenology. The objection raised in this paper is limited to one of the steps involved in the method, i.e., the interpretation of the heterophenomenological text as analogous to novelist fiction. I attempt to show that the assumptions made by Dennett about the interpretation of fiction are contradictory in nature and therefore the same cannot be applied to the interpretation of a heterophenomenological text. The assumptions fail in justifying the interpretation of fiction itself and hence exporting them by analogy to interpret a heterophenomenological text is a mistake.</p>","PeriodicalId":46695,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHIA","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2024-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139468915","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
PHILOSOPHIA
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1