首页 > 最新文献

Sport Ethics and Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Patriarchy in Disguise: Burke on Pike and World Rugby 伪装中的父权制:派克上的伯克和世界橄榄球
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-08-22 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2114534
Miroslav Imbrišević
ABSTRACT World Rugby (WR) announced in 2020 that transwomen should not be competing at the elite level because of safety and fairness concerns. WR and Jon Pike, a philosopher of sport advising them, adopted a lexical approach to get a grip on the three values in play: safety, fairness, and inclusion. Previously, governing bodies tried to balance these competing values. Michael Burke recently published a paper taking aim at Pike’s lexical approach.
世界橄榄球(WR)在2020年宣布,出于安全和公平考虑,跨性别女性不应该参加精英级别的比赛。WR和为他们提供建议的体育哲学家乔恩·派克(Jon Pike)采用了一种词汇方法来把握比赛中的三个价值观:安全、公平和包容。以前,管理机构试图平衡这些相互竞争的价值观。迈克尔·伯克(Michael Burke)最近发表了一篇论文,对派克的词汇方法提出了批评。
{"title":"Patriarchy in Disguise: Burke on Pike and World Rugby","authors":"Miroslav Imbrišević","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2114534","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2114534","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT World Rugby (WR) announced in 2020 that transwomen should not be competing at the elite level because of safety and fairness concerns. WR and Jon Pike, a philosopher of sport advising them, adopted a lexical approach to get a grip on the three values in play: safety, fairness, and inclusion. Previously, governing bodies tried to balance these competing values. Michael Burke recently published a paper taking aim at Pike’s lexical approach.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"37 1","pages":"204 - 222"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-08-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75235901","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Sportswashing: Complicity and Corruption 体育欺诈:共谋和腐败
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-08-02 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2107697
Kyle Fruh, Alfred Archer, Jake Wojtowicz
ABSTRACT When the 2022 FIFA Men’s World Cup was awarded to Qatar, it raised a number of moral concerns, perhaps the most prominent of which was Qatar’s woeful record on human rights in the arena of migrant labour. Qatar’s interest in hosting the event is aptly characterised as a case of ‘sportswashing’. The first aim of this paper is to provide an account of the nature of sportswashing, as a practice of using an association with sport, usually through hosting an event or owning a club (such as Newcastle United, owned by Saudi Arabia), to subvert the way that others attend to a moral violation for which the sportswashing agent is responsible. This may be done through distracting away from wrongdoing, minimising it, or normalising it. Second, we offer an account of the distinctive wrongs of sportswashing. The gravest moral wrong is the background injustice which sportswashing threatens to perpetuate. But the distinctive wrongs of sportswashing are twofold: first, it makes participants in sport (athletes, coaches, journalists, fans) complicit in the sportswasher’s wrongdoing, which extends a moral challenge to millions of people involved with sport. Second, sportswashing corrupts valuable heritage associated with sporting traditions and institutions. Finally, we examine how sportswashing ought to be resisted. The appropriate forms of resistance will depend upon different roles people fill, such as athlete, coach, journalist, fan. The basic dichotomy of resistance strategies is to either exit the condition of complicity, for example by refusing to participate in the sporting event, or to modify one’s engagement with the goal of transformation in mind. We recognize this is difficult and potentially burdensome: sports are an important part of many of our lives; our approach attempts to respect this.
当2022年国际足联男子世界杯主办权被授予卡塔尔时,引发了一系列道德问题,其中最突出的可能是卡塔尔在移民劳工领域的糟糕人权记录。卡塔尔对举办世界杯的兴趣被恰当地描述为“体育洗白”。本文的第一个目的是提供对体育洗白本质的解释,作为一种利用体育协会的做法,通常通过举办一项活动或拥有一家俱乐部(如沙特阿拉伯拥有的纽卡斯尔联队),颠覆其他人参与体育洗白代理人负责的道德违规行为的方式。这可以通过分散对不法行为的注意力、将其最小化或使其正常化来实现。其次,我们提供了一份关于体育丑闻的独特错误的报告。最严重的道德错误是不公正的背景,这种不公正可能会使体育丑闻永久化。但是,体育丑闻的明显错误有两个方面:首先,它使体育运动的参与者(运动员、教练、记者、球迷)与体育丑闻串通一气,这给数百万体育运动参与者带来了道德挑战。其次,体育贿赂腐败了与体育传统和制度相关的宝贵遗产。最后,我们将探讨如何抵制体育欺诈。适当的抵抗形式取决于人们扮演的不同角色,比如运动员、教练、记者、球迷。抵抗策略的基本二分法是,要么退出同谋的状态,例如拒绝参加体育赛事,要么调整自己的参与,以实现心中的转变目标。我们认识到这是困难的,而且可能是繁重的:体育是我们许多人生活的重要组成部分;我们的做法试图尊重这一点。
{"title":"Sportswashing: Complicity and Corruption","authors":"Kyle Fruh, Alfred Archer, Jake Wojtowicz","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2107697","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2107697","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT When the 2022 FIFA Men’s World Cup was awarded to Qatar, it raised a number of moral concerns, perhaps the most prominent of which was Qatar’s woeful record on human rights in the arena of migrant labour. Qatar’s interest in hosting the event is aptly characterised as a case of ‘sportswashing’. The first aim of this paper is to provide an account of the nature of sportswashing, as a practice of using an association with sport, usually through hosting an event or owning a club (such as Newcastle United, owned by Saudi Arabia), to subvert the way that others attend to a moral violation for which the sportswashing agent is responsible. This may be done through distracting away from wrongdoing, minimising it, or normalising it. Second, we offer an account of the distinctive wrongs of sportswashing. The gravest moral wrong is the background injustice which sportswashing threatens to perpetuate. But the distinctive wrongs of sportswashing are twofold: first, it makes participants in sport (athletes, coaches, journalists, fans) complicit in the sportswasher’s wrongdoing, which extends a moral challenge to millions of people involved with sport. Second, sportswashing corrupts valuable heritage associated with sporting traditions and institutions. Finally, we examine how sportswashing ought to be resisted. The appropriate forms of resistance will depend upon different roles people fill, such as athlete, coach, journalist, fan. The basic dichotomy of resistance strategies is to either exit the condition of complicity, for example by refusing to participate in the sporting event, or to modify one’s engagement with the goal of transformation in mind. We recognize this is difficult and potentially burdensome: sports are an important part of many of our lives; our approach attempts to respect this.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"1 1","pages":"101 - 118"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-08-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87089155","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 13
WADA’s Concept of the ’Protected Person’ – and Why it is No Protection for Minors 世界反兴奋剂机构的“受保护人”概念-以及为什么它不保护未成年人
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-07-21 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2091014
M. Campos, J. Parry, I. Martínková
ABSTRACT The recent alleged doping case of the figure skater Kamila Valieva at the Winter Olympic Games in Beijing 2022 dramatically raised the issue of the protection of minors in anti-doping policy. We firstly present the literature on doping in relation to minors. Secondly, we present WADA’s Protected Person (PP) concept and its implications. Thirdly, we analyse the WADA Code’s purpose and the vulnerability of minors under the Code, and fourthly, we identify the real threats from which minors should be protected by analysing the ineffective PP concept, and showing how it cannot be a real protection. We explain how preventing one threat can generate another, thus converting minor athletes from victims into suspects. We conclude by stressing the necessity for further research, and we indicate our future research direction, towards the development of a much wider concept of protection, and its application into sporting contexts.
近日,花样滑冰运动员卡米拉·瓦列娃(Kamila Valieva)在2022年北京冬奥会上涉嫌服用兴奋剂的事件,极大地引发了反兴奋剂政策中对未成年人的保护问题。我们首先介绍了有关未成年人使用兴奋剂的文献。其次,我们介绍了WADA的保护人(PP)概念及其含义。第三,我们分析了《世界反兴奋剂条例》的目的和未成年人在《条例》下的脆弱性;第四,我们通过分析无效的PP概念,找出未成年人应该受到保护的真正威胁,并说明它如何不能成为真正的保护。我们解释了如何防止一个威胁会产生另一个威胁,从而将小运动员从受害者转变为嫌疑人。最后,我们强调了进一步研究的必要性,并指出了我们未来的研究方向,即发展更广泛的保护概念,并将其应用于体育环境。
{"title":"WADA’s Concept of the ’Protected Person’ – and Why it is No Protection for Minors","authors":"M. Campos, J. Parry, I. Martínková","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2091014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2091014","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT The recent alleged doping case of the figure skater Kamila Valieva at the Winter Olympic Games in Beijing 2022 dramatically raised the issue of the protection of minors in anti-doping policy. We firstly present the literature on doping in relation to minors. Secondly, we present WADA’s Protected Person (PP) concept and its implications. Thirdly, we analyse the WADA Code’s purpose and the vulnerability of minors under the Code, and fourthly, we identify the real threats from which minors should be protected by analysing the ineffective PP concept, and showing how it cannot be a real protection. We explain how preventing one threat can generate another, thus converting minor athletes from victims into suspects. We conclude by stressing the necessity for further research, and we indicate our future research direction, towards the development of a much wider concept of protection, and its application into sporting contexts.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"98 1","pages":"58 - 69"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-07-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81126999","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Competitive Team Sport Without External Referees: The Case of the Flying Disc Sport Ultimate 没有外部裁判的竞技团体运动:飞盘运动的终极案例
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-07-21 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2101682
G. Thonhauser
ABSTRACT Ultimate is a competitive team sport that is played, even at the highest level of competition, without external referees. The key to Ultimate as a self-refereed sport is the so-called ‘Spirit of the Game’. As this paper aims to show, the Spirit of the Game closely resembles Habermas’s theory of communicative action. This suggests that Habermas’s theory might be used to spell out the philosophical presuppositions of the Spirit of the Game. Most importantly, the requirements for players to serve as referees of their own game specified in the ‘Rules of Ultimate’ turn out to be reformulation of the four validity claims of communicative action. Moreover, the Spirit of the Game can be interpreted as aiming towards facilitating real-life decision-making procedures that resemble as much as possible Habermas’s concept of an ideal speech situation. On the other hand, Ultimate might serve as a case study for exploring how Habermas’s idea of rational deliberation works in the practice of a competitive sporting environment. Most importantly, it makes manifest that self-refereeing is a trust-based system. This suggests that communicative rationality can only unfold its power—the unforced force of the better argument—within a context in which participants trust that everyone participates in good faith towards the common goal of finding the best decision. Hence, investigating the case of Ultimate allows us to draw broader conclusions about the requirements for rational deliberation to work in practice.
极限是一项竞技性的团队运动,即使是在最高水平的比赛中,也没有外部裁判。作为一项自我裁判的运动,极限运动的关键是所谓的“比赛精神”。正如本文旨在表明的那样,博弈精神与哈贝马斯的交往行为理论非常相似。这表明哈贝马斯的理论可以用来阐明游戏精神的哲学前提。最重要的是,“终极规则”中对玩家作为自己游戏裁判员的要求是对交流行为的四种有效性主张的重新表述。此外,游戏精神可以被解释为旨在促进现实生活中的决策程序,尽可能地类似于哈贝马斯理想演讲情境的概念。另一方面,《终极》可以作为一个案例研究,探索哈贝马斯的理性思考理念如何在竞技体育环境的实践中发挥作用。最重要的是,它表明了自我审查是一个基于信任的系统。这表明,交际理性只有在参与者相信每个人都真诚地朝着寻找最佳决策的共同目标参与的背景下,才能展现出它的力量——更好的论点的非强制性力量。因此,对Ultimate案件的调查使我们能够得出关于理性审议在实践中发挥作用的要求的更广泛的结论。
{"title":"Competitive Team Sport Without External Referees: The Case of the Flying Disc Sport Ultimate","authors":"G. Thonhauser","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2101682","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2101682","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Ultimate is a competitive team sport that is played, even at the highest level of competition, without external referees. The key to Ultimate as a self-refereed sport is the so-called ‘Spirit of the Game’. As this paper aims to show, the Spirit of the Game closely resembles Habermas’s theory of communicative action. This suggests that Habermas’s theory might be used to spell out the philosophical presuppositions of the Spirit of the Game. Most importantly, the requirements for players to serve as referees of their own game specified in the ‘Rules of Ultimate’ turn out to be reformulation of the four validity claims of communicative action. Moreover, the Spirit of the Game can be interpreted as aiming towards facilitating real-life decision-making procedures that resemble as much as possible Habermas’s concept of an ideal speech situation. On the other hand, Ultimate might serve as a case study for exploring how Habermas’s idea of rational deliberation works in the practice of a competitive sporting environment. Most importantly, it makes manifest that self-refereeing is a trust-based system. This suggests that communicative rationality can only unfold its power—the unforced force of the better argument—within a context in which participants trust that everyone participates in good faith towards the common goal of finding the best decision. Hence, investigating the case of Ultimate allows us to draw broader conclusions about the requirements for rational deliberation to work in practice.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"27 1","pages":"85 - 100"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-07-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75477346","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
(In)justice on Ice: Valieva and International Sport Governing Bodies’ Justice Duties Toward Underage Athletes 冰上的正义:Valieva和国际体育管理机构对未成年运动员的正义义务
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-07-12 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2099962
Brett A. Diaz, M. Campos, M. Škerbić, Cam Mallett, Francisco Javier López Frías
ABSTRACT After two years of discussions and revisions, the World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA) published the 2021 World Anti-Doping Code on June 16, 2020. Among the most significant additions to this iteration of the Code was the inclusion of new categories of athletes subject to differential treatment by WADA, including the “protected person” category. In this paper, we examine the recent case of figure skater Kamila Valeryevna Valieva, the first athlete given differential treatment due to her being categorized as a “protected person.” We apply a relational justice framework to the case to provide a nuanced, descriptive analysis of the case generally, and the application of the “protected person” category in particular.We first describe details of the athlete, her performances and anti-doping rule violation, and the “protected person” category, to provide context. We then describe and analyze the relations between several institutional actors, principally WADA and the International Court for the Arbitration of Sport (CAS), the athlete and her team, and other figure skating athletes at the Beijing Winter Olympic Games. To do so, we use two concepts of justice, conservative and ideal, and their component parts, entitlement, desert, and need.Our description and analyses demonstrate that (1) WADA’s notions of justice are essentially conservative, while CAS acted toward more ideal notions, creating a fundamental disagreement in what was owed and to whom. We show (2) that CAS’ decision may have nonetheless caused harm to the athlete, raising questions about the efficacy and capability of the “protected person” category. Finally, (3) our analyses show the influence that notions of justice necessarily have these actors shape each other, thus change the sporting institutions and activities themselves.
经过两年的讨论和修订,世界反兴奋剂机构(WADA)于2020年6月16日发布了2021年《世界反兴奋剂条例》。此次修订的《守则》中最重要的补充是列入了受世界反兴奋剂机构区别对待的运动员的新类别,包括“受保护人员”类别。在本文中,我们研究了最近的花样滑冰运动员卡米拉·瓦列耶夫娜·瓦列娃(Kamila Valeryevna Valieva)的案例,她是第一个因被归类为“受保护人员”而受到区别对待的运动员。我们将关系司法框架应用于案件,对案件进行细致入微的描述性分析,特别是对“受保护人”类别的应用。我们首先描述了运动员的细节,她的表现和违反反兴奋剂规则,以及“受保护人员”类别,以提供背景。然后,我们描述和分析了几个机构参与者之间的关系,主要是世界反兴奋剂机构和国际体育仲裁法庭(CAS),运动员和她的团队,以及北京冬奥会上的其他花样滑冰运动员。为了做到这一点,我们使用了两个正义概念,保守的和理想的,以及它们的组成部分,权利,应得和需要。我们的描述和分析表明:(1)WADA的正义观念本质上是保守的,而CAS的行为更理想,在欠什么和欠谁的问题上产生了根本的分歧。我们表明(2),尽管如此,CAS的决定可能对运动员造成了伤害,引发了对“受保护人员”类别的效力和能力的质疑。最后,(3)我们的分析表明,正义的概念必然会影响这些参与者相互塑造,从而改变体育机构和活动本身。
{"title":"(In)justice on Ice: Valieva and International Sport Governing Bodies’ Justice Duties Toward Underage Athletes","authors":"Brett A. Diaz, M. Campos, M. Škerbić, Cam Mallett, Francisco Javier López Frías","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2099962","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2099962","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT After two years of discussions and revisions, the World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA) published the 2021 World Anti-Doping Code on June 16, 2020. Among the most significant additions to this iteration of the Code was the inclusion of new categories of athletes subject to differential treatment by WADA, including the “protected person” category. In this paper, we examine the recent case of figure skater Kamila Valeryevna Valieva, the first athlete given differential treatment due to her being categorized as a “protected person.” We apply a relational justice framework to the case to provide a nuanced, descriptive analysis of the case generally, and the application of the “protected person” category in particular.We first describe details of the athlete, her performances and anti-doping rule violation, and the “protected person” category, to provide context. We then describe and analyze the relations between several institutional actors, principally WADA and the International Court for the Arbitration of Sport (CAS), the athlete and her team, and other figure skating athletes at the Beijing Winter Olympic Games. To do so, we use two concepts of justice, conservative and ideal, and their component parts, entitlement, desert, and need.Our description and analyses demonstrate that (1) WADA’s notions of justice are essentially conservative, while CAS acted toward more ideal notions, creating a fundamental disagreement in what was owed and to whom. We show (2) that CAS’ decision may have nonetheless caused harm to the athlete, raising questions about the efficacy and capability of the “protected person” category. Finally, (3) our analyses show the influence that notions of justice necessarily have these actors shape each other, thus change the sporting institutions and activities themselves.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":"70 - 84"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-07-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79124902","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Wales vs Ukraine 威尔士vs乌克兰
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-07-03 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2101284
A. Edgar
On 5 June 2022 Wales played Ukraine for a place in the FIFA World Cup finals, which are due to be held in Qatar in November and December 2022. I suspect that all right-mined people wanted Ukraine to win. That win would have provided a significant boost to the morale of a nation suffering under an unprovoked military incursion and brutal war. As I write, there is little prospect that the war will have ended by November. Although right-minded people may have wanted Ukraine to win, I supported Wales, and was delighted with their ultimate victory. I felt slightly guilty and, for personal reasons, a little surprised at my delight. My support for Wales is relatively easy to explain. I have lived half my life in Cardiff, and in a period of more than thirty years support of the national sports team, be it soccer, rugby, or any other sport you care to mention, has become ingrained. It is second nature. Added to that, for most of those thirty years I lived in the suburb of Cardiff where Gareth Bale was born and went to school. I passed the Gareth Bale mural on Church Road every time I went to the local shops. Sport can play fast and loose with our political sensibilities. In sport, it seems, we put our national (or even tribal) loyalties above issues of international justice. Indeed, if Wales had let Ukraine win, ensuring their place in the World Cup finals, it can be argued that a sporting injustice would have been committed. In sport, one respects one’s opponent not by indulging them, however worthy the outcome of that indulgence might be, but by playing them as aggressively and fairly as you would in any match. After all, in 2001, the Arizona Diamondbacks did not let the New York Yankees win the World Series, despite 9/ 11. The Diamondbacks showed the Yankees the respect they deserved. So too, Wales respected Ukraine by not letting them win. There are added complexities to all this. Some of these complexities are personal. By June 2022 I had moved away from Cardiff, and back to my native England. Should a change of national loyalties have occurred (perhaps at the precise moment in which I received the keys to my new house)? Should I have become a right-minded neutral when Wales played? Even if a change should have occurred, it didn’t. Second nature, so painstakingly shaped over thirty years, does not, I discovered, change over night. That image of Gareth Bale on a wall in Church Road is surprisingly persuasive. What is significant here is that sport can be a crucible in which one’s sense of identity, and thus the entangled and sometimes contradictory communities and cultures that demand your loyalty, are tested and exposed. Through sport, it seems, one can learn a lot about one’s personal identity politics. In sport one begins to tease out the complexities of who you are, who you have been, and who you might become. SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY 2022, VOL. 16, NO. 3, 251–253 https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2101284
2022年6月5日,威尔士队与乌克兰队争夺世界杯决赛席位,世界杯将于2022年11月和12月在卡塔尔举行。我怀疑所有右翼人士都希望乌克兰获胜。这场胜利将极大地提振这个遭受无端军事入侵和残酷战争的国家的士气。在我写这篇文章的时候,战争在11月结束的可能性微乎其微。虽然正直的人可能希望乌克兰获胜,但我支持威尔士,并为他们最终的胜利感到高兴。我感到有点内疚,出于个人原因,我对自己的喜悦感到有点惊讶。我对威尔士的支持相对容易解释。我在卡迪夫生活了半辈子,在三十多年的时间里,我对国家运动队的支持,无论是足球、橄榄球,还是其他任何你愿意提到的运动,都已经根深蒂固。这是第二天性。此外,在那30年的大部分时间里,我都住在加的夫郊区,加雷思·贝尔就是在那里出生和上学的。每次去当地的商店,我都会经过教堂路上的加雷斯·贝尔(Gareth Bale)壁画。体育运动可以忽悠我们的政治敏感性。在体育运动中,我们似乎把对国家(甚至是部落)的忠诚置于国际正义之上。事实上,如果威尔士让乌克兰获胜,确保了他们在世界杯决赛中的席位,可以说这是一种体育上的不公正。在体育运动中,一个人尊重自己的对手,不是通过纵容他们,不管这种纵容的结果是多么值得,而是通过像在任何比赛中一样积极和公平地对待他们。毕竟,在2001年,亚利桑那响尾蛇队没有让纽约洋基队赢得世界大赛,尽管9/ 11。响尾蛇队向洋基队展示了他们应得的尊重。威尔士也尊重乌克兰,不让他们赢。这一切都有额外的复杂性。其中一些复杂性是个人的。到2022年6月,我离开了卡迪夫,回到了我的祖国英国。是否应该改变对国家的忠诚(也许就在我拿到新房子钥匙的那一刻)?当威尔士比赛时,我应该成为一个正直的中立者吗?即使应该发生变化,它也没有发生。我发现,经过三十年精心塑造的第二天性,不会在一夜之间改变。加雷斯·贝尔(Gareth Bale)在教堂路(Church Road)墙上的照片令人惊讶地具有说服力。这里的重要意义在于,体育可以成为一个考验和暴露个人认同感的熔炉,从而考验和暴露要求你忠诚的那些纠缠在一起、有时甚至是相互矛盾的社区和文化。通过体育运动,人们似乎可以学到很多关于个人身份政治的东西。在体育运动中,一个人开始梳理出你是谁,你曾经是谁,你可能成为谁的复杂性。体育伦理与哲学,2022年,第16卷,第1期。3,251 - 253 https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2101284
{"title":"Wales vs Ukraine","authors":"A. Edgar","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2101284","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2101284","url":null,"abstract":"On 5 June 2022 Wales played Ukraine for a place in the FIFA World Cup finals, which are due to be held in Qatar in November and December 2022. I suspect that all right-mined people wanted Ukraine to win. That win would have provided a significant boost to the morale of a nation suffering under an unprovoked military incursion and brutal war. As I write, there is little prospect that the war will have ended by November. Although right-minded people may have wanted Ukraine to win, I supported Wales, and was delighted with their ultimate victory. I felt slightly guilty and, for personal reasons, a little surprised at my delight. My support for Wales is relatively easy to explain. I have lived half my life in Cardiff, and in a period of more than thirty years support of the national sports team, be it soccer, rugby, or any other sport you care to mention, has become ingrained. It is second nature. Added to that, for most of those thirty years I lived in the suburb of Cardiff where Gareth Bale was born and went to school. I passed the Gareth Bale mural on Church Road every time I went to the local shops. Sport can play fast and loose with our political sensibilities. In sport, it seems, we put our national (or even tribal) loyalties above issues of international justice. Indeed, if Wales had let Ukraine win, ensuring their place in the World Cup finals, it can be argued that a sporting injustice would have been committed. In sport, one respects one’s opponent not by indulging them, however worthy the outcome of that indulgence might be, but by playing them as aggressively and fairly as you would in any match. After all, in 2001, the Arizona Diamondbacks did not let the New York Yankees win the World Series, despite 9/ 11. The Diamondbacks showed the Yankees the respect they deserved. So too, Wales respected Ukraine by not letting them win. There are added complexities to all this. Some of these complexities are personal. By June 2022 I had moved away from Cardiff, and back to my native England. Should a change of national loyalties have occurred (perhaps at the precise moment in which I received the keys to my new house)? Should I have become a right-minded neutral when Wales played? Even if a change should have occurred, it didn’t. Second nature, so painstakingly shaped over thirty years, does not, I discovered, change over night. That image of Gareth Bale on a wall in Church Road is surprisingly persuasive. What is significant here is that sport can be a crucible in which one’s sense of identity, and thus the entangled and sometimes contradictory communities and cultures that demand your loyalty, are tested and exposed. Through sport, it seems, one can learn a lot about one’s personal identity politics. In sport one begins to tease out the complexities of who you are, who you have been, and who you might become. SPORT, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY 2022, VOL. 16, NO. 3, 251–253 https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2101284","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"10 1","pages":"251 - 253"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-07-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84435995","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
On the Definition of Sport 论体育的定义
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-05-25 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2077814
J. Parry
ABSTRACT This paper side-steps the question of whether ‘the’ concept of sport exists, or can be usefully analysed. Instead, I try to explain the much more modest aim of exhibition-analysis, which is to seek a description of an actually existing example of some concept of sport internal to a normative position. My example is that of Olympic-sport. I try to set out its logically necessary conditions, which of course are conditioned by its context within a theory that emphasises the values of formal competition, citius-altius-fortius, and excellence in contest, as well as rule-based procedural values related to fairness, justice and equality. In so doing, I readily accept that other kinds of sport can be similarly analysed, and I do not press the value claims of Olympic-sport. Instead, I try to show how Olympic-sport, properly construed, can accommodate the concerns of my critics with regard to sport’s play and game-like characteristics.
本文回避了“体育”概念是否存在或是否可以进行有益分析的问题。相反,我试图解释展览分析的更谦虚的目的,即寻求对一个实际存在的例子的描述,这个例子是一些体育概念内部的规范立场。我的例子是奥林匹克运动。我试图列出其逻辑上的必要条件,当然,这些条件是由其理论背景所限制的,该理论强调正式竞争,公民-高度-力量,竞争中的卓越价值,以及与公平,正义和平等相关的基于规则的程序价值。在这样做的过程中,我欣然接受其他种类的运动也可以进行类似的分析,我并没有强调奥林匹克运动的价值主张。相反,我试图展示奥林匹克运动如何在适当的解释下,能够适应我的批评者对体育运动的玩法和游戏特征的担忧。
{"title":"On the Definition of Sport","authors":"J. Parry","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2077814","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2077814","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT This paper side-steps the question of whether ‘the’ concept of sport exists, or can be usefully analysed. Instead, I try to explain the much more modest aim of exhibition-analysis, which is to seek a description of an actually existing example of some concept of sport internal to a normative position. My example is that of Olympic-sport. I try to set out its logically necessary conditions, which of course are conditioned by its context within a theory that emphasises the values of formal competition, citius-altius-fortius, and excellence in contest, as well as rule-based procedural values related to fairness, justice and equality. In so doing, I readily accept that other kinds of sport can be similarly analysed, and I do not press the value claims of Olympic-sport. Instead, I try to show how Olympic-sport, properly construed, can accommodate the concerns of my critics with regard to sport’s play and game-like characteristics.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"55 1","pages":"49 - 57"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-05-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80195482","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Children and Mixed Martial Arts 儿童和综合格斗
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-05-18 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2076728
Aderemi Artis
ABSTRACT J. S. Russell has argued that it is morally permissible for children to participate in dangerous sports and that much of value can be gained from such participation. He attempts to justify children’s participation in dangerous sport with two arguments, which he calls the common sense view and the uncommon sense view, and I apply the basic reasons given in these general arguments to the specific case of justifying children’s participation in mixed martial arts (MMA). To safeguard against wanton and gratuitous risk of great harm, Russell also includes some basic limitations for children’s participation in dangerous sports, and I use these limitations as a general framework for providing a number of additional constraints to render children’s MMA morally permissible.
j·s·罗素认为,儿童参加危险运动在道德上是允许的,而且从中可以获得很多价值。他试图用两种观点来证明儿童参加危险运动的合理性,他称之为常识观点和非常识观点,我将这些普遍观点中给出的基本理由应用于证明儿童参加综合格斗(MMA)的具体案例。为了防止肆意和无为的巨大伤害风险,罗素还对儿童参与危险运动提出了一些基本限制,我将这些限制作为一个总体框架,提供一些额外的约束,使儿童的综合格斗在道德上是允许的。
{"title":"Children and Mixed Martial Arts","authors":"Aderemi Artis","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2076728","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2076728","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT J. S. Russell has argued that it is morally permissible for children to participate in dangerous sports and that much of value can be gained from such participation. He attempts to justify children’s participation in dangerous sport with two arguments, which he calls the common sense view and the uncommon sense view, and I apply the basic reasons given in these general arguments to the specific case of justifying children’s participation in mixed martial arts (MMA). To safeguard against wanton and gratuitous risk of great harm, Russell also includes some basic limitations for children’s participation in dangerous sports, and I use these limitations as a general framework for providing a number of additional constraints to render children’s MMA morally permissible.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"1 1","pages":"607 - 622"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-05-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87403890","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Book Symposium. Steffen Borge, The Philosophy of Football 本研讨会。史蒂芬·博格,《足球哲学》
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-04-26 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2021.1974531
Steffen Borge, W. Morgan, Murray Smith, B. Weatherson
ABSTRACT This is a book symposium on Steffen Borge’s The Philosophy of Football. It has contributions from William Morgan, Murray Smith and Brian Weatherson with replies from Borge.
这是一场关于博格的《足球哲学》的学术研讨会。它有威廉·摩根,默里·史密斯和布莱恩·威瑟森的贡献,并有博格的回复。
{"title":"Book Symposium. Steffen Borge, The Philosophy of Football","authors":"Steffen Borge, W. Morgan, Murray Smith, B. Weatherson","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2021.1974531","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2021.1974531","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT This is a book symposium on Steffen Borge’s The Philosophy of Football. It has contributions from William Morgan, Murray Smith and Brian Weatherson with replies from Borge.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"31 2","pages":"333 - 396"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-04-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72416076","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dialectics in Transformations of Professional Sport 职业体育转型中的辩证法
IF 1.3 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2022-04-15 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2022.2063936
F. Lebed
ABSTRACT In this article, I explore the relationship between competitive sports and the phenomenon of sports fandom as a unique symbiosis that qualitatively changes the nature of sport and reveals new aspects of human play in general. I note that spectators as consumers transform sport, in addition to indirectly and directly influencing and intervening in sports practice. As a result of this versatile involvement—from the initial form of competitive, formalized and unproductive game—sport can evolve through four successive stages: professional sport → sports show → ‘meta-play’ → “meta-sport “. The first of them has been sufficiently studied from two points of view, mainly: (a) control of training progress, effective coaching, and maximalised performance, and (b) management and marketing. The second form, sports show, is very rarely studied separately from the first stage (e.g.). Here I separate them. The third and fourth stages are proposed and studied here anew by a philosophical analysis of current and possible future developments and changes in the sports show. I analyse all these changes from a dialectical perspective and support it using the paradigm of tension between positive and negative freedom. From this point of view, all the mentioned transformations—from professional sport to meta-sport—are caused by changes (from synergy to tension and conflict) in the positive and negative freedom of spectators and sports organizations in a ‘dialectical symbiosis’. These are followed by the tensive contradiction between the principal freedom of human play and the self- and institutional restriction of freedom in the stage by stage evolving frames of game, sport, and professional sport. ‘Dialectical symbiosis’ is considered here as the fusion of entities, as a result of which one of them, at least, is transformed into a new quality.
在这篇文章中,我探讨了竞技体育和体育迷现象之间的关系,这是一种独特的共生关系,从质量上改变了体育的本质,并揭示了人类游戏的新方面。我注意到,观众作为消费者,除了间接和直接地影响和干预体育实践外,还改变了体育运动。由于这种多样化的参与——从最初的竞争性、形式化和非生产性的游戏形式——体育可以通过四个连续的阶段发展:专业体育→体育表演→“元游戏”→“元体育”。第一个问题已经从两个方面得到了充分的研究,主要是:(a)对培训进度的控制,有效的指导,以及最大限度地提高绩效;(b)管理和营销。第二种形式,体育表演,很少与第一阶段分开研究(例如)。这里我把它们分开。本文通过对体育节目当前和未来可能的发展和变化的哲学分析,提出并重新研究了第三和第四阶段。我从辩证的角度来分析这些变化,并以积极自由与消极自由之间的张力为范式来支持这些变化。从这个角度来看,上述所有的转变——从职业体育到元体育——都是由观众和体育组织在“辩证共生”中积极和消极自由的变化(从协同到紧张和冲突)引起的。随之而来的是,在游戏、体育和职业体育的逐步发展框架中,人类游戏的主要自由与自由的自我和制度限制之间的紧张矛盾。在这里,“辩证共生”被认为是各种实体的融合,至少其中一个实体转化为一种新的性质。
{"title":"Dialectics in Transformations of Professional Sport","authors":"F. Lebed","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2022.2063936","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2022.2063936","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT In this article, I explore the relationship between competitive sports and the phenomenon of sports fandom as a unique symbiosis that qualitatively changes the nature of sport and reveals new aspects of human play in general. I note that spectators as consumers transform sport, in addition to indirectly and directly influencing and intervening in sports practice. As a result of this versatile involvement—from the initial form of competitive, formalized and unproductive game—sport can evolve through four successive stages: professional sport → sports show → ‘meta-play’ → “meta-sport “. The first of them has been sufficiently studied from two points of view, mainly: (a) control of training progress, effective coaching, and maximalised performance, and (b) management and marketing. The second form, sports show, is very rarely studied separately from the first stage (e.g.). Here I separate them. The third and fourth stages are proposed and studied here anew by a philosophical analysis of current and possible future developments and changes in the sports show. I analyse all these changes from a dialectical perspective and support it using the paradigm of tension between positive and negative freedom. From this point of view, all the mentioned transformations—from professional sport to meta-sport—are caused by changes (from synergy to tension and conflict) in the positive and negative freedom of spectators and sports organizations in a ‘dialectical symbiosis’. These are followed by the tensive contradiction between the principal freedom of human play and the self- and institutional restriction of freedom in the stage by stage evolving frames of game, sport, and professional sport. ‘Dialectical symbiosis’ is considered here as the fusion of entities, as a result of which one of them, at least, is transformed into a new quality.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":"6 3","pages":"589 - 606"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-04-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72613238","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Sport Ethics and Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1