首页 > 最新文献

Philosophical Perspectives最新文献

英文 中文
Are there really any dual-character concepts? 真的有双重性格的概念吗?
IF 2 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-20 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12194
Jonathan Phillips, David Plunkett
There has been growing excitement in recent years about “dual-character” concepts. Philosophers have argued that such concepts can help us make progress on a range of philosophical issues, from aesthetics to law to metaphysics. Dual-character concepts are thought to have a distinctive internal structure, which relates a set of descriptive features to an abstract value, and which allows people to use either the descriptive features or the abstract value for determining the extension of the concept. Here, we skeptically investigate the central argument in favor of their existence. Across three new empirical studies, we systematically demonstrate that the linguistic patterns that dual-character concepts were originally posited to explain are likely better explained by much more general features of language use.
近年来,人们对“双重性”概念越来越感兴趣。哲学家们认为,这些概念可以帮助我们在一系列哲学问题上取得进展,从美学到法律再到形而上学。双重特征概念被认为具有独特的内部结构,它将一组描述性特征与抽象价值联系起来,并允许人们使用描述性特征或抽象价值来确定概念的外延。在这里,我们以怀疑的态度调查支持它们存在的中心论点。在三项新的实证研究中,我们系统地证明,最初假设双字符概念可以解释的语言模式,可能可以用语言使用的更普遍的特征来更好地解释。
{"title":"Are there really any dual-character concepts?","authors":"Jonathan Phillips, David Plunkett","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12194","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12194","url":null,"abstract":"There has been growing excitement in recent years about “dual-character” concepts. Philosophers have argued that such concepts can help us make progress on a range of philosophical issues, from aesthetics to law to metaphysics. Dual-character concepts are thought to have a distinctive internal structure, which relates a set of descriptive features to an abstract value, and which allows people to use either the descriptive features or the abstract value for determining the extension of the concept. Here, we skeptically investigate the central argument in favor of their existence. Across three new empirical studies, we systematically demonstrate that the linguistic patterns that dual-character concepts were originally posited to explain are likely better explained by much more general features of language use.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"42 5","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138513177","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Functionalism and tacit knowledge of grammar 功能主义与隐性语法知识
IF 2 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-17 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12179
David Balcarras
In this article, I argue that if tacit knowledge of grammar is analyzable in functional-computational terms, then it cannot ground linguistic meaning, structure, or sound. If to know or cognize a grammar is to be in a certain computational state playing a certain functional role, there can be no unique grammar cognized. Satisfying the functional conditions for cognizing a grammar G entails satisfying those for cognizing many grammars disagreeing with G about expressions' semantic, phonetic, and syntactic values. This threatens the Chomskyan view that expressions have such values for speakers because they cognize grammars assigning them those values. For if this is true, semantics, syntax, and phonology must be indeterminate, thanks to the indeterminacy of grammar-cognizing (qua functional-computational state). So, the fact that a speaker cognizes a grammar cannot explain the determinate character of their language.
在本文中,我认为,如果语法的隐性知识可以用功能计算术语来分析,那么它就不能作为语言意义、结构或声音的基础。如果知道或认识一种语法就是处于某种计算状态,发挥某种功能作用,那么就不可能有唯一的被认识的语法。要满足认知语法G的功能条件,就必须满足认知许多与G不一致的语法关于表达式的语义、语音和句法价值的功能条件。这威胁到乔姆斯基的观点,即表达对说话者有这样的价值,因为他们认识到语法赋予了他们这些价值。因为如果这是真的,语义、句法和音系一定是不确定的,这要归功于语法认知的不确定性(即功能计算状态)。因此,说话者认识语法这一事实并不能解释其语言的决定性特征。
{"title":"Functionalism and tacit knowledge of grammar","authors":"David Balcarras","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12179","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12179","url":null,"abstract":"In this article, I argue that if tacit knowledge of grammar is analyzable in functional-computational terms, then it cannot ground linguistic meaning, structure, or sound. If to know or cognize a grammar is to be in a certain computational state playing a certain functional role, there can be no unique grammar cognized. Satisfying the functional conditions for cognizing a grammar G entails satisfying those for cognizing many grammars disagreeing with G about expressions' semantic, phonetic, and syntactic values. This threatens the Chomskyan view that expressions have such values for speakers because they cognize grammars assigning them those values. For if this is true, semantics, syntax, and phonology must be indeterminate, thanks to the indeterminacy of grammar-cognizing (qua functional-computational state). So, the fact that a speaker cognizes a grammar cannot explain the determinate character of their language.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"43 6","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":2.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138513176","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Conditional emotions 有条件的情感
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-13 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12184
Christina Hope Dietz
Abstract Some conditional involving factive emotives present a prima facie challenge to the thesis that conditionals obey modus ponens. Drawing on recent work by Timothy Williamson, I offer an error‐theoretic diagnosis of the phenomenon, one that appeals to a heuristic that we use in suppositional reasoning.
一些涉及实际情绪的条件句对“条件句服从命题方式”的论点提出了初步的挑战。根据蒂莫西·威廉姆森(Timothy Williamson)最近的工作,我对这一现象提出了一种错误理论诊断,这种诊断诉诸于我们在假设推理中使用的启发式方法。
{"title":"Conditional emotions","authors":"Christina Hope Dietz","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12184","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12184","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Some conditional involving factive emotives present a prima facie challenge to the thesis that conditionals obey modus ponens. Drawing on recent work by Timothy Williamson, I offer an error‐theoretic diagnosis of the phenomenon, one that appeals to a heuristic that we use in suppositional reasoning.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"46 21","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136347910","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Mental strength: A theory of experience intensity 精神力量:一种经验强度理论
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-07 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12189
Jorge Morales
Abstract Our pains can be more or less intense, our mental imagery can be more or less vivid, our perceptual experiences can be more or less striking. These degrees of intensity of conscious experiences are all manifestations of a phenomenal property I call mental strength . In this article, I argue that mental strength is a domain‐general phenomenal magnitude; in other words, it is a phenomenal quantity shared by all conscious experiences that explains their degree of felt intensity. Mental strength has been largely overlooked in favor of mental states’ type, representational contents, domain‐specific phenomenology, or processes such as attention. Considering mental strength in our reflections about the mind illuminates debates about the relation of representational contents and phenomenal character, and it also helps address questions about the structure and functions of consciousness. Mental strength provides a unifying construct to model what is shared in the phenomenology of different types of conscious experiences.
我们的痛苦可以或多或少地强烈,我们的心理意象可以或多或少地生动,我们的感知体验可以或多或少地引人注目。这些意识体验的强度程度都是一种现象属性的表现,我称之为精神力量。在这篇文章中,我认为精神力量是一个领域-一般现象量级;换句话说,这是所有意识体验共有的现象量,解释了它们感受到的强度程度。由于心理状态的类型、表征内容、特定领域现象学或注意等过程,心理强度在很大程度上被忽视了。在我们对心灵的反思中考虑到精神力量,可以阐明关于表征意旨和现象性特征之间关系的争论,也有助于解决关于意识的结构和功能的问题。精神力量为不同类型的意识体验的现象学提供了一个统一的模型。
{"title":"Mental strength: A theory of experience intensity","authors":"Jorge Morales","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12189","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12189","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Our pains can be more or less intense, our mental imagery can be more or less vivid, our perceptual experiences can be more or less striking. These degrees of intensity of conscious experiences are all manifestations of a phenomenal property I call mental strength . In this article, I argue that mental strength is a domain‐general phenomenal magnitude; in other words, it is a phenomenal quantity shared by all conscious experiences that explains their degree of felt intensity. Mental strength has been largely overlooked in favor of mental states’ type, representational contents, domain‐specific phenomenology, or processes such as attention. Considering mental strength in our reflections about the mind illuminates debates about the relation of representational contents and phenomenal character, and it also helps address questions about the structure and functions of consciousness. Mental strength provides a unifying construct to model what is shared in the phenomenology of different types of conscious experiences.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"2 8","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135541927","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Disagreement and alienation 分歧与疏离
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-30 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12197
Berislav Marušić, Stephen J. White
Abstract This paper proposes to reorient the philosophical debate about peer disagreement. The problem of peer disagreement is normally seen as a problem about the extent to which disagreement provides one with evidence against one's own conclusions. It is thus regarded as a problem for individual inquiry. But things look different in more collaborative contexts. Ethical norms relevant to those contexts make a difference to the epistemology. In particular, we argue that a norm of mutual answerability applies to us when we engage in shared inquiry with others, and precludes us from treating one another's conflicting judgments as evidence relevant to the dispute. From this it follows that standard philosophical accounts of peer disagreement—e.g., the Equal Weight View and the Total Evidence View—presuppose that the disagreeing parties are in a sense alienated from one another. It's doubtful that such forms of alienated disagreement should be treated as the central case.
摘要本文提出重新定位关于同伴分歧的哲学争论。同伴意见分歧的问题通常被视为一个问题,即意见分歧在多大程度上为一个人提供了反对自己结论的证据。因此,它被视为一个个人探究的问题。但在协作性更强的环境中,情况就不同了。与这些背景相关的伦理规范对认识论产生了影响。特别是,我们认为,当我们与他人进行共同调查时,相互负责的规范适用于我们,并阻止我们将彼此相互冲突的判断视为与争议相关的证据。由此可以得出,关于同侪分歧的标准哲学解释——例如:“等权重观点”和“全证据观点”的前提是,持不同意见的各方在某种意义上是相互疏远的。这种形式的异化分歧是否应该被视为核心案例,这是值得怀疑的。
{"title":"Disagreement and alienation","authors":"Berislav Marušić, Stephen J. White","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12197","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12197","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This paper proposes to reorient the philosophical debate about peer disagreement. The problem of peer disagreement is normally seen as a problem about the extent to which disagreement provides one with evidence against one's own conclusions. It is thus regarded as a problem for individual inquiry. But things look different in more collaborative contexts. Ethical norms relevant to those contexts make a difference to the epistemology. In particular, we argue that a norm of mutual answerability applies to us when we engage in shared inquiry with others, and precludes us from treating one another's conflicting judgments as evidence relevant to the dispute. From this it follows that standard philosophical accounts of peer disagreement—e.g., the Equal Weight View and the Total Evidence View—presuppose that the disagreeing parties are in a sense alienated from one another. It's doubtful that such forms of alienated disagreement should be treated as the central case.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"55 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136102397","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Compositionality and constituent structure in the analogue mind 类比思维中的组合性和组成结构
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-27 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12182
Sam Clarke
Abstract I argue that analogue mental representations possess a canonical decomposition into privileged constituents from which they compose. I motivate this suggestion, and rebut arguments to the contrary, through reflection on the approximate number system , whose representations are widely expected to have an analogue format. I then argue that arguments for the compositionality and constituent structure of these analogue representations generalize to other analogue mental representations posited in the human mind, such as those in early vision and visual imagery.
摘要我认为,模拟心理表征具有典型的分解成特权成分,从他们组成。通过对近似数字系统的反思,我提出了这个建议,并反驳了相反的论点,人们普遍认为近似数字系统的表示具有模拟格式。然后我认为,关于这些模拟表征的组合性和构成结构的论点可以推广到人类大脑中其他的模拟心理表征,比如早期视觉和视觉意象。
{"title":"Compositionality and constituent structure in the analogue mind","authors":"Sam Clarke","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12182","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12182","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract I argue that analogue mental representations possess a canonical decomposition into privileged constituents from which they compose. I motivate this suggestion, and rebut arguments to the contrary, through reflection on the approximate number system , whose representations are widely expected to have an analogue format. I then argue that arguments for the compositionality and constituent structure of these analogue representations generalize to other analogue mental representations posited in the human mind, such as those in early vision and visual imagery.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"13 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136262614","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Kripke's knowledge argument against materialism 克里普克反对唯物主义的知识论证
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-26 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12195
Adriana Renero
Abstract In his unpublished 1979 Lectures on the Philosophy of Mind, Saul Kripke offers a knowledge argument against materialism focusing on deaf people who lack knowledge of auditory experience. Kripke's argument is a precursor of Frank Jackson's better‐known knowledge argument against materialism (1982). The paper sets out Kripke's argument, brings out its interest and philosophical importance, and explores some similarities and differences between Kripke's knowledge argument and Jackson's.
在1979年未发表的《心灵哲学讲座》中,索尔·克里普克(Saul Kripke)以缺乏听觉经验知识的聋人为对象,提出了一种反对唯物主义的知识论证。Kripke的论点是Frank Jackson更为人所知的反对唯物主义的知识论点(1982)的先驱。本文阐述了克里普克的观点,揭示了其趣味性和哲学意义,并探讨了克里普克的知识观点与杰克逊的知识观点之间的异同。
{"title":"Kripke's knowledge argument against materialism","authors":"Adriana Renero","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12195","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12195","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In his unpublished 1979 Lectures on the Philosophy of Mind, Saul Kripke offers a knowledge argument against materialism focusing on deaf people who lack knowledge of auditory experience. Kripke's argument is a precursor of Frank Jackson's better‐known knowledge argument against materialism (1982). The paper sets out Kripke's argument, brings out its interest and philosophical importance, and explores some similarities and differences between Kripke's knowledge argument and Jackson's.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"449 3","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134908317","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Neural Decoding, the Atlantis Machine, and Zombies 神经解码,亚特兰蒂斯机器,还有僵尸
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-25 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12181
Rosa Cao, Jared Warren
Abstract Neural decoding studies seem to show that the “private” experiences of others are more accessible than philosophers have traditionally believed. While these studies have many limitations, they do demonstrate that by capturing patterns in brain activity, we can discover a great deal about what a subject is experiencing. We present a thought experiment about a super‐decoder — the Atlantis machine — and argue that given plausible assumptions, an Atlantis machine could one day be built. On the basis of this argument, we then argue for the rejection of robust notions of consciousness, which have generated numerous puzzles, including puzzles about the possibility of philosophical zombies. In light of the Atlantis machine, it can be seen that robust notions of consciousness do not earn their explanatory or descriptive keep. More modest concepts of consciousness are sufficient to account for all phenomena — in both senses of the term. This kind of antirobustness about consciousness is a deflationary approach to conscious experience that differs in important ways from illusionist approaches.
神经解码研究似乎表明,他人的“私人”经历比哲学家传统上认为的更容易理解。虽然这些研究有很多局限性,但它们确实表明,通过捕捉大脑活动的模式,我们可以发现很多关于受试者正在经历的事情。我们提出了一个关于超级解码器的思想实验-亚特兰蒂斯机器-并认为在合理的假设下,亚特兰蒂斯机器有一天会被建造出来。在此论证的基础上,我们主张摒弃强有力的意识概念,这一概念产生了许多难题,包括关于哲学僵尸可能性的难题。在亚特兰蒂斯机器的光芒下,我们可以看到,强健的意识概念并不能获得解释性或描述性的保留。更温和的意识概念足以解释所有的现象——在这个术语的两种意义上。这种关于意识的反鲁棒性是一种对意识体验的紧缩方法,在很多重要的方面不同于幻觉的方法。
{"title":"Neural Decoding, the Atlantis Machine, and Zombies","authors":"Rosa Cao, Jared Warren","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12181","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12181","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Neural decoding studies seem to show that the “private” experiences of others are more accessible than philosophers have traditionally believed. While these studies have many limitations, they do demonstrate that by capturing patterns in brain activity, we can discover a great deal about what a subject is experiencing. We present a thought experiment about a super‐decoder — the Atlantis machine — and argue that given plausible assumptions, an Atlantis machine could one day be built. On the basis of this argument, we then argue for the rejection of robust notions of consciousness, which have generated numerous puzzles, including puzzles about the possibility of philosophical zombies. In light of the Atlantis machine, it can be seen that robust notions of consciousness do not earn their explanatory or descriptive keep. More modest concepts of consciousness are sufficient to account for all phenomena — in both senses of the term. This kind of antirobustness about consciousness is a deflationary approach to conscious experience that differs in important ways from illusionist approaches.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"4 4","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135217421","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Grounding physicalism and the knowledge argument 基础物理主义和知识论证
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-23 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12190
Alex Moran
Abstract Standard responses to the knowledge argument grant that Mary could know all of the physical facts even while trapped inside her black‐and‐white room. What they deny is that upon leaving her black‐and‐white room and experiencing red for the first time, Mary learns a genuinely new fact. This paper develops an alternate response in a grounding physicalist framework, on which Mary does not know all of the physical facts while trapped inside the room. The main thesis is that Mary does not know certain phenomenal facts while trapped inside the room, whereby these facts classify as physical due to being wholly and fully metaphysically grounded in the underlying fundamental facts which are themselves entirely physical.
对知识论证的标准回答是,即使玛丽被困在黑白房间里,她也能知道所有的物理事实。他们否认的是,当玛丽离开她的黑白房间并第一次体验红色时,她了解到一个真正的新事实。本文在基础物理主义框架中提出了另一种反应,在这种框架下,玛丽被困在房间里时并不知道所有的物理事实。主要论点是,当玛丽被困在房间里时,她不知道某些现象性的事实,因此这些事实被归类为物理的,因为它们完全和完全形而上学地建立在潜在的基本事实之上,而这些基本事实本身完全是物理的。
{"title":"Grounding physicalism and the knowledge argument","authors":"Alex Moran","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12190","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12190","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Standard responses to the knowledge argument grant that Mary could know all of the physical facts even while trapped inside her black‐and‐white room. What they deny is that upon leaving her black‐and‐white room and experiencing red for the first time, Mary learns a genuinely new fact. This paper develops an alternate response in a grounding physicalist framework, on which Mary does not know all of the physical facts while trapped inside the room. The main thesis is that Mary does not know certain phenomenal facts while trapped inside the room, whereby these facts classify as physical due to being wholly and fully metaphysically grounded in the underlying fundamental facts which are themselves entirely physical.","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"25 12","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135366171","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A planning theory of belief 一个关于信念的计划理论
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-23 DOI: 10.1111/phpe.12178
Sara Aronowitz
1. What does it mean to hold a belief? Some of our ways of speaking in English suggest that to hold a belief is to have something in your mind: beliefs are things we acquire, defend, recover, and so on (Abelson, 1986). That is, believing is a matter of being in a state of having a thing. In this paper, I will argue for an alternative: believing is something we do. This is not a new suggestion. For instance, Matthew Boyle (2011) defends a theory of belief as an activity, which he traces back to Aristotle. This paper, however, makes two new contributions: first, I argue for an analogy between belief and planning that fleshes out what it would mean to understand belief as an activity, and second, I aim to show how the resulting view can help sense of a variety of theories in cognitive psychology that suggest cognitive information storage is dynamic and reconstructive. Imagine you are eating breakfast while planning your route to work. In virtue of what do you count as planning? The most obvious answer is that you are conducting a certain kind of mental activity, a kind of search for the best (or perhaps merely an acceptable) way to get to work. Further, as I'll argue, this mental activity can't be reduced to holding in one's mind a series of plans – it's possible to be planning without having a plan yet, as when you just start thinking, and plans can also be brought to mind without planning taking place, as in when you implement a plan that was formed earlier on. The belief-as-planning account draws on these features. Our theory of belief should really be a theory of believing, a mental activity that is not reducible to a set of beliefs. By placing this activity at the center of the account, we can now see beliefs, the sets of things, as an abstraction over the activity of believing. This allows for an alternative to pure representationalism or pure dispositionalism: believing is representational, whereas beliefs are a function of this activity in real and counterfactual circumstances. Occupying this middle ground preserves something important about representationalism, namely the idea that belief happens in the mind and can be real even if it has no impact on action. At the same time, the planning account sides with the dispositionalist in allowing a looser relationship between thought and the total set of believed propositions. The structure is as follows. In §2, I bring out two features of non-occurrent beliefs, and in §3, argue that these cause problems for representationalist accounts of belief. These problems indicate a desideratum for accounts of belief: to be psychologically grounded but not dependent on representational form. §4 proposes a simplified model of planning, which forms the basis for an analogy between belief and planning in §5. In the final section, I discuss some upshots and challenges for the proposal. 2. On the intuitive view suggested by English idioms, believing means being in a state of having a thing. Contemporary analyti
这是一个不受欢迎的答案,因为我们认为人们会自相矛盾,例如,在他们只想到佛罗里达会有多好而不考虑他们的背景知识的情况下,佛罗里达现在有飓风。这种矛盾,至少如果我们直截了当地解释的话,指出了发生的和非发生的信念之间的不一致性。如果我们将碎片场景归类为不符合信念标准,这种类型的自相矛盾将与其他情况没有什么不同,在这些情况下,我们有一致的信念,但有时没有利用所有可用的信息:例如,我可能正在制定一个修理自行车轮胎的计划,而没有花时间找出去修理店的路线最省油。发生的信念和信念的片段之间的不一致性似乎是不同的。在这里,非发生的部分不仅与潜在的信念有内在的联系,而且在非连贯的情况下,是连接我的实际信念的纽带。更一般地说,由于出现的想法只代表了一种消极状态的一小部分时间和影响,过于严格的信念标准将排除心理状态之间的许多关系,例如随着时间的推移的一致性,长期推理,以及其他超越出现的想法的过渡。答案会不会是,她现在持有信念是因为她倾向于在未来将其组合起来?即使我们现在假设了表征主义,对于非发生信念的问题,我们可能会允许一个更倾向于配置主义的答案。但假设我们走这条路:只有发生的信念是通过表征来持有的,而像克莱利亚这样的信念则是通过在适当的时间(比如被问到的时候)倾向于持有表征而持有的。这个答案限制了传统观点的范围,因此,要么只有发生的信念才是真正“持有”的,要么相反,我们应该削弱我们持有信念的概念,以捕捉两种形式的关系,即性格和表征。前者的答案与许多日常信念具有不完全表征形式的假设相反,因为我们必须要么承认这些日常状态不是信念,要么承认它们具有不完全表征形式。后者让我们偏离了传统观点,并提出了一些具有挑战性的问题。一个信念概念怎么能同时被表征性实例和性情性实例所满足呢?现在,我们应该排除这样一种可能性,即这仅仅是通过将信念归因弱化为性格归因而起作用,这既违背了我最初对温和表征主义的假设,也意味着表征归因严格地强于性格归因。换句话说,不可能任何时候一个状态S在表征性标准下被归类为信念,同样的状态总是在性格标准下被归类为信念。例如,我可能认为动物的灵魂具有一种深刻而神秘的统一性,因此我相信这种观点(前提是我与这种观点有相关关系)。然而,这种信念可能是如此不精确,难以表达或与其他思想和行为脱节,以至于如果我不持有这样的表象,我就不会倾向于采取不同的行动,思考甚至说话。更一般地说,在许多关于这两种类型的归因(表征性和性情性)如何发挥作用的解释中,归因依赖于非常不同的性质,因此,如果无论表征性归因何时存在,性情性归因总是适用的话,那将是令人惊讶的。但是如果用其他方式把这两种类型联系起来呢?我们可能会接受一种关于信仰归属的析取理论,或者类似地,一种基于家族相似性或集群的理论,在这种理论的基础上,表征性和性格特征都足以让人相信,而不存在一种更抽象的信仰概念,两者都属于这种概念。我不会在这里反对这些观点,但只是认为它们似乎有些令人反感,而且没有回答一个问题,这个问题至少是值得回答的,如果不是必须回答的话:克莱莉亚现在的信仰和她明天的信仰之间有什么共同之处?回答这个问题的第一种方式放弃了从信仰的片段中获得(表征性的)占有。相反,第二种反应试图这样做。 这些碎片和她的信念有什么共同之处?一些选项包括:(a)它们将与她的未来状态有因果关系,(b)它们将与她的未来状态有构成性关系,或(c)它们已经以正确的方式将她与命题联系起来,无论未来会发生什么。当然,这些联系可能有一组或组合是相关的或必要的,让她现在相信。选项(a)和(b)都依赖于未来会发生什么。这产生了一个可预见的问题:假设我们现在有两个相同的克莱利亚斯,但只有其中一个会碰巧被问及邮局,因此被认为现在有了这个信念。当我们讨论过去的一段时间,并问,从那时到现在,克利利亚信仰什么?从这个角度来看,偶然性被移除,过去状态的解释性、因果性或构成性相关性被突出。这些观点与标准观点的基本思想没有任何矛盾,因为同样有可能给出一种理论,例如,作为财产的所有者,纸契约的相关性取决于它是否会继续被兑现的未来偶然性。选项(c)以一种新的形式提出了我最初的问题,即与信念相关的信念的“部分”是什么。撇开上面的答案不谈,我们现在需要一个只利用“碎片”当前状态的答案,即整个人的当前性格或未来联系的作用。也就是说,他们应该站在一个完整信念的关系上这个关系可以解释为什么我们现在认为克莱莉亚持有完整信念,但不依赖于任何未来的或有事件。那么这个连接的线索是什么呢?我们有一种直觉,即从碎片到完整信念的功能将完全不确定——当然,有许多信念可以从“碎片”中形成,特别是考虑到个人独特的认知倾向和倾向的作用。相反,我将建议另一种选择。传统观点被迫解释信仰是如何隐式地呈现在各个片段中,当你把这些片段放在一起时,隐式信仰就实现了。相反,我认为把碎片拼凑在一起的方式就是信念。更准确地说,它是一种信仰:一种作为信仰归属基础的活动。有人可能会反对说,这些消极的论点把信仰的隐喻看得太严肃了。当然,代表性主义是有范围的,把最极端的版本作为我们唯一的目标是错误的。在这里,我反对的只是对表现形式敏感的表现主义形式,因此关心草图和作品之间的区别。我们可以对比一下,弱表征主义,认为P需要有一个整体表征状态或其子集映射到内容P强表征主义,认为P需要有一个与内容P*的表征,其中P*是一个适当相关的命题或P本身。上面的论点并没有反对弱表征主义,因为非发生片段场景的关键特征只是没有特定的表征与她的信仰相对应,也没有从这些特定的“片段”到信仰内容的合适功能。这并不是说,她的整个精神状态和性情对信仰的内容没有适当的作用。但是,虽然强烈的代表性主义似乎难以置信地字面化,但它得到了一些人的辩护(例如,曼德尔鲍姆即将于2019年;Mandelbaum & Bendaña, 2020)。更重要的是,用强烈的表征主义来解决这个问题,将为另一种选择设定一个关键目标:解释非发生信仰与发生信仰之间的关系,并允许信仰随着时间的推移和表征形式的转变而延伸。4. 表征形式的光谱对强表征主义提出了挑战。在本节中,我将开始构建一个具有基本规划模型的替代方案。考虑一下计划去商店意味着什么。通常情况下,你最终肯定会去商店并不足以算作计划去,你肯定会去而且你知道这一点也不够。这涉及到一种不同于单纯意识的认知。然而,计划去商店并不需要有一个心理对象,去商店的计划,有这个对象也不足以算作计划。为了理解这一点,想象一下,有人刚刚开始考虑今天下午要做什么,不知道她应该去美食城还是去El Super。她还没有制定计划——她只是提出了这个问题。 这在我在更新明确的计划表示之前被打断的情况下尤其明显:在这些情况下,模型将根据我当前的进度将我的计划松散地确定为我所承诺的,而不是已经明确表示的。从本质上讲,这个规范是不完整的,可以有不同的解释(例如,我实际要承诺的是什么,我应该承诺的是什么)。在我看来,计划是首要的,计划源于计划的活动。这可能会让读者觉得违反直觉。我首先要说明的是,计划并不等同于有计划。但即使这是真的,我们可能还是会问:计划不总是以计划结束吗?我认为这个id。
{"title":"A planning theory of belief","authors":"Sara Aronowitz","doi":"10.1111/phpe.12178","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12178","url":null,"abstract":"1. What does it mean to hold a belief? Some of our ways of speaking in English suggest that to hold a belief is to have something in your mind: beliefs are things we acquire, defend, recover, and so on (Abelson, 1986). That is, believing is a matter of being in a state of having a thing. In this paper, I will argue for an alternative: believing is something we do. This is not a new suggestion. For instance, Matthew Boyle (2011) defends a theory of belief as an activity, which he traces back to Aristotle. This paper, however, makes two new contributions: first, I argue for an analogy between belief and planning that fleshes out what it would mean to understand belief as an activity, and second, I aim to show how the resulting view can help sense of a variety of theories in cognitive psychology that suggest cognitive information storage is dynamic and reconstructive. Imagine you are eating breakfast while planning your route to work. In virtue of what do you count as planning? The most obvious answer is that you are conducting a certain kind of mental activity, a kind of search for the best (or perhaps merely an acceptable) way to get to work. Further, as I'll argue, this mental activity can't be reduced to holding in one's mind a series of plans – it's possible to be planning without having a plan yet, as when you just start thinking, and plans can also be brought to mind without planning taking place, as in when you implement a plan that was formed earlier on. The belief-as-planning account draws on these features. Our theory of belief should really be a theory of believing, a mental activity that is not reducible to a set of beliefs. By placing this activity at the center of the account, we can now see beliefs, the sets of things, as an abstraction over the activity of believing. This allows for an alternative to pure representationalism or pure dispositionalism: believing is representational, whereas beliefs are a function of this activity in real and counterfactual circumstances. Occupying this middle ground preserves something important about representationalism, namely the idea that belief happens in the mind and can be real even if it has no impact on action. At the same time, the planning account sides with the dispositionalist in allowing a looser relationship between thought and the total set of believed propositions. The structure is as follows. In §2, I bring out two features of non-occurrent beliefs, and in §3, argue that these cause problems for representationalist accounts of belief. These problems indicate a desideratum for accounts of belief: to be psychologically grounded but not dependent on representational form. §4 proposes a simplified model of planning, which forms the basis for an analogy between belief and planning in §5. In the final section, I discuss some upshots and challenges for the proposal. 2. On the intuitive view suggested by English idioms, believing means being in a state of having a thing. Contemporary analyti","PeriodicalId":51519,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Perspectives","volume":"25 8","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135413300","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Philosophical Perspectives
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1