首页 > 最新文献

Review of Philosophy and Psychology最新文献

英文 中文
Transitive Inference over Affective Representations in Non-Human Animals 非人类动物情感表征的转义推理
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-09-11 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00749-6
Sanja Srećković

The mainstream philosophical approach to inference, which insists on sentence-like representations and a linguistic capability, excludes non-human animals as possible agents capable of making inferences. However, an abundance of studies show that many animal species exhibit behaviors that seem to rely on some kind of reasoning. My focus here are the transitive inference tasks, which most species solve quite successfully. These findings put pressure on the mainstream views, and still lack a convincing explanation. I introduce the concept of affective representations, which satisfy the semantic and structural requirements for participating in inferences. I also argue for a broader conception of inference, and show how we can apply this view to explain the results of the transitive inference studies. Finally, I suggest it is more useful to think of flexibility of thought in terms of a continuous range, rather than a dichotomy of flexible vs. inflexible.

推理的主流哲学方法坚持使用类似句子的表征和语言能力,将非人类动物排除在能够进行推理的可能主体之外。然而,大量研究表明,许多动物物种的行为似乎都依赖于某种推理。我在这里重点讨论的是反式推理任务,大多数物种都能相当成功地完成这些任务。这些发现给主流观点带来了压力,但仍然缺乏令人信服的解释。我引入了情感表征的概念,它满足了参与推理的语义和结构要求。我还主张采用更广泛的推理概念,并说明我们如何运用这一观点来解释反式推理研究的结果。最后,我建议从一个连续的范围来思考思维的灵活性,而不是灵活与不灵活的二分法。
{"title":"Transitive Inference over Affective Representations in Non-Human Animals","authors":"Sanja Srećković","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00749-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00749-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The mainstream philosophical approach to inference, which insists on sentence-like representations and a linguistic capability, excludes non-human animals as possible agents capable of making inferences. However, an abundance of studies show that many animal species exhibit behaviors that seem to rely on some kind of reasoning. My focus here are the transitive inference tasks, which most species solve quite successfully. These findings put pressure on the mainstream views, and still lack a convincing explanation. I introduce the concept of affective representations, which satisfy the semantic and structural requirements for participating in inferences. I also argue for a broader conception of inference, and show how we can apply this view to explain the results of the transitive inference studies. Finally, I suggest it is more useful to think of flexibility of thought in terms of a continuous range, rather than a dichotomy of flexible vs. inflexible.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-09-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142223193","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Self-Deception: A Case Study in Folk Conceptual Structure 自我欺骗:民间概念结构案例研究
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-08-15 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00743-y
Carme Isern-Mas, Ivar R. Hannikainen

Theoretical debates around the concept of self-deception revolve around identifying the conditions for a behavior to qualify as self-deception. Experiments 1 and 2 revealed that various candidate features—such as intent, belief change, and motive—are treated as sufficient, but non-necessary, conditions according to the lay concept of self-deception. This led us to ask whether there are multiple lay concepts, such that different participants endorse competing theories (the disagreement view), or whether individual participants assign partial weight to various features and consequently waver in cases of middling similarity (the conflict view). In Experiment 3, by-participant regression models uncovered that most participants additively consider multiple characteristics of the prototype of self-deception, while only a minority of participants treat a characteristic (or a combination thereof) as necessary and sufficient. In sum, by disambiguating interpersonal disagreement and intrapersonal conflict in a within-subjects design, the present experiments indicate that the lay concept may primarily exhibit a prototype structure. In closing, we suggest that future research deploying this method may help to explain why experimental research on philosophical concepts often engenders partial support for competing theories.

围绕自欺概念的理论争论主要集中在确定一种行为符合自欺条件的问题上。实验 1 和 2 显示,根据非专业人士的自欺概念,各种候选特征--如意图、信念改变和动机--被视为充分但非必要的条件。这让我们想到,是否存在多种非专业概念,以至于不同的参与者支持相互竞争的理论(分歧观点),或者是否个别参与者对各种特征赋予了部分权重,从而在相似度中等的情况下摇摆不定(冲突观点)。在实验 3 中,通过参与者回归模型发现,大多数参与者会加法考虑自我欺骗原型的多个特征,而只有少数参与者会将某一特征(或其组合)视为必要且充分的特征。总之,通过在被试内设计中区分人际分歧和人际冲突,本实验表明外行概念可能主要表现出一种原型结构。最后,我们建议未来的研究采用这种方法,这可能有助于解释为什么有关哲学概念的实验研究经常为相互竞争的理论提供部分支持。
{"title":"Self-Deception: A Case Study in Folk Conceptual Structure","authors":"Carme Isern-Mas, Ivar R. Hannikainen","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00743-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00743-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Theoretical debates around the concept of self-deception revolve around identifying the conditions for a behavior to qualify as self-deception. Experiments 1 and 2 revealed that various candidate features—such as intent, belief change, and motive—are treated as sufficient, but non-necessary, conditions according to the lay concept of self-deception. This led us to ask whether there are multiple lay concepts, such that different participants endorse competing theories (the disagreement view), or whether individual participants assign partial weight to various features and consequently waver in cases of middling similarity (the conflict view). In Experiment 3, by-participant regression models uncovered that most participants additively consider multiple characteristics of the prototype of self-deception, while only a minority of participants treat a characteristic (or a combination thereof) as necessary and sufficient. In sum, by disambiguating interpersonal disagreement and intrapersonal conflict in a within-subjects design, the present experiments indicate that the lay concept may primarily exhibit a prototype structure. In closing, we suggest that future research deploying this method may help to explain why experimental research on philosophical concepts often engenders partial support for competing theories.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-08-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142223194","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophy for Preschoolers? A Critical Review to Promote informed Implementation of P4C in Preschools 学前儿童的哲学?促进学前班知情实施 P4C 的批判性评论
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-08-11 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00747-8
Hélène Maire, Emmanuèle Auriac-Slusarczyk

Between the elitist “philosophy is for grown-ups” and the demagogic “everyone can be a philosopher”, where does Philosophy for Children (P4C) belong in preschools? What is it assumed, expected, or intended to achieve? How is it implemented? This article reviews the literature evaluating the impact of P4C practices on preschool children (aged 3–6). It identifies the main actual or purported obstacles signaled by educators to argue that philosophy cannot be practiced before age 6. It then appraises, from a cognitive developmental psychology perspective, the reality of these supposed obstacles, considering the underlying developmental skills that very young children may lack compared with older ones. Finally, pedagogical adjustments to P4C school practices are suggested, illustrated, and discussed to adapt this program, initially designed and documented for elementary-school children, to the potential of preschoolers.

在 "哲学是大人的事 "的精英主义和 "人人都能成为哲学家 "的蛊惑人心之间,儿童哲学(P4C)在学前教育中属于什么位置?它的假设、预期或目的是什么?如何实施?本文回顾了评估 "儿童哲学 "实践对学龄前儿童(3-6 岁)影响的文献。文章指出了教育工作者认为哲学不能在 6 岁前实施的主要实际障碍或声称的障碍。然后,从认知发展心理学的角度,考虑到与年龄较大的儿童相比,年龄很小的儿童可能缺乏潜在的发展技能,对这些所谓障碍的真实性进行评估。最后,对 P4C 学校实践的教学调整提出了建议、进行了说明并展开了讨论,以使这一最初为小学生设计并记录在案的项目适应学龄前儿童的潜力。
{"title":"Philosophy for Preschoolers? A Critical Review to Promote informed Implementation of P4C in Preschools","authors":"Hélène Maire, Emmanuèle Auriac-Slusarczyk","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00747-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00747-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Between the elitist “philosophy is for grown-ups” and the demagogic “everyone can be a philosopher”, where does Philosophy for Children (P4C) belong in preschools? What is it assumed, expected, or intended to achieve? How is it implemented? This article reviews the literature evaluating the impact of P4C practices on preschool children (aged 3–6). It identifies the main actual or purported obstacles signaled by educators to argue that philosophy cannot be practiced before age 6. It then appraises, from a cognitive developmental psychology perspective, the reality of these supposed obstacles, considering the underlying developmental skills that very young children may lack compared with older ones. Finally, pedagogical adjustments to P4C school practices are suggested, illustrated, and discussed to adapt this program, initially designed and documented for elementary-school children, to the potential of preschoolers.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-08-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141947106","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Where Does Cardinality Come From? 卡性从何而来?
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-08-06 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00746-9
Markus Pantsar, Bahram Assadian

How do we acquire the notions of cardinality and cardinal number? In the (neo-)Fregean approach, they are derived from the notion of equinumerosity. According to some alternative approaches, defended and developed by Husserl and Parsons among others, the order of explanation is reversed: equinumerosity is explained in terms of cardinality, which, in turn, is explained in terms of our ordinary practices of counting. In their paper, ‘Cardinality, Counting, and Equinumerosity’, Richard Kimberly Heck proposes that instead of equinumerosity or counting, cardinality is derived from a cognitively earlier notion of just as many. In this paper, we assess Heck’s proposal in terms of contemporary theories of number concept acquisition. Focusing on bootstrapping theories, we argue that there is no evidence that the notion of just as many is cognitively primary. Furthermore, since the acquisition of cardinality is an enculturated process, the cognitive primariness of these notions, possibly including just as many, depends on various external cultural factors. Therefore, being possibly a cultural construction, just as many could be one among several notions used in the acquisition of cardinality and cardinal number concepts. This paper thus challenges those accounts which seek for a fundamental concept underlying all aspects of numerical cognition.

我们如何获得 "万有引力 "和 "万有引力数 "的概念?按照(新)弗雷格的方法,它们是从等差数列的概念中衍生出来的。根据胡塞尔和帕森斯等人所捍卫和发展的另一种方法,解释的顺序是相反的:等数性是根据万有性来解释的,而万有性又是根据我们普通的计数实践来解释的。理查德-金伯利-赫克(Richard Kimberly Heck)在其论文《万国牌、计数和等数性》中提出,万国牌不是等数性或计数,而是源自认知上更早的 "一样多 "概念。在本文中,我们将从当代数字概念习得理论的角度来评估赫克的提议。以引导理论为重点,我们认为没有证据表明 "一样多 "的概念在认知上是首要的。此外,由于 "万有引力 "的习得是一个文化熏陶的过程,这些概念(可能包括 "一样多")的认知首要性取决于各种外部文化因素。因此,"一样多 "可能是一种文化建构,它可能是在习得万有引力和万有引力数概念时使用的几个概念中的一个。因此,本文对那些寻求数字认知所有方面的基本概念的说法提出了质疑。
{"title":"Where Does Cardinality Come From?","authors":"Markus Pantsar, Bahram Assadian","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00746-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00746-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p>How do we acquire the notions of cardinality and cardinal number? In the (neo-)Fregean approach, they are derived from the notion of equinumerosity. According to some alternative approaches, defended and developed by Husserl and Parsons among others, the order of explanation is reversed: equinumerosity is explained in terms of cardinality, which, in turn, is explained in terms of our ordinary practices of counting. In their paper, ‘Cardinality, Counting, and Equinumerosity’, Richard Kimberly Heck proposes that instead of equinumerosity or counting, cardinality is derived from a cognitively earlier notion of <i>just as many</i>. In this paper, we assess Heck’s proposal in terms of contemporary theories of number concept acquisition. Focusing on bootstrapping theories, we argue that there is no evidence that the notion of <i>just as many</i> is cognitively primary. Furthermore, since the acquisition of cardinality is an enculturated process, the cognitive primariness of these notions, possibly including <i>just as many</i>, depends on various external cultural factors. Therefore, being possibly a cultural construction, <i>just as many</i> could be one among several notions used in the acquisition of cardinality and cardinal number concepts. This paper thus challenges those accounts which seek for a fundamental concept underlying all aspects of numerical cognition.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-08-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141947107","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Collaborative Inhibition: A Phenomenological Perspective 合作抑制:现象学视角
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-08-05 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00748-7
Daniel Gyollai

The tendency for people to remember less as members of a group than they would be capable of were they to remember alone is a phenomenon known as collaborative inhibition. The article offers a phenomenological account of this highly counterintuitive effect of group remembering. It argues that the mutual failure to live up to one’s potential does not warrant the standard, strongly negative views about the role of others in recall. Rather, the phenomenon may imply that sharedness itself becomes constitutive of the process in the sense that interaction partners co-determine what and how to remember. Drawing on phenomenological approaches to remembering and second-person engagement, the article argues that individuals participating in shared remembering co-construct their memories by reciprocally and dynamically incorporating each other’s perspectives, attitudes, and emotions about their shared past.

人们作为群体成员的记忆能力往往低于他们单独记忆的能力,这种现象被称为协作抑制。文章从现象学角度解释了群体记忆的这种高度反直觉效应。文章认为,相互无法发挥各自的潜能,并不意味着对他人在记忆中的作用持有标准的、强烈的负面看法。相反,这种现象可能意味着,在互动伙伴共同决定记忆的内容和方式的意义上,共享性本身成为了记忆过程的构成要素。文章借鉴了记忆和第二人称参与的现象学方法,论证了参与共同记忆的个体通过互惠和动态地吸收彼此对共同过去的观点、态度和情感来共同构建他们的记忆。
{"title":"Collaborative Inhibition: A Phenomenological Perspective","authors":"Daniel Gyollai","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00748-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00748-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The tendency for people to remember less as members of a group than they would be capable of were they to remember alone is a phenomenon known as <i>collaborative inhibition</i>. The article offers a phenomenological account of this highly counterintuitive effect of group remembering. It argues that the mutual failure to live up to one’s potential does not warrant the standard, strongly negative views about the role of others in recall. Rather, the phenomenon may imply that sharedness itself becomes constitutive of the process in the sense that interaction partners co-determine what and how to remember. Drawing on phenomenological approaches to remembering and second-person engagement, the article argues that individuals participating in shared remembering co-construct their memories by reciprocally and dynamically incorporating each other’s perspectives, attitudes, and emotions about their shared past.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-08-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141946984","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Beyond Cognition and Affect: An Analysis of Anorexia Nervosa within the Framework of Addiction 超越认知与情感:在成瘾框架内分析神经性厌食症
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-07-13 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00745-w
Nevia Dolcini

Anorexia Nervosa is widely recognized as having both cognitive and affective dimensions. Current accounts typically explain the perplexing behaviors associated with this eating disorder by emphasizing either its cognitive components—particularly false beliefs related to the denial of the patient’s actual conditions—or its affective components, such as the intense fear of gaining weight. I will argue that neither approach is sufficient to fully capture the complexity of Anorexia Nervosa. This paper explores a more comprehensive approach that goes beyond the cognition-affect dichotomy, aligning better with the DSM-5 criteria for Anorexia Nervosa. These criteria suggest that while both affective and cognitive components play significant roles, neither the cognitive element nor the affective element is necessary or sufficient to define the condition on its own. I propose that this can be achieved by drawing an analogy with addiction, where both conditions can be seen as stemming from and maintained by an all-consuming fixation that permeates individuals’ lives and profoundly influences their behaviors. In Anorexia Nervosa, this fixation manifests as a pervasive preoccupation with body size and weight. What distinguishes these behaviors is their internal self-endorsement, aligning with the well-documented ego-syntonic nature of Anorexia Nervosa: sufferers perceive these behaviors as consistent with their feelings, values, and ideals, making them resistant to change. Understanding Anorexia Nervosa within the framework of addiction, particularly by recognizing the pivotal role of ego-syntonic fixation, allows for a more comprehensive approach to the disorder that sheds light on its high resistance to treatment and the challenges faced in clinical interventions.

厌食症被广泛认为具有认知和情感两个层面。目前的研究通常通过强调厌食症的认知因素(尤其是与否认患者实际情况相关的错误信念)或情感因素(如对体重增加的强烈恐惧)来解释与这种饮食失调症相关的令人困惑的行为。我将论证这两种方法都不足以完全概括神经性厌食症的复杂性。本文探讨了一种更全面的方法,这种方法超越了认知与情感的二分法,更符合 DSM-5 关于神经性厌食症的标准。这些标准表明,虽然情感和认知因素都起着重要作用,但认知因素和情感因素都不是单独定义厌食症的必要或充分条件。我建议通过与成瘾进行类比来实现这一点,因为这两种病症都可以被看作是源于并由一种贯穿个人生活并深刻影响其行为的全然固着所维持的。在神经性厌食症中,这种固着表现为对体型和体重的普遍关注。这些行为的不同之处在于其内在的自我认可,这与有充分证据表明的神经性厌食症的自我同步性相一致:患者认为这些行为与他们的情感、价值观和理想相一致,从而使他们抗拒改变。在成瘾的框架内理解神经性厌食症,尤其是认识到自我同步固着的关键作用,可以更全面地看待这种疾病,从而揭示其治疗的高阻力以及临床干预所面临的挑战。
{"title":"Beyond Cognition and Affect: An Analysis of Anorexia Nervosa within the Framework of Addiction","authors":"Nevia Dolcini","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00745-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00745-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Anorexia Nervosa is widely recognized as having both cognitive and affective dimensions. Current accounts typically explain the perplexing behaviors associated with this eating disorder by emphasizing either its cognitive components—particularly false beliefs related to the denial of the patient’s actual conditions—or its affective components, such as the intense fear of gaining weight. I will argue that neither approach is sufficient to fully capture the complexity of Anorexia Nervosa. This paper explores a more comprehensive approach that goes beyond the cognition-affect dichotomy, aligning better with the DSM-5 criteria for Anorexia Nervosa. These criteria suggest that while both affective and cognitive components play significant roles, neither the cognitive element nor the affective element is necessary or sufficient to define the condition on its own. I propose that this can be achieved by drawing an analogy with addiction, where both conditions can be seen as stemming from and maintained by an all-consuming fixation that permeates individuals’ lives and profoundly influences their behaviors. In Anorexia Nervosa, this fixation manifests as a pervasive preoccupation with body size and weight. What distinguishes these behaviors is their internal self-endorsement, aligning with the well-documented ego-syntonic nature of Anorexia Nervosa: sufferers perceive these behaviors as consistent with their feelings, values, and ideals, making them resistant to change. Understanding Anorexia Nervosa within the framework of addiction, particularly by recognizing the pivotal role of ego-syntonic fixation, allows for a more comprehensive approach to the disorder that sheds light on its high resistance to treatment and the challenges faced in clinical interventions.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-07-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141609946","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Probing the Unorthodox: Moderate Direct Control over Implicit Bias 探索非正统:适度直接控制隐性偏见
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-07-12 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00739-8
Philip Mack

The consensus among philosophers is that indirect control is the only plausible type of control that individuals can exercise over implicit bias. By contrast, direct control over implicit bias is dismissed as implausible. It is dismissed on two grounds. First, direct control is susceptible to the rebound effect. Second, the nature of implicit bias belies direct control. This paper grates against the prevailing philosophical consensus by defending direct control against its dismissal. Accordingly, I argue that the rebound effect is not a knock-down-drag-out phenomenon against direct control. I further argue that philosophers have an unnuanced view of the rebound effect and represent it in ways that betray inaccuracies. I argue that this opens up some space to develop a moderate view of direct control over implicit bias. The view I develop is rooted in dual-system theory and the findings of experimental social psychology and neuroscience. Taken together, the evidence suggests two things: (1) the nature of implicit bias does not always belie direct control, and (2) that a moderate type of direct control over implicit bias is plausible. I end with a caution against treating indirect control as the standard-bearer for control over implicit bias. Indirect control is secured by undertaking control-based intervention techniques. But evidence suggests that the effects of these techniques fade over time. I do not suggest, however, that indirect control be jettisoned. Instead, I propose that it be used as a strategy along with moderate direct control such that no ameliorative avenue is foreclosed.

哲学家们的共识是,间接控制是个人对内隐偏见唯一可信的控制类型。相比之下,对内隐偏见的直接控制被认为是不可信的。其理由有二。首先,直接控制容易受到反弹效应的影响。其次,内隐偏差的性质也否定了直接控制。本文一反流行的哲学共识,为直接控制辩护,反对否定直接控制。因此,我认为,反弹效应并不是一种对直接控制的击倒-拖垮现象。我进一步指出,哲学家们对反弹效应的看法有失偏颇,对它的表述也有不准确之处。我认为,这为发展一种温和的直接控制内隐偏见的观点开辟了一些空间。我所提出的观点植根于双系统理论以及实验社会心理学和神经科学的研究成果。综合来看,这些证据表明了两点:(1) 内隐偏见的本质并不总是意味着直接控制;(2) 对内隐偏见的适度类型的直接控制是可信的。最后,我提醒大家不要把间接控制当作控制内隐偏见的标准。间接控制是通过采取基于控制的干预技术来保证的。但有证据表明,这些方法的效果会随着时间的推移而减弱。不过,我并不建议放弃间接控制。相反,我建议将间接控制作为一种策略,与适度的直接控制一起使用,这样就不会切断任何改善途径。
{"title":"Probing the Unorthodox: Moderate Direct Control over Implicit Bias","authors":"Philip Mack","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00739-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00739-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The consensus among philosophers is that indirect control is the only plausible type of control that individuals can exercise over implicit bias. By contrast, direct control over implicit bias is dismissed as implausible. It is dismissed on two grounds. First, direct control is susceptible to the rebound effect. Second, the nature of implicit bias belies direct control. This paper grates against the prevailing philosophical consensus by defending direct control against its dismissal. Accordingly, I argue that the rebound effect is not a knock-down-drag-out phenomenon against direct control. I further argue that philosophers have an unnuanced view of the rebound effect and represent it in ways that betray inaccuracies. I argue that this opens up some space to develop a moderate view of direct control over implicit bias. The view I develop is rooted in dual-system theory and the findings of experimental social psychology and neuroscience. Taken together, the evidence suggests two things: (1) the nature of implicit bias does not always belie direct control, and (2) that a moderate type of direct control over implicit bias is plausible. I end with a caution against treating indirect control as the standard-bearer for control over implicit bias. Indirect control is secured by undertaking control-based intervention techniques. But evidence suggests that the effects of these techniques fade over time. I do not suggest, however, that indirect control be jettisoned. Instead, I propose that it be used as a strategy along with moderate direct control such that no ameliorative avenue is foreclosed.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-07-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141609947","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What Is Wrong with Aesthetic Empiricism? An Experimental Study 审美经验主义有什么问题?一项实验研究
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-07-01 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00744-x
Clément Canonne, Pierre Saint-Germier

According to Aesthetic Empiricism, only the features of artworks accessible by sensory perception can be aesthetically relevant. In other words, aesthetic properties supervene on perceptual properties. Although commonly accepted in early analytic aesthetics, Aesthetic Empiricism has been the target of a number of thought experiments popularized by Gombrich, Walton, and Levinson, purporting to show that perceptually indiscernible artworks may differ aesthetically. In particular, this literature exploits three kinds of differences among perceptually indiscernible artworks that may account for aesthetic differences: relative to categories of art, historical provenance, or means of production. Like in all philosophical thought experiments, the reliability of the elicited intuitions remains an empirical question that we address here with the methods of experimental philosophy. Throughout three studies, we show that most people do not believe that non-perceptual properties can modulate our evaluation of an artwork’s beauty. However, intuitions were much more divided when considering expressive aesthetic properties (such as intensity), and even clearly reversed when considering artistic properties (such as originality or technical achievement). Overall, our studies show that the central intuitions elicited by the classical indiscernibility arguments strongly depend on the class of manipulated properties (expressive aesthetic properties vs formal aesthetic properties; aesthetic properties vs artistic properties) and are thus more suited to refute artistic empiricism than aesthetic empiricism, narrowly construed.

审美经验主义认为,只有感官知觉所能触及的艺术品特征才具有审美相关性。换句话说,审美特性服从于知觉特性。尽管审美经验主义在早期的分析美学中被普遍接受,但在贡布里希、沃尔顿和莱文森的推动下,审美经验主义成为了许多思想实验的目标,这些思想实验旨在证明感知上无法辨别的艺术品在审美上可能存在差异。特别是,这篇文献利用了感知上无法辨别的艺术品之间的三种差异来解释审美差异:相对于艺术类别、历史出处或制作手段。与所有哲学思维实验一样,我们在这里用实验哲学的方法来探讨所激发的直觉的可靠性问题。通过三项研究,我们发现大多数人并不认为非感知属性会影响我们对艺术品美感的评价。然而,在考虑表现性审美属性(如强度)时,直觉的分歧要大得多,而在考虑艺术属性(如独创性或技术成就)时,直觉的分歧甚至明显相反。总之,我们的研究表明,经典的不可辨性论证所引发的核心直觉在很大程度上取决于所操纵的属性类别(表现性审美属性与形式性审美属性;审美属性与艺术属性),因此比狭义的审美经验主义更适合反驳艺术经验主义。
{"title":"What Is Wrong with Aesthetic Empiricism? An Experimental Study","authors":"Clément Canonne, Pierre Saint-Germier","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00744-x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00744-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p>According to Aesthetic Empiricism, only the features of artworks accessible by sensory perception can be aesthetically relevant. In other words, aesthetic properties supervene on perceptual properties. Although commonly accepted in early analytic aesthetics, Aesthetic Empiricism has been the target of a number of thought experiments popularized by Gombrich, Walton, and Levinson, purporting to show that perceptually indiscernible artworks may differ aesthetically. In particular, this literature exploits three kinds of differences among perceptually indiscernible artworks that may account for aesthetic differences: relative to categories of art, historical provenance, or means of production. Like in all philosophical thought experiments, the reliability of the elicited intuitions remains an empirical question that we address here with the methods of experimental philosophy. Throughout three studies, we show that most people do not believe that non-perceptual properties can modulate our evaluation of an artwork’s beauty. However, intuitions were much more divided when considering expressive aesthetic properties (such as intensity), and even clearly reversed when considering artistic properties (such as originality or technical achievement). Overall, our studies show that the central intuitions elicited by the classical indiscernibility arguments strongly depend on the class of manipulated properties (expressive aesthetic properties vs formal aesthetic properties; aesthetic properties vs artistic properties) and are thus more suited to refute artistic empiricism than aesthetic empiricism, narrowly construed.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141504265","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Amodal Completion: Mental Imagery or 3D Modeling? 阿莫多尔完成:心理想象还是 3D 建模?
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-07-01 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00740-1
Christopher Gauker

In amodal completion the mind in some sense completes the visual perceptual representation of a scene by representing parts of the scene hidden behind other objects. Cognitive science has had a lot to say about how amodal completion occurs but has had little to say about the format of the representations involved and the way in which they represent. Some philosophers hold that amodal completions take the form of sensory imaginings of the occluded portions. This theory poses a puzzle for both philosophy and neuroscience about how the occluded parts are imagined to be located relative to the unoccluded parts. A better theory begins with the observation that for many purposes it is useful to suppose that the mind contains mental models of three-dimensional structure. Visual perceptions and mental images may be conceived as mental models that represent external scenes by virtue of homomorphism and which possess both a deep aspect, representing both visible and occluded three-dimensional structure, and a perspectival aspect, representing only an arrangement of visible surfaces. In these terms we can explain various problem-solving abilities, such as the ability to imagine what a scene will look like from another point of view. Amodal completions can be treated as deep perceptual representations of three-dimensional structure. Thus amodal completions do not consist of mental imagery, but they can be used to generate mental imagery representing how a scene would look from alternative points of view.

在 "模态完成"(amodal completion)中,思维在某种意义上通过表现隐藏在其他物体后面的场景部分来完成场景的视觉感知表征。认知科学对模态完成是如何发生的有很多论述,但对所涉及的表征形式及其表征方式却知之甚少。一些哲学家认为,模态完成的形式是对被遮蔽部分的感官想象。这种理论给哲学和神经科学都带来了一个难题,即如何想象被遮蔽部分相对于未被遮蔽部分的位置。更好的理论首先要观察到,在许多情况下,假设大脑包含三维结构的心理模型是有用的。视觉感知和心理图像可以被看作是心理模型,它们通过同构性来表现外部场景,并同时具有深度和视角两个方面,前者代表可见和隐蔽的三维结构,后者只代表可见表面的排列。我们可以用这些术语来解释各种解决问题的能力,例如想象场景从另一个角度看会是什么样子的能力。模态补全可被视为三维结构的深层感知表征。因此,模态补全并不包含心理想象,但它们可以用来产生心理想象,代表一个场景从其他角度看会是什么样子。
{"title":"Amodal Completion: Mental Imagery or 3D Modeling?","authors":"Christopher Gauker","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00740-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00740-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In amodal completion the mind in some sense completes the visual perceptual representation of a scene by representing parts of the scene hidden behind other objects. Cognitive science has had a lot to say about how amodal completion occurs but has had little to say about the format of the representations involved and the way in which they represent. Some philosophers hold that amodal completions take the form of sensory imaginings of the occluded portions. This theory poses a puzzle for both philosophy and neuroscience about how the occluded parts are imagined to be located relative to the unoccluded parts. A better theory begins with the observation that for many purposes it is useful to suppose that the mind contains mental models of three-dimensional structure. Visual perceptions and mental images may be conceived as mental models that represent external scenes by virtue of homomorphism and which possess both a deep aspect, representing both visible and occluded three-dimensional structure, and a perspectival aspect, representing only an arrangement of visible surfaces. In these terms we can explain various problem-solving abilities, such as the ability to imagine what a scene will look like from another point of view. Amodal completions can be treated as deep perceptual representations of three-dimensional structure. Thus amodal completions do not consist of mental imagery, but they can be used to generate mental imagery representing how a scene would look from alternative points of view.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141504263","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Engaging with Conspiracy Believers 与阴谋论信徒接触
IF 2 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-06-24 DOI: 10.1007/s13164-024-00741-0
Karen M. Douglas, Robbie M. Sutton, Mikey Biddlestone, Ricky Green, Daniel Toribio-Flórez

Conspiracy theories abound in social and political discourse, believed by millions of people around the world. In this article, we highlight when it is important to engage with people who believe in conspiracy theories and review recent literature highlighting how best to do so. We first summarise research on the potentially damaging consequences of conspiracy beliefs for individuals, including consequences related to psychopathology. We also focus on the consequences for groups, and societies, and the importance of understanding and addressing conspiracy beliefs. We then review recent literature on how to engage with people who believe in conspiracy theories, specifically with the goal to reduce susceptibility to conspiracy theories and other types of misinformation. We focus on interpersonal strategies to communicate with individuals who believe in conspiracy theories, and large-scale strategies designed to reduce conspiracy beliefs within broader communities.

阴谋论在社会和政治言论中比比皆是,全世界有数百万人相信它。在这篇文章中,我们强调了与相信阴谋论的人接触的重要性,并回顾了最近的文献,重点介绍了如何最好地与他们接触。我们首先总结了有关阴谋论信仰对个人的潜在破坏性后果的研究,包括与精神病理学相关的后果。我们还关注对群体和社会造成的后果,以及理解和解决阴谋论信仰问题的重要性。然后,我们回顾了最近关于如何与相信阴谋论的人接触的文献,特别是以减少对阴谋论和其他类型错误信息的易感性为目标。我们重点关注与相信阴谋论的个人进行沟通的人际策略,以及旨在减少更广泛社区中阴谋论信仰的大规模策略。
{"title":"Engaging with Conspiracy Believers","authors":"Karen M. Douglas, Robbie M. Sutton, Mikey Biddlestone, Ricky Green, Daniel Toribio-Flórez","doi":"10.1007/s13164-024-00741-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-024-00741-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Conspiracy theories abound in social and political discourse, believed by millions of people around the world. In this article, we highlight when it is important to engage with people who believe in conspiracy theories and review recent literature highlighting how best to do so. We first summarise research on the potentially damaging consequences of conspiracy beliefs for individuals, including consequences related to psychopathology. We also focus on the consequences for groups, and societies, and the importance of understanding and addressing conspiracy beliefs. We then review recent literature on how to engage with people who believe in conspiracy theories, specifically with the goal to reduce susceptibility to conspiracy theories and other types of misinformation. We focus on interpersonal strategies to communicate with individuals who believe in conspiracy theories, and large-scale strategies designed to reduce conspiracy beliefs within broader communities.</p>","PeriodicalId":47055,"journal":{"name":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141504264","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Review of Philosophy and Psychology
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1