首页 > 最新文献

University of Chicago Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
The Nanny Corporation 保姆公司
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2009-02-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1348235
M. Henderson
Individuals in common pools-employees in firms, shareholders in firms, individuals in insurance plans, and citizens in a jurisdiction - want the managers of those common pools to act paternalistically toward other individuals, because this lowers the costs of being in the pool. The nanny state, which bans smoking in public places and imposes innumerable sin taxes, and the nanny corporation, which is starting to force employees to be more healthy, are simply responding to this demand. These two can thought of as competing in the "market for paternalism" to deliver paternalism to individuals that demand it. Where nannyism is inevitable, as it is in a world in which others pay, the question then becomes which of the two sources of nanny rules - the state or the firm - is the most efficient supplier of paternalism. This essay describes numerous reasons why corporate nannies are superior to their state analogs in some cases. For instance, corporate policies are subjected to more instantaneous feedback from labor markets, which reduces overreaching but also helps solve information problems in ways likely to reduce the sum of decision and error costs. There is, however, no theory under which the state or firm will always be superior at imposing nanny limitations on behavior. Because of this, we might expect firms to supply nanny rules when it is efficient for them to do so, say because of better monitoring, lower agency costs, or the like, and not to do so when government rules could be supplied at lower cost for a given efficacy level. The problem, however, is that there are government rules, regulations, statutes, constitutional provisions, and case law that may distort the market from efficiency. This essay makes the case for corporate nannyism and shows how government regulation may be biased without justification in favor of the nanny state.
公共资金池中的个人——公司雇员、公司股东、保险计划中的个人和司法管辖区的公民——希望这些公共资金池的管理者对其他个人表现出家长式的态度,因为这降低了参与公共资金池的成本。禁止在公共场所吸烟并征收无数罪恶税的保姆国家,以及开始强迫员工更健康的保姆公司,都只是对这种需求的回应。这两者可以被认为是在“家长制市场”上竞争,将家长制传递给需要它的个人。在保姆主义不可避免的地方,就像在一个由他人买单的世界里一样,那么问题就变成了保姆规则的两个来源——国家还是公司——哪一个是家长作风最有效的提供者。这篇文章描述了为什么公司保姆在某些情况下优于国家保姆的许多原因。例如,公司政策受到劳动力市场更多即时反馈的影响,这减少了过度扩张,但也有助于以可能减少决策和错误成本总和的方式解决信息问题。然而,没有理论表明,国家或公司在对行为施加保姆限制方面总是更胜一筹。正因为如此,我们可能会期望公司在这样做是有效的时候提供保姆规则,比如因为更好的监督,更低的代理成本,或者类似的,而不是当政府规则可以以更低的成本提供给定的功效水平时这样做。但问题是,有可能扭曲市场效率的政府规章、条例、法令、宪法规定和判例法。这篇文章阐述了企业保姆主义,并展示了政府监管如何在没有正当理由的情况下偏向保姆国家。
{"title":"The Nanny Corporation","authors":"M. Henderson","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1348235","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1348235","url":null,"abstract":"Individuals in common pools-employees in firms, shareholders in firms, individuals in insurance plans, and citizens in a jurisdiction - want the managers of those common pools to act paternalistically toward other individuals, because this lowers the costs of being in the pool. The nanny state, which bans smoking in public places and imposes innumerable sin taxes, and the nanny corporation, which is starting to force employees to be more healthy, are simply responding to this demand. These two can thought of as competing in the \"market for paternalism\" to deliver paternalism to individuals that demand it. Where nannyism is inevitable, as it is in a world in which others pay, the question then becomes which of the two sources of nanny rules - the state or the firm - is the most efficient supplier of paternalism. This essay describes numerous reasons why corporate nannies are superior to their state analogs in some cases. For instance, corporate policies are subjected to more instantaneous feedback from labor markets, which reduces overreaching but also helps solve information problems in ways likely to reduce the sum of decision and error costs. There is, however, no theory under which the state or firm will always be superior at imposing nanny limitations on behavior. Because of this, we might expect firms to supply nanny rules when it is efficient for them to do so, say because of better monitoring, lower agency costs, or the like, and not to do so when government rules could be supplied at lower cost for a given efficacy level. The problem, however, is that there are government rules, regulations, statutes, constitutional provisions, and case law that may distort the market from efficiency. This essay makes the case for corporate nannyism and shows how government regulation may be biased without justification in favor of the nanny state.","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"14 1","pages":"1517-1612"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2009-02-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89382231","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Changing Name Changing: Framing Rules and the Future of Marital Names 改变名字:框架规则和婚姻名字的未来
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2008-05-06 DOI: 10.7916/D8Z0385D
Elizabeth F. Emens
Marital names shape our ideas about marriage, about our children, and about our selves. For about a hundred years, American states required married women to take their husbands' names in order to engage in basic civic activities such as voting. While the law no longer requires women to change their names, it still shapes people's decisions about marital names in both formal and informal ways. For example, the formal legal default rule in most places is that both spouses keep their premarital names. This rule is minoritarian for women, which means it imposes a range of social costs on women who make the most conventional naming choice. But the rule is majoritarian for men, which means it does nothing to unsettle the most robust aspect of our current marital naming conventions - the fact that men almost never change their names, even to hyphenate. This fact about men's names - coupled with the fact that children almost always have their father's name, even if their mother makes an unconventional naming choice for herself - means that women are ostensibly choosing their marital names, but in fact they are choosing from a very limited decision set. That is, women effectively can have nominal continuity either with their past (their families of origin and premarital selves) or with their future (their children and possibly their spouse), but not across all three generations. The formal legal default that both spouses keep their names reinforces this bind for women. Informally, legal institutions also shape choices through desk-clerk law, that is, advice given by the government functionaries who answer public inquiries at state and local agencies. These legal actors frequently mislead people and discourage unconventional naming choices as a result of ignorance or their own views about proper practice. Because states historically reinforced a regime of patrilineal descent of names, what might seem a neutral default regime is inadequate. States should set defaults and frame choices to encourage more egalitarian decisions about whether to change names and how. States could try any number of creative solutions using existing categories for thinking about choice regimes, drawn from contract-law theory: default rules (what rule the state fills in if the parties don't speak to the contrary); menus (what range of options parties are given); and altering rules (what steps parties must take to contract around the default rule into different alternatives). Most modestly, states could adopt a forced choosing approach, requiring both spouses to state their postmarital names. More ambitiously, states might encourage hyphenation and, at the next generation, biphenation - defined as the passing of one name from each hyphenated parent - by making this the default option. States could also create what might be called framing rules, which would dictate how the state asks the question of parties in a choice regime. Framing rules encompass what information the state gives
婚名塑造了我们对婚姻、孩子和自我的看法。在大约一百年的时间里,美国各州要求已婚妇女随其丈夫的姓,以便参加投票等基本的公民活动。虽然法律不再要求女性改名,但它仍然以正式和非正式的方式影响着人们对婚姻姓氏的决定。例如,在大多数地方,正式的法律默认规则是夫妻双方保留婚前的名字。这条规则对女性来说是少数人的,这意味着它给那些选择最传统的名字的女性施加了一系列的社会成本。但这条规则对男性来说是多数主义的,这意味着它不会动摇我们目前婚姻命名惯例中最牢固的一面——事实上,男性几乎从不改变他们的名字,即使是连字符。男人名字的这一事实——再加上孩子几乎总是随父亲的名字,即使他们的母亲给自己取了一个非常规的名字——意味着表面上是女性在选择她们的结婚名字,但实际上她们的选择范围非常有限。也就是说,女性实际上可以与她们的过去(原籍家庭和婚前自我)或未来(她们的孩子,可能还有配偶)保持名义上的连续性,但不能跨越三代。正式的法律默认,夫妻双方都保留自己的名字,这加强了女性的这种束缚。非正式地,法律机构还通过“案记员法”(desk-clerk law)来塑造选择,即由在州和地方机构回答公众询问的政府官员提供建议。这些法律行为者经常误导人们,由于无知或他们自己对正确做法的看法,他们不鼓励非传统的命名选择。由于国家在历史上强化了姓氏的父系血统制度,看似中立的默认制度是不够的。各州应该设定默认值并制定选择框架,以鼓励在是否改名以及如何改名方面做出更平等的决定。各州可以尝试任何创造性的解决方案,使用现有的类别来思考选择制度,从合同法理论中得出:默认规则(如果各方不反对,国家填写什么规则);菜单(提供给各方的选择范围);以及改变规则(各方必须采取哪些步骤来绕过默认规则,形成不同的替代规则)。最温和的做法是,各州可以采取强制选择的方式,要求夫妻双方说出他们的婚后姓名。更有野心的是,各州可能会鼓励使用连字符,并在下一代采用双字符——定义为从每个使用连字符的父母那里继承一个名字——将其作为默认选项。各州还可以制定所谓的框架规则,这将规定各州如何在选择制度中向各方提出问题。框架规则包括国家向当事人提供的信息、使用的词语、围绕问题的上下文以及问题的时间。框架规则在某些情况下尤其重要,例如婚姻姓名,在这些情况下,社会习俗对选择有很大影响,而文书法可能是错误或误导的。
{"title":"Changing Name Changing: Framing Rules and the Future of Marital Names","authors":"Elizabeth F. Emens","doi":"10.7916/D8Z0385D","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8Z0385D","url":null,"abstract":"Marital names shape our ideas about marriage, about our children, and about our selves. For about a hundred years, American states required married women to take their husbands' names in order to engage in basic civic activities such as voting. While the law no longer requires women to change their names, it still shapes people's decisions about marital names in both formal and informal ways. For example, the formal legal default rule in most places is that both spouses keep their premarital names. This rule is minoritarian for women, which means it imposes a range of social costs on women who make the most conventional naming choice. But the rule is majoritarian for men, which means it does nothing to unsettle the most robust aspect of our current marital naming conventions - the fact that men almost never change their names, even to hyphenate. This fact about men's names - coupled with the fact that children almost always have their father's name, even if their mother makes an unconventional naming choice for herself - means that women are ostensibly choosing their marital names, but in fact they are choosing from a very limited decision set. That is, women effectively can have nominal continuity either with their past (their families of origin and premarital selves) or with their future (their children and possibly their spouse), but not across all three generations. The formal legal default that both spouses keep their names reinforces this bind for women. Informally, legal institutions also shape choices through desk-clerk law, that is, advice given by the government functionaries who answer public inquiries at state and local agencies. These legal actors frequently mislead people and discourage unconventional naming choices as a result of ignorance or their own views about proper practice. Because states historically reinforced a regime of patrilineal descent of names, what might seem a neutral default regime is inadequate. States should set defaults and frame choices to encourage more egalitarian decisions about whether to change names and how. States could try any number of creative solutions using existing categories for thinking about choice regimes, drawn from contract-law theory: default rules (what rule the state fills in if the parties don't speak to the contrary); menus (what range of options parties are given); and altering rules (what steps parties must take to contract around the default rule into different alternatives). Most modestly, states could adopt a forced choosing approach, requiring both spouses to state their postmarital names. More ambitiously, states might encourage hyphenation and, at the next generation, biphenation - defined as the passing of one name from each hyphenated parent - by making this the default option. States could also create what might be called framing rules, which would dictate how the state asks the question of parties in a choice regime. Framing rules encompass what information the state gives ","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"32 1","pages":"763-863"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2008-05-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78097129","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 40
The Dale Problem: Property and Speech Under the Regulatory State 戴尔问题:管制国家下的财产与言论
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2008-01-09 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1082114
Louis Michael Seidman
A contradiction lies at the core of the modern law of speech and property. The contradiction is captured by four propositions, all of which are widely accepted, but all of which cannot be true. Proposition 1: Freedom of speech is not subject to political revision. Proposition 2: Within broad limits, property entitlements are subject to political revision. Proposition 3: The freedom of speech does not include the right to use another person's property in order to convey one's message Proposition 4: All speech requires the use of some property. These four propositions cannot be reconciled. If it is true that economic entitlements, including most property rights, are subject to political revision, and if it is true that there is no right to use another's property for speech, and if it is true that speech requires property, then it cannot also be true that speech rights are immune from political revision. This article explores the ramifications of this simple but puzzling syllogism, using the Supreme Court's decision in Boy Scouts of America v. Dale as a central example. It concludes that contradictions in Supreme Court doctrine at the intersection of property and speech law make both our speech and property regimes less stable than they might at first appear to be.
现代言论与财产法的核心矛盾在于此。这个矛盾被四个命题抓住了,它们都被广泛接受,但不可能都是真的。命题1:言论自由不受政治修改。提案2:在广泛的范围内,财产权利受到政治修改。命题3:言论自由不包括使用他人财产来传达自己信息的权利命题4:所有言论都需要使用某些财产。这四种主张是不能调和的。如果包括大多数财产权在内的经济权利确实会受到政治修正,如果确实没有权利使用他人的财产进行言论,如果确实言论需要财产,那么言论权利也不可能不受政治修正的影响。本文以最高法院对美国童子军诉戴尔案(Boy Scouts of America v. Dale)的判决为中心,探讨了这个简单但令人费解的三段论的后果。它的结论是,在财产法和言论法的交叉点上,最高法院的原则存在矛盾,这使得我们的言论和财产制度都不像最初看起来那么稳定。
{"title":"The Dale Problem: Property and Speech Under the Regulatory State","authors":"Louis Michael Seidman","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1082114","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1082114","url":null,"abstract":"A contradiction lies at the core of the modern law of speech and property. The contradiction is captured by four propositions, all of which are widely accepted, but all of which cannot be true. \u0000Proposition 1: Freedom of speech is not subject to political revision. \u0000Proposition 2: Within broad limits, property entitlements are subject to political revision. \u0000Proposition 3: The freedom of speech does not include the right to use another person's property in order to convey one's message \u0000Proposition 4: All speech requires the use of some property. \u0000These four propositions cannot be reconciled. If it is true that economic entitlements, including most property rights, are subject to political revision, and if it is true that there is no right to use another's property for speech, and if it is true that speech requires property, then it cannot also be true that speech rights are immune from political revision. \u0000This article explores the ramifications of this simple but puzzling syllogism, using the Supreme Court's decision in Boy Scouts of America v. Dale as a central example. It concludes that contradictions in Supreme Court doctrine at the intersection of property and speech law make both our speech and property regimes less stable than they might at first appear to be.","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"22 1","pages":"5"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2008-01-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85090926","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 8
Does Political Bias in the Judiciary Matter?: Implications of Judicial Bias Studies for Legal and Constitutional Reform 司法中的政治偏见重要吗?司法偏见研究对法律和宪法改革的影响
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2008-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1082055
E. Posner
Recent empirical scholarship that shows that judges decide cases in a manner that is consistent with their political biases has motivated a stream of proposals for reform, including judicial term limits, limitations on judicial review of statutes and agency actions, revision of the judicial appointments process, and mandatory mixed party representation on judicial panels. However, these proposals incorrectly assume that judicial bias is necessarily harmful, and do not fully consider the costs to other values even when reduction of judicial bias is justified. To evaluate proposals for reform, one needs a theory of judicial review, one that explains how bias and other characteristics of judicial behavior result in socially good or bad outcomes. This paper supplies such a theory, drawing on rational-choice accounts of the role of the judiciary in the legislative process. It argues that judicial bias is not harmful in a broad range of circumstances, and that the merits of the reform proposals depend on many factors, including, among others, the degree of supermajoritarianism of the legislative process, the magnitude of legislative bargaining costs, judicial competence, and the extent to which the judicial appointments process and party competition result in an ideologically diverse judiciary.
最近的实证研究表明,法官判决案件的方式与其政治偏见相一致,这激发了一系列改革建议,包括司法任期限制,对法规和机构行为的司法审查的限制,修订司法任命程序,以及司法小组中强制性的混合政党代表。然而,这些建议错误地假设司法偏见必然是有害的,即使在减少司法偏见是合理的情况下,也没有充分考虑到其他价值的成本。为了评估改革建议,人们需要一个司法审查理论,一个解释偏见和司法行为的其他特征如何导致社会好的或坏的结果的理论。本文提供了这样一种理论,借鉴了司法机构在立法过程中的作用的理性选择理论。它认为,司法偏见在广泛的情况下是无害的,改革建议的优点取决于许多因素,其中包括立法程序的超级多数主义程度、立法谈判成本的大小、司法能力,以及司法任命程序和政党竞争在多大程度上导致意识形态多样化的司法。
{"title":"Does Political Bias in the Judiciary Matter?: Implications of Judicial Bias Studies for Legal and Constitutional Reform","authors":"E. Posner","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1082055","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1082055","url":null,"abstract":"Recent empirical scholarship that shows that judges decide cases in a manner that is consistent with their political biases has motivated a stream of proposals for reform, including judicial term limits, limitations on judicial review of statutes and agency actions, revision of the judicial appointments process, and mandatory mixed party representation on judicial panels. However, these proposals incorrectly assume that judicial bias is necessarily harmful, and do not fully consider the costs to other values even when reduction of judicial bias is justified. To evaluate proposals for reform, one needs a theory of judicial review, one that explains how bias and other characteristics of judicial behavior result in socially good or bad outcomes. This paper supplies such a theory, drawing on rational-choice accounts of the role of the judiciary in the legislative process. It argues that judicial bias is not harmful in a broad range of circumstances, and that the merits of the reform proposals depend on many factors, including, among others, the degree of supermajoritarianism of the legislative process, the magnitude of legislative bargaining costs, judicial competence, and the extent to which the judicial appointments process and party competition result in an ideologically diverse judiciary.","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"6 1","pages":"853"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2008-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79697313","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 75
Overseers or 'The Deciders': The Courts in Administrative Law 监督者或“决定者”:行政法中的法院
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2007-11-22 DOI: 10.7916/D8862GC2
P. Strauss
The Real World of Arbitrariness Review (q.v.) supplements Professors Miles and Sunsteins' valuable empirical analysis of federal court of appeals Chevron decisions, with a similar analysis of merits review of EPA and NLRB actions they associate with the Court's contemporary decision in State Farm. Their analysis shows political patterns that are perhaps not surprising; one should perhaps celebrate the evidence of effective moderation on mixed panels, although doubting whether measures intended to produce such panels might tend more to legitimize than to cure the politicization of judging. This brief responsive essay begins by setting out a framework for understanding Chevron, State Farm and other recent standard-of-review cases (e.g., Mead Corp.). The whole issue, it argues, is one of allocation: differentiating those issues that courts must decide for themselves, from those their process of decision leads them to conclude have been validly committed to the care of others, subject to residual judicial oversight. The oversight function, and consequently both State Farm and the second step of Chevron analysis, is governed by the statute controlling judicial review of administrative action (5 USC 706) and the constitutional imperatives underlying delegation concerns. Seen in this light, it is suggested, these cases are considerably less troublesome and complicated than commonly appears from the literature. Turning to the Miles-Sunstein data, the paper questions whether it suggests any causal relation from Chevron and/or State Farm, as results like these could presumably be found in NLRB cases (the bulk of their present data set) for the decades prior to the mid-80's decisions in those two cases. NLRB cases, moreover, do not entail State Farm review in the usual sense. One particular concern of this paper is that easing up on State Farm hard look review, an apparent recommendation from their analysis, would further diminish the influence of those within the administration who care about well reasoned and scientifically supported analysis over those who are more disposed to bend science in the interest of politics. Not knowing how reviewing panels will be constituted, agencies facing hard look must prepare for rigorous review of movement in either conservative or liberal directions; free of that prospect, they would lose this incentive and science could be more readily bent. If it is so that politics inevitably has some influence on judging, it hardly follows that relief from judging somewhat distorted by this influence will produce better administrative judgment, rather than more effective acts of political will.
《武断审查的真实世界》(qv)补充了迈尔斯教授和桑斯坦教授对联邦上诉法院雪佛龙判决的宝贵实证分析,并对EPA和NLRB的行为进行了类似的分析,他们将其与法院在州立农场一案中的判决联系起来。他们的分析显示出的政治模式或许并不令人惊讶;人们也许应该庆祝在混合小组中有效节制的证据,尽管怀疑旨在产生这种小组的措施是否更倾向于合法化而不是治愈审判的政治化。这篇简短的回应文章首先提出了一个理解雪佛龙、州立农场和其他最近的标准审查案例(如米德公司)的框架。它认为,整个问题是一个分配问题:将法院必须自己决定的问题与法院的决定过程导致它们得出结论的那些问题区分开来,这些问题已被有效地委托给他人照顾,并受到剩余的司法监督。监督职能,因此州立农场和雪佛龙分析的第二步,都受到控制行政行为司法审查的法规(5 USC 706)和授权关注的宪法要求的约束。从这个角度来看,有人认为,这些病例比通常从文献中出现的要少得多的麻烦和复杂。转向迈尔斯-桑斯坦的数据,论文质疑它是否表明雪佛龙和/或州立农场之间存在因果关系,因为这样的结果可能在NLRB的案件中找到(他们目前的大部分数据集),在80年代中期对这两个案件做出裁决之前的几十年里。此外,国家劳资关系委员会的案件不需要对州立农场进行通常意义上的审查。这篇论文特别关注的一点是,放松对State Farm的严格审查,这是他们分析中明显的建议,将进一步削弱政府内部那些关心合理和科学支持的分析的人对那些更倾向于为了政治利益而扭曲科学的人的影响力。由于不知道审查小组将如何组成,面临严厉审查的机构必须准备好对保守或自由方向的行动进行严格审查;如果没有这种前景,他们就会失去这种动力,科学就会更容易被歪曲。如果政治不可避免地对判断产生某种影响,那么很难得出这样的结论:摆脱这种影响在一定程度上扭曲了的判断,将产生更好的行政判断,而不是更有效的政治意愿行为。
{"title":"Overseers or 'The Deciders': The Courts in Administrative Law","authors":"P. Strauss","doi":"10.7916/D8862GC2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8862GC2","url":null,"abstract":"The Real World of Arbitrariness Review (q.v.) supplements Professors Miles and Sunsteins' valuable empirical analysis of federal court of appeals Chevron decisions, with a similar analysis of merits review of EPA and NLRB actions they associate with the Court's contemporary decision in State Farm. Their analysis shows political patterns that are perhaps not surprising; one should perhaps celebrate the evidence of effective moderation on mixed panels, although doubting whether measures intended to produce such panels might tend more to legitimize than to cure the politicization of judging. This brief responsive essay begins by setting out a framework for understanding Chevron, State Farm and other recent standard-of-review cases (e.g., Mead Corp.). The whole issue, it argues, is one of allocation: differentiating those issues that courts must decide for themselves, from those their process of decision leads them to conclude have been validly committed to the care of others, subject to residual judicial oversight. The oversight function, and consequently both State Farm and the second step of Chevron analysis, is governed by the statute controlling judicial review of administrative action (5 USC 706) and the constitutional imperatives underlying delegation concerns. Seen in this light, it is suggested, these cases are considerably less troublesome and complicated than commonly appears from the literature. Turning to the Miles-Sunstein data, the paper questions whether it suggests any causal relation from Chevron and/or State Farm, as results like these could presumably be found in NLRB cases (the bulk of their present data set) for the decades prior to the mid-80's decisions in those two cases. NLRB cases, moreover, do not entail State Farm review in the usual sense. One particular concern of this paper is that easing up on State Farm hard look review, an apparent recommendation from their analysis, would further diminish the influence of those within the administration who care about well reasoned and scientifically supported analysis over those who are more disposed to bend science in the interest of politics. Not knowing how reviewing panels will be constituted, agencies facing hard look must prepare for rigorous review of movement in either conservative or liberal directions; free of that prospect, they would lose this incentive and science could be more readily bent. If it is so that politics inevitably has some influence on judging, it hardly follows that relief from judging somewhat distorted by this influence will produce better administrative judgment, rather than more effective acts of political will.","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"55 1","pages":"815-829"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2007-11-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82320018","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Regulating the regulators 监管监管者
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2007-11-09 DOI: 10.2307/1600278
W. Viscusi
Since the 1970s, there has been a tremendous growth in government regulation pertaining to risk and the environment. These efforts have emerged quite legitimately because market processes alone cannot fully address risk-related concerns.' Without some kind of regulation or liability, for example, firms lack appropriate incentives to restrict their pollution. Similarly, when products or activities are extremely risky, if people are not cognizant of the risks they face, the firms generating the hazards may not have adequate incentives to issue warnings. To solve these problems, regulatory agencies have mounted a wide variety of efforts to improve the quality of the air we breathe, the water we drink, the products we use, and the workplaces where we toil. Notwithstanding the legitimate impetus for these regulatory activities, government agencies sometimes overstep their bounds. The presence of market failure creates a potential role for government action, but this action must be well conceived. A clearly misguided and unduly burdensome regulation certainly would not be in society's best interest even if it were intended to address a legitimate social problem. As in other policy contexts, the task is to structure regulatory efforts to promote society's welfare as effectively as possible. The importance of this task stems from the need to ensure that the substantial overall cost of regulatory policies is justified. Estimates suggest that total annual regulatory costs are in the vicinity of $400 to $500 billion.2 Of this amount, approximately $100 billion comprises transfers that do not create a net efficien-
自20世纪70年代以来,政府对风险和环境的监管有了巨大的增长。这些努力的出现是相当合理的,因为单靠市场过程无法完全解决与风险相关的担忧。例如,如果没有某种监管或责任,企业就缺乏限制污染的适当激励。同样,当产品或活动风险极大时,如果人们没有意识到他们所面临的风险,制造危险的公司可能没有足够的动机发出警告。为了解决这些问题,监管机构采取了各种各样的措施来改善我们呼吸的空气、饮用的水、使用的产品和工作场所的质量。尽管这些监管活动有合法的动机,但政府机构有时会越界。市场失灵的存在为政府行动创造了一个潜在的角色,但这种行动必须经过深思熟虑。一项明显被误导且负担过重的监管,即使意在解决一个合理的社会问题,也肯定不符合社会的最佳利益。与其他政策背景一样,我们的任务是构建监管努力,以尽可能有效地促进社会福利。这项任务的重要性源于需要确保监管政策的大量总成本是合理的。据估计,每年的总监管成本约为4000亿至5000亿美元在这一数额中,大约有1 000亿美元是没有产生净效率的转移
{"title":"Regulating the regulators","authors":"W. Viscusi","doi":"10.2307/1600278","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1600278","url":null,"abstract":"Since the 1970s, there has been a tremendous growth in government regulation pertaining to risk and the environment. These efforts have emerged quite legitimately because market processes alone cannot fully address risk-related concerns.' Without some kind of regulation or liability, for example, firms lack appropriate incentives to restrict their pollution. Similarly, when products or activities are extremely risky, if people are not cognizant of the risks they face, the firms generating the hazards may not have adequate incentives to issue warnings. To solve these problems, regulatory agencies have mounted a wide variety of efforts to improve the quality of the air we breathe, the water we drink, the products we use, and the workplaces where we toil. Notwithstanding the legitimate impetus for these regulatory activities, government agencies sometimes overstep their bounds. The presence of market failure creates a potential role for government action, but this action must be well conceived. A clearly misguided and unduly burdensome regulation certainly would not be in society's best interest even if it were intended to address a legitimate social problem. As in other policy contexts, the task is to structure regulatory efforts to promote society's welfare as effectively as possible. The importance of this task stems from the need to ensure that the substantial overall cost of regulatory policies is justified. Estimates suggest that total annual regulatory costs are in the vicinity of $400 to $500 billion.2 Of this amount, approximately $100 billion comprises transfers that do not create a net efficien-","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"30 1","pages":"883 - 883"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2007-11-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85956251","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 31
Emergency Lawmaking After 9/11 and 7/7 911和7/7之后的紧急立法
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2007-10-07 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1019542
Adrian Vermeule
This essay offers case studies of three emergency statutes, all dealing with terrorism and all enacted within less than a year after a major terrorist attack: the September 14, 2001 Authorization to Use Military Force; the USA PATRIOT Act; and the U.K. Terrorism Act 2006. A standard worry about such cases is that the circumstances of emergency lawmaking produce blank-check delegations to the executive. The fog of uncertainty, emotions such as urgency and visceral fear, and the tendency of legislators and the public to rally 'round the flag, all cause legislators to vote the executive massive new powers, regardless of whether those powers are rationally justifiable. This view is descriptively and theoretically flawed. Descriptively, executives in all three episodes lost control of the political dynamics, faced bipartisan resistance or rebellion in the legislature, and ended up obtaining far less than they asked for or desired. Theoretically, emergency conditions have cross-cutting political effects on legislators. The mechanisms and forces operative during emergency lawmaking cut both ways, constraining as well as empowering the executive, with unpredictable net results in particular cases. Although executives usually receive new powers in emergencies, there is no reason to think that they systematically tend to receive more new authority than a rational legislature would provide.
本文提供了三个紧急状态法的案例研究,它们都与恐怖主义有关,而且都是在重大恐怖袭击发生后不到一年的时间内颁布的:2001年9月14日《授权使用军事力量法》;《美国爱国者法案》;以及《2006年英国恐怖主义法案》。对这种情况的一个标准担忧是,紧急立法的情况会给行政部门带来空头支票。不确定性的迷雾,紧迫感和发自内心的恐惧等情绪,以及立法者和公众团结在旗帜周围的倾向,都导致立法者投票给行政部门大量的新权力,而不管这些权力是否合理。这种观点在描述和理论上都是有缺陷的。总的来说,在这三个事件中,高管们都失去了对政治动态的控制,在立法机构中面临两党的抵制或反叛,最终得到的远远少于他们所要求或期望的。从理论上讲,紧急情况对立法者具有跨领域的政治影响。在紧急立法期间运作的机制和力量是双向的,既限制行政部门,也赋予行政部门权力,在特定情况下产生不可预测的最终结果。虽然行政人员通常在紧急情况下获得新的权力,但没有理由认为他们系统地倾向于获得比理性立法机构所能提供的更多的新权力。
{"title":"Emergency Lawmaking After 9/11 and 7/7","authors":"Adrian Vermeule","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1019542","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1019542","url":null,"abstract":"This essay offers case studies of three emergency statutes, all dealing with terrorism and all enacted within less than a year after a major terrorist attack: the September 14, 2001 Authorization to Use Military Force; the USA PATRIOT Act; and the U.K. Terrorism Act 2006. A standard worry about such cases is that the circumstances of emergency lawmaking produce blank-check delegations to the executive. The fog of uncertainty, emotions such as urgency and visceral fear, and the tendency of legislators and the public to rally 'round the flag, all cause legislators to vote the executive massive new powers, regardless of whether those powers are rationally justifiable. This view is descriptively and theoretically flawed. Descriptively, executives in all three episodes lost control of the political dynamics, faced bipartisan resistance or rebellion in the legislature, and ended up obtaining far less than they asked for or desired. Theoretically, emergency conditions have cross-cutting political effects on legislators. The mechanisms and forces operative during emergency lawmaking cut both ways, constraining as well as empowering the executive, with unpredictable net results in particular cases. Although executives usually receive new powers in emergencies, there is no reason to think that they systematically tend to receive more new authority than a rational legislature would provide.","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"61 5 1","pages":"5"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2007-10-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89059486","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
The Primary Jurisdiction Two-Step 初级管辖权分为两步
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2007-10-01 DOI: 10.2307/20141869
Bryson Santaguida
The doctrine of primary jurisdiction applies when a claim is originally cognizable in the courts but involves issues that fall within the special competence of an administrative agency. Under the doctrine, a court can stay litigation and refer such issues to the agency for its decision.' Primary jurisdiction is a cousin of better known abstention doctrines that permit (and sometimes require) federal courts to abstain from addressing issues cognizable by state courts or state agencies.2 The essential difference between primary jurisdiction and these other forms of abstention is that primary jurisdiction furthers comity between federal courts and federal agencies rather than federal courts and state institutions. As the Supreme Court has explained, "[n]o fixed formula exists for applying the doctrine of primary jurisdiction."3 When a federal district court decides if an agency has primary jurisdiction over an issue, it must ask "whether the reasons for the existence of the doctrine are present and whether the purposes it serves will be aided by its application in the particular litigation."' One thing is certain: every grant of primary jurisdiction requires district courts to first interpret enabling statutes and then exercise judicial discretion. Because the propriety of primary jurisdiction includes legal and discretionary considerations, circuit courts face the difficult task of deciding whether to review primary jurisdiction decisions de novo or for abuse of discretion. Statutory interpretation is a matter of law and therefore reviewed de novo. Decisions that turn on the discretion of a trial court are reviewed for an abuse of discretion.
当一项索赔最初可在法院审理,但涉及的问题属于行政机构的特殊权限时,适用初级管辖权原则。根据这一原则,法院可以暂停诉讼,并将此类问题交由行政机关裁决。初级司法管辖权与弃权原则类似,后者允许(有时要求)联邦法院在处理州法院或州机构可认定的问题时弃权初级管辖权与这些其他形式的弃权之间的本质区别在于,初级管辖权促进了联邦法院和联邦机构之间的友好关系,而不是联邦法院和州机构之间的友好关系。正如最高法院所解释的那样,“适用初级管辖权原则并不存在固定的公式。”当联邦地区法院决定某机关是否对某一问题具有主要管辖权时,它必须询问“该原则存在的理由是否存在,以及该原则在特定诉讼中的适用是否有助于达到该原则所要达到的目的。”有一件事是肯定的:每次授予初级管辖权都要求地区法院首先解释授权法规,然后行使司法自由裁量权。由于初级管辖权的适当性包括法律和自由裁量权的考虑,巡回法院面临着决定是否重新审查初级管辖权决定或滥用自由裁量权的困难任务。法定解释是一个法律问题,因此需要重新审查。开启初审法院自由裁量权的决定会被审查是否滥用自由裁量权。
{"title":"The Primary Jurisdiction Two-Step","authors":"Bryson Santaguida","doi":"10.2307/20141869","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/20141869","url":null,"abstract":"The doctrine of primary jurisdiction applies when a claim is originally cognizable in the courts but involves issues that fall within the special competence of an administrative agency. Under the doctrine, a court can stay litigation and refer such issues to the agency for its decision.' Primary jurisdiction is a cousin of better known abstention doctrines that permit (and sometimes require) federal courts to abstain from addressing issues cognizable by state courts or state agencies.2 The essential difference between primary jurisdiction and these other forms of abstention is that primary jurisdiction furthers comity between federal courts and federal agencies rather than federal courts and state institutions. As the Supreme Court has explained, \"[n]o fixed formula exists for applying the doctrine of primary jurisdiction.\"3 When a federal district court decides if an agency has primary jurisdiction over an issue, it must ask \"whether the reasons for the existence of the doctrine are present and whether the purposes it serves will be aided by its application in the particular litigation.\"' One thing is certain: every grant of primary jurisdiction requires district courts to first interpret enabling statutes and then exercise judicial discretion. Because the propriety of primary jurisdiction includes legal and discretionary considerations, circuit courts face the difficult task of deciding whether to review primary jurisdiction decisions de novo or for abuse of discretion. Statutory interpretation is a matter of law and therefore reviewed de novo. Decisions that turn on the discretion of a trial court are reviewed for an abuse of discretion.","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"88 1","pages":"11"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2007-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73520878","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Luck of the Draw: Using Random Case Assignment to Investigate Attorney Ability 抽奖的运气:使用随机案件分配来调查律师的能力
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2007-10-01 DOI: 10.2307/20141859
David S. Abrams, Albert H. Yoon
One of the most challenging problems in legal scholarship is the measurement of attorney ability. Measuring attorney ability presents inherent challenges because the nonrandom pairing of attorney and client in most cases makes it difficult, if not impossible, to distinguish between attorney ability and case selection. Las Vegas felony case data, provided by the Clark County Office of the Public Defender in Nevada, offer a unique opportunity to compare attorney performance. The office assigns its incoming felony cases randomly among its pool of attorneys, thereby creating a natural experiment free from selection bias. We find substantial heterogeneity in attorney performance that cannot be explained simply by differences in case characteristics, and this heterogeneity correlates with attorneys’ individual observable characteristics. Attorneys with longer tenure in the office achieve better outcomes for the client. We find that a veteran public defender with ten years of experience reduces the average length of incarceration by 17 percent relative to a public defender in her first year. While we find no statistical difference based on law school attended or gender, we find evidence that the public defender’s race correlates with sentence length, with Hispanic attorneys obtaining sentences that were up to 26 percent shorter on average than those obtained by black or white attorneys. We also find evidence suggesting that differences in sentencing may be driven partly by different plea bargaining behavior on the part of the public defenders.
法律学术研究中最具挑战性的问题之一是对律师能力的衡量。衡量律师能力存在固有的挑战,因为在大多数情况下,律师和客户的非随机配对使得区分律师能力和案件选择变得困难,如果不是不可能的话。拉斯维加斯重罪案件数据由内华达州克拉克县公设辩护人办公室提供,为比较律师的表现提供了一个独特的机会。该办公室在其律师池中随机分配即将到来的重罪案件,从而创造了一个没有选择偏见的自然实验。我们发现律师表现的实质性异质性不能简单地用案件特征的差异来解释,这种异质性与律师个人的可观察特征相关。在办公室工作的时间越长,为客户带来的结果就越好。我们发现,一个有十年经验的资深公设辩护人比一个第一年的公设辩护人平均减少了17%的监禁时间。虽然我们没有发现基于法学院或性别的统计差异,但我们发现有证据表明,公设辩护人的种族与刑期有关,西班牙裔律师获得的刑期平均比黑人或白人律师短26%。我们还发现证据表明,量刑的差异可能部分是由公设辩护人不同的辩诉交易行为驱动的。
{"title":"The Luck of the Draw: Using Random Case Assignment to Investigate Attorney Ability","authors":"David S. Abrams, Albert H. Yoon","doi":"10.2307/20141859","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/20141859","url":null,"abstract":"One of the most challenging problems in legal scholarship is the measurement of attorney ability. Measuring attorney ability presents inherent challenges because the nonrandom pairing of attorney and client in most cases makes it difficult, if not impossible, to distinguish between attorney ability and case selection. Las Vegas felony case data, provided by the Clark County Office of the Public Defender in Nevada, offer a unique opportunity to compare attorney performance. The office assigns its incoming felony cases randomly among its pool of attorneys, thereby creating a natural experiment free from selection bias. We find substantial heterogeneity in attorney performance that cannot be explained simply by differences in case characteristics, and this heterogeneity correlates with attorneys’ individual observable characteristics. Attorneys with longer tenure in the office achieve better outcomes for the client. We find that a veteran public defender with ten years of experience reduces the average length of incarceration by 17 percent relative to a public defender in her first year. While we find no statistical difference based on law school attended or gender, we find evidence that the public defender’s race correlates with sentence length, with Hispanic attorneys obtaining sentences that were up to 26 percent shorter on average than those obtained by black or white attorneys. We also find evidence suggesting that differences in sentencing may be driven partly by different plea bargaining behavior on the part of the public defenders.","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"25 1","pages":"1"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2007-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"91187813","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 88
The Case for Reviewing Debt/Equity Determinations for Abuse of Discretion 审查滥用自由裁量权的债务/股权决定的案例
IF 2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2007-10-01 DOI: 10.2307/20141863
N. Christensen
For at least thirty-eight years, the circuit courts of appeals have been split over the proper standard of review for a trial court's distinc tion of debt from equity.1 Whether a financial disbursement counts as debt or equity is material to the tax treatment it receives. Underlying this split are two central disagreements. One is academic?whether the debt/equity distinction is ultimately a legal or factual determina tion. The other is practical?whether deferential or independent re view will strike the right balance between decisionmaking accuracy and costs. Courts commonly consider three options for standard of review: clearly erroneous, abuse of discretion, and de novo. But on this issue, the circuits are split four ways, with different circuits advocating for the three principal standards as well as a hybrid utilizing both clearly erroneous and de novo review. The inquiry is complex and dynamic, and clear resolution is needed.2 Courts of appeals have been resolving debt/equity cases for over fifty years. But the dust has not yet settled?just last year the Third Circuit formally adopted its position, joining the majority of circuits in classifying the question as factual and the review as for
至少38年来,巡回上诉法院在初审法院区分债务与股权的适当审查标准上一直存在分歧一笔财务支出是算作债务还是权益,对其所接受的税务处理至关重要。这种分歧背后有两个核心分歧。一个是学术?债务/股权的区别最终是法律上的还是事实上的决定。另一个是实用的吗?无论是恭恭敬敬的还是独立的审查都将在决策准确性和成本之间取得适当的平衡。法院通常考虑三种审查标准:明显错误、滥用自由裁量权和从头开始。但在这个问题上,电路分为四种方式,不同的电路主张三个主要标准,以及混合使用明显错误和从头审查。调查是复杂的、动态的,需要明确的解决方案上诉法院解决债务/股权案件已有50多年的历史。但尘埃还没有落定?就在去年,第三巡回上诉法院正式采纳了自己的立场,加入了大多数巡回上诉法院的行列,将这一问题归为事实,并将审查结果归为
{"title":"The Case for Reviewing Debt/Equity Determinations for Abuse of Discretion","authors":"N. Christensen","doi":"10.2307/20141863","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/20141863","url":null,"abstract":"For at least thirty-eight years, the circuit courts of appeals have been split over the proper standard of review for a trial court's distinc tion of debt from equity.1 Whether a financial disbursement counts as debt or equity is material to the tax treatment it receives. Underlying this split are two central disagreements. One is academic?whether the debt/equity distinction is ultimately a legal or factual determina tion. The other is practical?whether deferential or independent re view will strike the right balance between decisionmaking accuracy and costs. Courts commonly consider three options for standard of review: clearly erroneous, abuse of discretion, and de novo. But on this issue, the circuits are split four ways, with different circuits advocating for the three principal standards as well as a hybrid utilizing both clearly erroneous and de novo review. The inquiry is complex and dynamic, and clear resolution is needed.2 Courts of appeals have been resolving debt/equity cases for over fifty years. But the dust has not yet settled?just last year the Third Circuit formally adopted its position, joining the majority of circuits in classifying the question as factual and the review as for","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"100 1","pages":"5"},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2007-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77578713","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
期刊
University of Chicago Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1