首页 > 最新文献

Sport Ethics and Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Return of the Grasshopper: Games, Leisure, and the Good Life in the Third Millennium Return of the Grasshopper: Games, Leisure, and the Good Life in the Third Millennium , by Bernard Suits (edited by Christopher C. Yorke and Francisco Javier López Frías), illustrated by Paul Hammond, (Ethics and Sport Series), London and New York, Routledge (Taylor & Francis Group), 2022, 190 pp., (paperback, 22 B/W Illustrations), $48.95 (paperback), $170.00 (hardback), $48.95 (ebook), ISBN 978-1-… 《蚱蜢的回归:第三个千年的游戏、休闲和美好生活》,伯纳德·赛茨著(克里斯托弗·c·约克和弗朗西斯科·哈维尔编辑López Frías),保罗·哈蒙德插图(道德与运动系列),伦敦和纽约,劳特利奇出版社(泰勒&安普;弗朗西斯集团),2022,190页,(平装本,22 B/W插图),48.95美元(平装本),170.00美元(精装本),48.95美元(电子书),ISBN 978-1-…
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-19 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2272052
Taliah L. Powers
Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).
点击放大图片点击缩小图片披露声明作者未发现潜在的利益冲突。
{"title":"Return of the Grasshopper: Games, Leisure, and the Good Life in the Third Millennium <b>Return of the Grasshopper: Games, Leisure, and the Good Life in the Third Millennium</b> , by Bernard Suits (edited by Christopher C. Yorke and Francisco Javier López Frías), illustrated by Paul Hammond, (Ethics and Sport Series), London and New York, Routledge (Taylor &amp; Francis Group), 2022, 190 pp., (paperback, 22 B/W Illustrations), $48.95 (paperback), $170.00 (hardback), $48.95 (ebook), ISBN 978-1-…","authors":"Taliah L. Powers","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2272052","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2272052","url":null,"abstract":"Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135778506","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
‘Ecce Ego’: Apollo, Dionysus, and Performative Social Media “自我至上”:阿波罗、酒神和表现性社交媒体
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-13 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2265070
Aurélien Daudi
Epitomized in the bodily exhibitions of ‘fitspiration’, photo-based social media is biased toward self-beautification and glorification of reality. Meanwhile, evidence is growing of psychological side effects connected to this ‘pictorial turn’ in our communication. In The Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche poses the question how ugliness and discord can produce aesthetic pleasure. This paper proceeds from an inverse relationship and examines why glorification of appearances and conspicuous beauty fails to do the same, and even compounds suffering. Drawing on the Apollo-Dionysus dualism undergirding Nietzsche’s aesthetic philosophy, I posit a deeper relation between the saturation of visual self-exhibitionism typified in fitspiration and its empirical effects. Concentrating on the medium and self-representational photograph, I argue that Instagram is primarily an instrument of Apolline artifice and that the pictorial turn which defines the present centers Apolline mediation to the detrimental exclusion of meaningful communion with its Dionysiac antithesis. For users immersed in this Apolline sphere of visual self-representation, a fractured existence beholden to conditions of the image ensues—comprising surface-level appearances, deification of the moment, and loss of existential sustenance through myth. By positioning fitspiration not as an aberration but as the logical conclusion of the medium’s intrinsic Apolline property, it becomes a litmus test of the entire visual landscape and illustrative of the implications that uncritical participation in it may bring.
以照片为基础的社交媒体倾向于自我美化和美化现实,这体现在“fitspiration”的身体展览中。与此同时,越来越多的证据表明,与我们交流中的这种“图像化转变”有关的心理副作用。在《悲剧的诞生》中,尼采提出了丑陋和不和谐如何产生审美愉悦的问题。本文从相反的关系出发,探讨了为什么美化外表和引人注目的美丽不能做到同样的事情,甚至加剧了痛苦。根据尼采美学哲学基础上的阿波罗-狄俄尼索斯二元论,我假设在以fitspiration为代表的视觉自我展示主义的饱和与其经验效应之间存在更深层次的关系。专注于媒介和自我表现的照片,我认为Instagram主要是Apolline技巧的工具,并且定义当前中心的绘画转向是Apolline中介的有害排除与其酒神对立的有意义的交流。对于沉浸在视觉自我呈现的Apolline领域的用户来说,一种依赖于图像条件的断裂存在随之而来——包括表面的外观,对当下的神化,以及通过神话失去存在的寄托。通过将fitspiration定位为媒介内在Apolline属性的逻辑结论,它成为了整个视觉景观的试金石,并说明了不加批判地参与其中可能带来的影响。
{"title":"‘Ecce Ego’: Apollo, Dionysus, and Performative Social Media","authors":"Aurélien Daudi","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2265070","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2265070","url":null,"abstract":"Epitomized in the bodily exhibitions of ‘fitspiration’, photo-based social media is biased toward self-beautification and glorification of reality. Meanwhile, evidence is growing of psychological side effects connected to this ‘pictorial turn’ in our communication. In The Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche poses the question how ugliness and discord can produce aesthetic pleasure. This paper proceeds from an inverse relationship and examines why glorification of appearances and conspicuous beauty fails to do the same, and even compounds suffering. Drawing on the Apollo-Dionysus dualism undergirding Nietzsche’s aesthetic philosophy, I posit a deeper relation between the saturation of visual self-exhibitionism typified in fitspiration and its empirical effects. Concentrating on the medium and self-representational photograph, I argue that Instagram is primarily an instrument of Apolline artifice and that the pictorial turn which defines the present centers Apolline mediation to the detrimental exclusion of meaningful communion with its Dionysiac antithesis. For users immersed in this Apolline sphere of visual self-representation, a fractured existence beholden to conditions of the image ensues—comprising surface-level appearances, deification of the moment, and loss of existential sustenance through myth. By positioning fitspiration not as an aberration but as the logical conclusion of the medium’s intrinsic Apolline property, it becomes a litmus test of the entire visual landscape and illustrative of the implications that uncritical participation in it may bring.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135854092","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reframing the Debate over Performance-Enhancing Drugs: The Reasonable Athlete Argument 重新讨论提高成绩的药物:合理的运动员论点
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-09 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2266581
Matthew C. Altman
ABSTRACTTwo of the major arguments against performance-enhancing drugs (PEDs), appealing to fairness and the protection of athletes’ health, have serious flaws. First, there is no relevant moral distinction between the use of PEDs and the use of other performance enhancers that introduce unfairness and that we accept nonetheless. Second, prohibiting PEDs for athletes’ own good ignores the fact that adult athletes are constantly making tradeoffs to improve performance and pursue excellence, including sacrificing their health. We should not paternalistically impose our values on them. On the other side, arguments to allow ‘safe’ PEDs provide no normative criterion to determine the acceptable level of risk, thus begging the question. The reasonable athlete argument solves both sets of problems: it justifies a ban on some performance-enhancing drugs based on health and fairness, while avoiding paternalism, and it also establishes a non-arbitrary standard to determine which drugs ought to be allowed. First, if unsafe PEDs were allowed, some athletes would refuse to take them out of concern for their health. This is a reasonable decision even though it would put them at a competitive disadvantage against athletes who choose to use unsafe PEDs. It would be unfair for clean athletes to suffer a competitive disadvantage for acting reasonably. Therefore, PEDs that pose significant health risks should be prohibited for all athletes. Second, it would be unreasonable for athletes to refuse, on principle, relatively safe and effective PEDs, so a blanket prohibition is also unjustified. Which drugs and which doses to allow should be determined not by athletes’ actual choices but by the hypothetical choices of the reasonable athlete. The resulting sport-specific drug policy would carve a justifiable middle path between complete prohibition and complete permission.KEYWORDS: Performance-enhancing drugsdopingfairnesscoercionsteroids AcknowledgmentsI am grateful to Cynthia Coe and Lou Matz for helpful comments on earlier drafts. The two reviewers for Sport, Ethics and Philosophy also provided valuable suggestions as I revised the article for publication.Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Some philosophers have questioned whether elite athletes are in fact fully free. For example, Murray (Citation1983), Fraleigh (Citation1985), and Holowchak (Citation2000) claim that they are coerced—forced to choose either to harm themselves, lower expectations, or quit the sport; and pressured by team owners and fans—and are thus not in control of their choices regarding PEDs. Brown (Citation1985a) and Veber (Citation2014) challenge that idea, claiming that the athlete’s situation is not coercive, or coercive enough, for them to be in need of protection against their own decisions. Saying that someone must do something dangerous to compete at the highest levels, such as the McTwist maneuver in skateboarding, is not coercive,
【摘要】反对使用兴奋剂的两大论点——呼吁公平和保护运动员健康——存在严重缺陷。首先,使用ped和使用其他会带来不公平的性能增强剂之间没有相关的道德区别,尽管如此,我们还是接受了。其次,为了运动员的利益而禁止使用ped忽视了一个事实,即成年运动员为了提高成绩和追求卓越而不断做出权衡,包括牺牲自己的健康。我们不应该以家长式的方式把我们的价值观强加给他们。另一方面,允许“安全”的ped的论点没有提供确定可接受风险水平的规范性标准,因此回避了这个问题。合理的运动员论点解决了这两组问题:它证明了基于健康和公平禁止一些提高成绩的药物是合理的,同时避免了家长式作风;它还建立了一个非武断的标准来确定哪些药物应该被允许使用。首先,如果允许使用不安全的ped,一些运动员会出于对健康的考虑而拒绝服用。这是一个合理的决定,即使这将使他们在与选择使用不安全的ped的运动员的竞争中处于劣势。如果清白的运动员因为行为合理而处于竞争劣势,这是不公平的。因此,所有运动员都应该禁止使用具有重大健康风险的ped。其次,运动员原则上拒绝相对安全有效的ped是不合理的,因此全面禁止也是不合理的。服用何种药物和剂量不应由运动员的实际选择决定,而应由理性运动员的假设选择决定。由此产生的针对体育运动的药物政策将在完全禁止和完全允许之间开辟一条合理的中间道路。感谢Cynthia Coe和Lou Matz对早期草稿的有益评论。在我修改文章准备发表的过程中,《体育、伦理和哲学》的两位审稿人也提供了宝贵的建议。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。一些哲学家质疑优秀运动员是否真的完全自由。例如,Murray (Citation1983)、Fraleigh (Citation1985)和Holowchak (Citation2000)声称他们是被迫选择伤害自己、降低期望或退出这项运动的;并受到球队老板和球迷的压力,因此他们无法控制自己对ped的选择。Brown (Citation1985a)和Veber (Citation2014)对这一观点提出了质疑,他们认为运动员的情况不是强制性的,或者强制性的程度不足以让他们需要保护自己不受自己决定的影响。说一个人必须做一些危险的事情才能参加最高水平的比赛,比如滑板中的McTwist动作,这不是强制性的,使用ped的压力也不是强制性的(Veber引文2014)。西蒙持中间观点:尽管运动员没有被强迫(Simon Citation1985, 8-10;Simon, Torres, and Hager Citation2015, 90-92),他们被给予一个“不道德的约束选择”,要么冒着伤害的风险去竞争,要么不竞争,要么退出这项运动(Simon, Torres, and Hager Citation2015, 92-95)。Loland (Citation2009)同意,“在成熟和理性的运动员可以自由和知情地选择使用技术的情况下,关于运动员脆弱性和被剥削的争论似乎没有根据”。所以,洛兰德似乎想让他们自己选择。“然而,”他补充说,“这种情况不太可能出现。运动成绩是从小多年甚至几十年艰苦训练的结果,很少有运动员有必要的知识来做出自己的选择。显然,精英运动员在智力和道德上都发育不良,他们不能被允许为自己做出重要的决定,即使这只会影响到他们。罗兰说的有些道理。大多数优秀运动员从小就开始训练,所以他们的运动规范是从小灌输的。体操运动员、网球运动员、游泳运动员和许多其他运动员在很小的时候就被父母和教练告知,他们应该利用一切可能的优势来提高自己的竞争力并取得成功。这种训练无疑会影响运动员的决策,以至于他们作为成年人做出的选择既不是被强迫的,也不是简单的自主的。这就提出了一个更大的问题,即间接的道德运气是否会削弱我们获得自由的能力,这超出了本文的范围。据估计,即使有现有的禁令,精英运动员群体中使用兴奋剂的比例也高达57% (Ulrich等)。Citation2018)。3。肖恩·麦基弗(Citation2017)在反对儿科医生的观点中称这是一个“糟糕的选择”。
{"title":"Reframing the Debate over Performance-Enhancing Drugs: The Reasonable Athlete Argument","authors":"Matthew C. Altman","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2266581","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2266581","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTTwo of the major arguments against performance-enhancing drugs (PEDs), appealing to fairness and the protection of athletes’ health, have serious flaws. First, there is no relevant moral distinction between the use of PEDs and the use of other performance enhancers that introduce unfairness and that we accept nonetheless. Second, prohibiting PEDs for athletes’ own good ignores the fact that adult athletes are constantly making tradeoffs to improve performance and pursue excellence, including sacrificing their health. We should not paternalistically impose our values on them. On the other side, arguments to allow ‘safe’ PEDs provide no normative criterion to determine the acceptable level of risk, thus begging the question. The reasonable athlete argument solves both sets of problems: it justifies a ban on some performance-enhancing drugs based on health and fairness, while avoiding paternalism, and it also establishes a non-arbitrary standard to determine which drugs ought to be allowed. First, if unsafe PEDs were allowed, some athletes would refuse to take them out of concern for their health. This is a reasonable decision even though it would put them at a competitive disadvantage against athletes who choose to use unsafe PEDs. It would be unfair for clean athletes to suffer a competitive disadvantage for acting reasonably. Therefore, PEDs that pose significant health risks should be prohibited for all athletes. Second, it would be unreasonable for athletes to refuse, on principle, relatively safe and effective PEDs, so a blanket prohibition is also unjustified. Which drugs and which doses to allow should be determined not by athletes’ actual choices but by the hypothetical choices of the reasonable athlete. The resulting sport-specific drug policy would carve a justifiable middle path between complete prohibition and complete permission.KEYWORDS: Performance-enhancing drugsdopingfairnesscoercionsteroids AcknowledgmentsI am grateful to Cynthia Coe and Lou Matz for helpful comments on earlier drafts. The two reviewers for Sport, Ethics and Philosophy also provided valuable suggestions as I revised the article for publication.Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Some philosophers have questioned whether elite athletes are in fact fully free. For example, Murray (Citation1983), Fraleigh (Citation1985), and Holowchak (Citation2000) claim that they are coerced—forced to choose either to harm themselves, lower expectations, or quit the sport; and pressured by team owners and fans—and are thus not in control of their choices regarding PEDs. Brown (Citation1985a) and Veber (Citation2014) challenge that idea, claiming that the athlete’s situation is not coercive, or coercive enough, for them to be in need of protection against their own decisions. Saying that someone must do something dangerous to compete at the highest levels, such as the McTwist maneuver in skateboarding, is not coercive, ","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135094569","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Towards a Value-Neutral Definition of Sport 走向体育的价值中立定义
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-30 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2260116
Michael Hemmingsen
ABSTRACTIn this paper I argue that philosophers of sport should avoid value-laden definitions of sport; that is, they should avoid building into the definition of sport that they are inherently worthwhile activities. Sports may very well often be worthwhile as a contingent matter, but this should not be taken to be a core feature included in the definition of sport. I start by outlining what I call the ‘legitimacy-conferring’ element of the category ‘sport’. I then argue that we ought not to include such a dimension in our definition of sport, on the grounds that it confuses issues of description with issues of definition: the issue of what sport does with what sport is. Following this, I consider a Wittgensteinian family resemblance approach to defining sport; Kevin Schieman’s argument that sports are necessarily good games; and the oft-cited wide-following and institutional criteria, as arguments for including an evaluative dimension in the definition of sport. I conclude that none succeed, for similar reasons: they either fail to track our common sense intuitions about what does or does not count as a sport; and/or they make it impossible for us to ever describe something a ‘bad’ sport (or instance of sport). Just as a good definition of, say, art, shouldn’t make it impossible for us to describe something as ‘bad art’, I argue that our definition of sport shouldn’t build in a necessarily positive evaluation. I conclude by discussing some of the practical reasons why supporters of activities about which there is currently debate as to their status as sports might want to see those activities included under the sports umbrella, but suggest that this on its own isn’t a good reason for modifying a philosophical definition of sport to include them.KEYWORDS: value-neutraldefining sportlegitimacy AcknowledgmentsI would like to thank Don Oxtoby for his comments on a draft of this paper, as well as the two anonymous reviewers for their helpful feedback.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Realising that you made a definitional mistake like this is not the same as extending a chain of family resemblances. Whereas extending a chain of family resemblances continues to take the original feature as definitionally central to some instances of sport—s1, say, even if we now realise that it doesn’t apply to s2, s3, etc., – realising that you’ve made a definitional mistake is a matter of appreciating that you should never have taken that element to be definitionally important in the first place.2. Again putting aside the question of physicality, which is important to Schieman’s definition, but somewhat tangential to our discussion here.
摘要本文认为,体育哲学家应该避免对体育进行带有价值色彩的定义;也就是说,他们应该避免将体育定义为具有内在价值的活动。体育作为一种偶然性的事物可能很有价值,但这不应该被视为体育定义的核心特征。我首先概述了“体育”类别中我所谓的“合法性赋予”元素。然后,我认为我们不应该在我们的体育定义中包含这样一个维度,因为它混淆了描述问题和定义问题:混淆了体育做什么和体育是什么问题。在此之后,我考虑用维特根斯坦的家族相似性方法来定义体育;Kevin Schieman认为体育一定是优秀的游戏;以及经常被引用的广泛追随和制度性标准,作为在体育定义中加入评估维度的论据。我得出的结论是,由于类似的原因,它们都没有成功:它们要么没有遵循我们关于什么算运动、什么不算运动的常识直觉;而且/或者他们让我们无法将某件事描述为“糟糕的”运动(或运动的实例)。就像一个好的艺术定义不应该让我们无法将某些东西描述为“糟糕的艺术”一样,我认为我们对体育的定义不应该建立在一个必然的积极评价之上。最后,我讨论了一些实际的原因,为什么目前存在争议的活动的支持者可能希望看到这些活动被纳入运动的保护伞下,但建议这本身并不是修改体育的哲学定义以包括它们的好理由。我要感谢Don Oxtoby对本文草稿的评论,以及两位匿名审稿人提供的有益反馈。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。意识到你犯了这样一个定义上的错误和延续家族相似性的链条是不一样的。然而,延伸家族相似性链继续将原始特征作为某些运动实例的定义中心-例如s1,即使我们现在意识到它不适用于s2, s3等-意识到你犯了一个定义错误是一个认识到你不应该首先将该元素定义为重要元素的问题。再一次把肉体性的问题放在一边,这对Schieman的定义很重要,但与我们的讨论有些离题。
{"title":"Towards a Value-Neutral Definition of Sport","authors":"Michael Hemmingsen","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2260116","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2260116","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTIn this paper I argue that philosophers of sport should avoid value-laden definitions of sport; that is, they should avoid building into the definition of sport that they are inherently worthwhile activities. Sports may very well often be worthwhile as a contingent matter, but this should not be taken to be a core feature included in the definition of sport. I start by outlining what I call the ‘legitimacy-conferring’ element of the category ‘sport’. I then argue that we ought not to include such a dimension in our definition of sport, on the grounds that it confuses issues of description with issues of definition: the issue of what sport does with what sport is. Following this, I consider a Wittgensteinian family resemblance approach to defining sport; Kevin Schieman’s argument that sports are necessarily good games; and the oft-cited wide-following and institutional criteria, as arguments for including an evaluative dimension in the definition of sport. I conclude that none succeed, for similar reasons: they either fail to track our common sense intuitions about what does or does not count as a sport; and/or they make it impossible for us to ever describe something a ‘bad’ sport (or instance of sport). Just as a good definition of, say, art, shouldn’t make it impossible for us to describe something as ‘bad art’, I argue that our definition of sport shouldn’t build in a necessarily positive evaluation. I conclude by discussing some of the practical reasons why supporters of activities about which there is currently debate as to their status as sports might want to see those activities included under the sports umbrella, but suggest that this on its own isn’t a good reason for modifying a philosophical definition of sport to include them.KEYWORDS: value-neutraldefining sportlegitimacy AcknowledgmentsI would like to thank Don Oxtoby for his comments on a draft of this paper, as well as the two anonymous reviewers for their helpful feedback.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Realising that you made a definitional mistake like this is not the same as extending a chain of family resemblances. Whereas extending a chain of family resemblances continues to take the original feature as definitionally central to some instances of sport—s1, say, even if we now realise that it doesn’t apply to s2, s3, etc., – realising that you’ve made a definitional mistake is a matter of appreciating that you should never have taken that element to be definitionally important in the first place.2. Again putting aside the question of physicality, which is important to Schieman’s definition, but somewhat tangential to our discussion here.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136280544","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Embodied Experience, Embodied Advantage, and the Inclusion of Transgender Athletes in Competitive Sport: Expanded Framework, Criticisms, and Policy Recommendations 体现经验、体现优势和跨性别运动员在竞技体育中的包容:扩展框架、批评和政策建议
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-22 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2260112
Francisco Javier Lopez Frias, Cesar R. Torres
ABSTRACTIn a previous paper entitled ‘Beyond Physiology: Embodied Experience, Embodied Advantage, and the Inclusion of Transgender Athletes in Competitive Sport,’ we claim that analyses of the inclusion or exclusion of transgender athletes in competitive sport must go beyond physiological criteria and incorporate the notions of embodied experience and embodied advantage. Our stance has recently been challenged as impractical and excessively exclusionary. In this paper, we address these challenges and build upon them to expand on the policy implications of our original framework, highlighting that embodied experience and embodied advantage heavily influence athletic performance. We differentiate competitive fairness from justice to, with an emphasis on the inclusion of transgender women in competitive sport, formulate a justice-based argument for maximizing inclusion. Afterward, we identify ideal and nonideal policy recommendations connected to our analysis of embodied experience and embodied advantage. We ultimately advocate for a qualified inclusion that assesses potential residual (physiological and embodied) advantages while striving for justice and competitive fairness.KEYWORDS: transgender athletesembodied experienceinclusion, justicecompetitive fairness Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. See Birrell and Cole (Citation1990) and, among others, Herman (Citation1976) and Lautens (Citation1976).2. Moreover, one may wonder whether philosophy by itself can make sound contributions to policymaking (Wolff Citation2019).3. We acknowledge that Loland’s account of competitive fairness, especially his distinction between stable and dynamic conditions, clashes with some of the policy recommendations reviewed below. However, it is possible to draw on Loland’s fair play opportunity principle without also accepting (some of) his further refinements and applications of the notion. See Camporesi (Citation2020); Camporesi and Hämäläinen (Citation2021); Hämäläinen (Citation2012).4. Also see Berg (Citation2015), (Citation2018).5. One year after the publication of English’s work, Iris Marion Young (Citation1979), another feminist philosopher who formulated a justice-based argument for sex segregation in sport, expanded on this argument. By drawing on Simone de Beauvoir, she argued that sport engagement allows individuals to flourish. Thus, a lack of participation in sport prevents them from developing capacities crucial to leading fully human lives. For an analysis of feminist approaches to sport, see Burke Citation2015.6. This concept also plays a key role in the works of Young (Citation1979). For a detailed analysis of this concept, see Falbo (Citation2008).7. As Schultz et al. (Citation2022) expound, data from communities with transgender inclusive policies indicate that ‘the inclusion of trans athletes at the high school level has had no negative impact on sport participation or athletic achievements fo
在之前的一篇题为《超越生理学:体现经验、体现优势和跨性别运动员在竞技体育中的纳入》的论文中,我们声称,对跨性别运动员在竞技体育中的纳入或排除的分析必须超越生理学标准,并纳入体现经验和体现优势的概念。我们的立场最近受到挑战,被认为不切实际和过分排外。在本文中,我们解决了这些挑战,并在此基础上扩展了我们原始框架的政策含义,强调具体化经验和具体化优势严重影响运动员的表现。我们将竞争公平与正义区分开来,重点是将跨性别女性纳入竞技体育,并提出了一个基于正义的论点,以最大限度地实现包容性。随后,我们根据具体经验和具体优势的分析,确定了理想和非理想的政策建议。我们最终主张在争取正义和竞争公平的同时,评估潜在的剩余(生理和体现)优势的合格包容。关键词:跨性别运动员;体现体验;包容;公正;竞争公平;参见Birrell和Cole (Citation1990),以及Herman (Citation1976)和Lautens (Citation1976)。此外,人们可能会怀疑哲学本身是否可以为政策制定做出合理的贡献(Wolff Citation2019)。我们承认,洛兰德对竞争公平的描述,尤其是他对稳定条件和动态条件的区分,与下文所述的一些政策建议存在冲突。然而,我们可以借鉴洛兰德的公平竞争机会原则,而不接受他对这一概念的进一步改进和应用。参见Camporesi (Citation2020);Camporesi和Hämäläinen (Citation2021);Hamalainen (Citation2012)。4。参见Berg (Citation2015), (Citation2018)。在英格利希的作品发表一年后,另一位女权主义哲学家艾丽斯·马里恩·杨(Iris Marion Young, Citation1979)进一步阐述了这一观点,她为体育运动中的性别隔离提出了基于正义的论点。通过借鉴西蒙娜·德·波伏娃的观点,她认为体育活动可以让个人蓬勃发展。因此,缺乏体育运动使他们无法发展对过完整的人类生活至关重要的能力。有关女权主义运动方法的分析,请参见Burke Citation2015.6。这一概念在Young (Citation1979)的作品中也发挥了关键作用。关于这一概念的详细分析,请参见Falbo (Citation2008)。正如Schultz等人(Citation2022)所阐述的那样,来自实施跨性别包容政策的社区的数据表明,“在高中阶段接纳跨性别运动员对顺性别妇女和女孩的体育参与或运动成绩没有负面影响”(22)。此外,他们还指出,有证据似乎表明,“变性人的加入并不会损害顺性人的参与;它改善了它”(22)。关于这一建议的批评,见Pike (Citation2023)。英格利希对接近理想的可能性持乐观态度,因为由于体育的发展潜力,人们长期以来一直接受体育。事实上,她希望女性进入体育界能够促进这些价值观的重新觉醒,这些价值观得到了广泛认同,但最近在大型商业体育的洗牌中却被遗忘了。如果能力分组要有效的话,这种重新觉醒是必要的”(《英国引文》1978,274)。正如一位匿名评论者所指出的那样,这种方法似乎只适用于那些肯定二元性别的跨性别者,而忽略了那些属于非二元性别的人。然而,事实并非如此。寻求进入竞技体育的非二元运动员可以很好地要求进入他们喜欢的类别,并受到与跨性别运动员相同的体现经验和体现优势资格标准的约束。例如,我们的框架将支持将加拿大足球运动员Quinn纳入女子类别。这与国际奥委会最近关于基于性别认同和性别差异的公平、包容和不歧视的框架是一致的。
{"title":"Embodied Experience, Embodied Advantage, and the Inclusion of Transgender Athletes in Competitive Sport: Expanded Framework, Criticisms, and Policy Recommendations","authors":"Francisco Javier Lopez Frias, Cesar R. Torres","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2260112","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2260112","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTIn a previous paper entitled ‘Beyond Physiology: Embodied Experience, Embodied Advantage, and the Inclusion of Transgender Athletes in Competitive Sport,’ we claim that analyses of the inclusion or exclusion of transgender athletes in competitive sport must go beyond physiological criteria and incorporate the notions of embodied experience and embodied advantage. Our stance has recently been challenged as impractical and excessively exclusionary. In this paper, we address these challenges and build upon them to expand on the policy implications of our original framework, highlighting that embodied experience and embodied advantage heavily influence athletic performance. We differentiate competitive fairness from justice to, with an emphasis on the inclusion of transgender women in competitive sport, formulate a justice-based argument for maximizing inclusion. Afterward, we identify ideal and nonideal policy recommendations connected to our analysis of embodied experience and embodied advantage. We ultimately advocate for a qualified inclusion that assesses potential residual (physiological and embodied) advantages while striving for justice and competitive fairness.KEYWORDS: transgender athletesembodied experienceinclusion, justicecompetitive fairness Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. See Birrell and Cole (Citation1990) and, among others, Herman (Citation1976) and Lautens (Citation1976).2. Moreover, one may wonder whether philosophy by itself can make sound contributions to policymaking (Wolff Citation2019).3. We acknowledge that Loland’s account of competitive fairness, especially his distinction between stable and dynamic conditions, clashes with some of the policy recommendations reviewed below. However, it is possible to draw on Loland’s fair play opportunity principle without also accepting (some of) his further refinements and applications of the notion. See Camporesi (Citation2020); Camporesi and Hämäläinen (Citation2021); Hämäläinen (Citation2012).4. Also see Berg (Citation2015), (Citation2018).5. One year after the publication of English’s work, Iris Marion Young (Citation1979), another feminist philosopher who formulated a justice-based argument for sex segregation in sport, expanded on this argument. By drawing on Simone de Beauvoir, she argued that sport engagement allows individuals to flourish. Thus, a lack of participation in sport prevents them from developing capacities crucial to leading fully human lives. For an analysis of feminist approaches to sport, see Burke Citation2015.6. This concept also plays a key role in the works of Young (Citation1979). For a detailed analysis of this concept, see Falbo (Citation2008).7. As Schultz et al. (Citation2022) expound, data from communities with transgender inclusive policies indicate that ‘the inclusion of trans athletes at the high school level has had no negative impact on sport participation or athletic achievements fo","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136061705","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ontology and interdisciplinary research in esports 电子竞技本体与跨学科研究
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-21 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2260567
Tom Brock
This article identifies the benefits of adopting a critical realist ontology to researching esports in the social sciences. The article outlines some of the challenges in researching esports, paying particular attention to the emerging specialisms and sub-disciplines. The article suggests that different schools of thought have different ontological and epistemological commitments, resulting in a complex and somewhat fragmented or contested set of definitions and research directives. The article considers how the philosophy of science can enable researchers to gain a more complete understanding and appreciation of esports. More specifically, the article outlines some of the central philosophical commitments of critical realism and considers their benefits for researching the multi-layered and multifaceted nature of esports. What results is a stratified ontology of esports, in which various biological, psychological and sociological factors interact to produce emergent outcomes at micro, meso and macro levels of causality. Such an interdisciplinary approach resists previous attempts to reduce esports research to singular (and competing) epistemological claims. Instead, this article invites sports researchers to investigate the complex ways natural and social factors interact to generate and change esports structures, institutions and agential behaviours.
本文确定了采用批判现实主义本体论在社会科学中研究电子竞技的好处。本文概述了研究电子竞技的一些挑战,特别关注新兴的专业和子学科。本文认为,不同的思想流派有不同的本体论和认识论的承诺,导致一套复杂的,有些支离破碎或有争议的定义和研究方向。本文探讨了科学哲学如何使研究人员对电子竞技有更全面的了解和欣赏。更具体地说,本文概述了批判现实主义的一些核心哲学承诺,并考虑了它们对研究电子竞技的多层次和多面性的好处。结果是电子竞技的分层本体,其中各种生物,心理和社会学因素相互作用,在微观,中观和宏观因果关系层面产生紧急结果。这种跨学科的方法抵制了之前将电子竞技研究减少到单一(和竞争)认识论主张的尝试。相反,本文邀请体育研究人员调查自然因素和社会因素相互作用产生和改变电子竞技结构、制度和代理行为的复杂方式。
{"title":"Ontology and interdisciplinary research in esports","authors":"Tom Brock","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2260567","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2260567","url":null,"abstract":"This article identifies the benefits of adopting a critical realist ontology to researching esports in the social sciences. The article outlines some of the challenges in researching esports, paying particular attention to the emerging specialisms and sub-disciplines. The article suggests that different schools of thought have different ontological and epistemological commitments, resulting in a complex and somewhat fragmented or contested set of definitions and research directives. The article considers how the philosophy of science can enable researchers to gain a more complete understanding and appreciation of esports. More specifically, the article outlines some of the central philosophical commitments of critical realism and considers their benefits for researching the multi-layered and multifaceted nature of esports. What results is a stratified ontology of esports, in which various biological, psychological and sociological factors interact to produce emergent outcomes at micro, meso and macro levels of causality. Such an interdisciplinary approach resists previous attempts to reduce esports research to singular (and competing) epistemological claims. Instead, this article invites sports researchers to investigate the complex ways natural and social factors interact to generate and change esports structures, institutions and agential behaviours.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136135901","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Heidegger and the possibilities of ‘Authenticity’ in Sports participation 海德格尔与体育参与中“真实性”的可能性
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-19 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2259620
Neslihan Filiz
ABSTRACTThe aim of this paper is to analyze the possibility of ‘authenticity’, in other words, ‘authentic being’ in sports, based on the ideas in Heidegger’s Being and Time (Sein und Zeit). In order to do that, I firstly explain Dasein and its existentialia (which are significant for this paper: being-in-the-world, thrownness, understanding, attunement, and possibilities), the concept of ‘care’, and Heideggerian understanding of authenticity. Then, I examine the possibilities of authenticity in sports participation, and I look at some related studies analyzing the Heideggerian take on authenticity in sports. Finally, considering human existence (i.e. Dasein) within the sportsworld, I describe some possibilities for an authentic being to reveal itself, even for a short moment, such as ‘the realization of our finitude’ (by confronting death, especially in extreme sports); ‘coping with failure or loss (by facing with the call of conscience)’; ‘anxiety of losing the familiarity to the world’ (non-skillful coping in sports) and anxiety accompanying the realization of being-in-the-sportsworld’ (They-self vs. One-Self as an athlete) etc.KEYWORDS: Heideggersportsauthenticityauthentic being AcknowledgmentsI really appreciate Assoc. Prof. Dr. Irena Parry Martínková and two anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. This article was partially submitted as a presentation at the 11th Czech Philosophy of Sport Conference.2. Heidegger uses the term ‘Dasein’ to address the being of human beings (or i.e. human existence). It is the central concept used in B&T which is wisely-chosen by Heidegger to denote that only human beings have the the possibility of an existential understanding of ‘what it means to exist’ by way of self-relation and its relation to other beings. Moreover, Dasein is the entity which makes its very Being an issue (and the meaning of Being) and so, cares.3. ‘existentialia’ i.e. the existential structures of Dasein. HEIDEGGER (Citation2001, §9, 71) states that “Existentialia andcategories are the two basic possibilities for characters of Being. The entities which correspond to them require different kinds of primary interrogation respectively: any entity is either a ‘who’ (existence) or a ‘what’ (presence-at-hand in the broadest sense)”. Therefore, we need existentialia to interpret the Being of Dasein, its existence.4. Here, it is significant to distinguish what ontological (i.e. ontologico-existential) and ontical (ontico-existentiell) inquiries mean. In the footnote of their translation of B&T, Macquarrie & Robinson define the terms as follows: the ontical one is “concerned with the entities and the facts about them and the ontological one is ‘concerned primarily with Being’5. As the translators of B&T, Macquarrie and Robinson, clarified in a footnote that the German Stimmung is ‘the usual word for one’s mood or humour’ and they prefer to translat
摘要本文旨在从海德格尔的《存在与时间》(Sein und Zeit)的观点出发,分析体育运动中“本真”即“本真存在”的可能性。为了做到这一点,我首先解释此在及其存在性(这对本文来说很重要:在世界中存在、抛掷、理解、调和和可能性)、“关心”的概念,以及海德格尔对真实性的理解。然后,我考察了真实性在体育参与中的可能性,我看了一些相关的研究,分析海德格尔对体育真实性的看法。最后,考虑到体育世界中的人类存在(即此在),我描述了一些真实存在揭示自身的可能性,即使是短暂的时刻,例如“实现我们的有限性”(通过面对死亡,特别是在极限运动中);“面对失败或损失(通过面对良心的召唤)”;“对世界失去熟悉感的焦虑”(运动中的非熟练应对)和“在运动世界中存在的焦虑”(作为运动员的自我vs.自我)等。关键词:海德格尔体育真实性真实性认同我很欣赏协会Irena Parry博士教授Martínková和两位匿名评论者的宝贵意见。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。这篇文章的一部分是作为第11届捷克体育哲学会议的报告提交的。海德格尔使用“此在”一词来表述人的存在(即人的存在)。这是海德格尔明智地选择在《理性与批判》中使用的中心概念,以表示只有人类才有可能通过自我关系及其与其他存在的关系来理解“存在的意义”。而且,此在是一个实体,它使它的存在本身成为一个问题(和存在的意义)。存在主义,即此在的存在结构。海德格尔(Citation2001,§9,71)指出:“存在性和范畴是存在的两种基本可能性。与它们相对应的实体分别需要不同类型的初级讯问:任何实体要么是‘谁’(存在),要么是‘什么’(最广义上的在场)”。因此,我们需要存在主义来解释此在的存在,即它的存在。在这里,区分本体论(即本体论-存在主义)和本体论(即本体论-存在主义)调查的含义是很重要的。在翻译《B&T》的脚注中,麦考瑞和罗宾逊对这两个术语的定义如下:本体论“关注实体和关于实体的事实”,而本体论“主要关注存在”。正如《B&T》的译者麦考瑞和罗宾逊在脚注中澄清的那样,德语Stimmung是“一个人的情绪或幽默的常用词汇”,他们更愿意把它翻译成“情绪”。同样,他们将Gestimmtsein翻译为“与北京和谐”,将Befindlichkeit翻译为“精神状态”。然而,他们警告我们,“of-mind”属于英语成语,在德语单词“of-mind”的结构中没有对应的字面意思。有些作家在谈论“协调”的存在主义时使用Stimmung,有些使用Befindlichkeit,这就是为什么我把两个德语单词都放在括号里。在拉丁语中,它的意思是“独自一人”或“独自一人”。关于规则的进一步讨论,可以看《The Grasshopper of Suits》,第6章:Ivan和abdul。另一方面,埃德加(Citation2013)声称,当运动员和观众的全部注意力集中在创造表演的动作和材料上时,体育有可能使人类及其世界摆脱器质性的干扰。1. 目标很明确。2. 反馈是即时的。3.技能匹配挑战。4. 专注是深度的。5. 问题被遗忘了。6. 控制是可能的。7. 自我意识消失。时间的感觉被改变了。9. 这种体验会自动消失。德雷福斯在他的技能模型中试图表明,最高水平的技能如何表现出越来越无意识和自动的行为形式。专家只是采取行动。他们不需要进行反思性和主题性的思考。身体最清楚。大脑中的平行网络完成了这项工作”(Breivik Citation2007 p.132)。事实上,Breivik在他进一步的文章《危险的元素游戏:走向冒险运动的现象学》中也对其他一些冒险运动做了这样的分析。GORICHANAZ (Citation2019)解释说,在某个时候决定不继续跑步和停止跑步不仅是一种DNF,而且还会出现急性症状,经历精神衰竭,速度太慢。在某些情况下,官员们也会做出这样的决定,为特定的超级马拉松运动员结束比赛。 本研究由土耳其科学技术研究委员会在TUBITAK-2219土耳其公民国际博士后研究奖学金项目下支持。
{"title":"Heidegger and the possibilities of ‘Authenticity’ in Sports participation","authors":"Neslihan Filiz","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2259620","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2259620","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThe aim of this paper is to analyze the possibility of ‘authenticity’, in other words, ‘authentic being’ in sports, based on the ideas in Heidegger’s Being and Time (Sein und Zeit). In order to do that, I firstly explain Dasein and its existentialia (which are significant for this paper: being-in-the-world, thrownness, understanding, attunement, and possibilities), the concept of ‘care’, and Heideggerian understanding of authenticity. Then, I examine the possibilities of authenticity in sports participation, and I look at some related studies analyzing the Heideggerian take on authenticity in sports. Finally, considering human existence (i.e. Dasein) within the sportsworld, I describe some possibilities for an authentic being to reveal itself, even for a short moment, such as ‘the realization of our finitude’ (by confronting death, especially in extreme sports); ‘coping with failure or loss (by facing with the call of conscience)’; ‘anxiety of losing the familiarity to the world’ (non-skillful coping in sports) and anxiety accompanying the realization of being-in-the-sportsworld’ (They-self vs. One-Self as an athlete) etc.KEYWORDS: Heideggersportsauthenticityauthentic being AcknowledgmentsI really appreciate Assoc. Prof. Dr. Irena Parry Martínková and two anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. This article was partially submitted as a presentation at the 11th Czech Philosophy of Sport Conference.2. Heidegger uses the term ‘Dasein’ to address the being of human beings (or i.e. human existence). It is the central concept used in B&T which is wisely-chosen by Heidegger to denote that only human beings have the the possibility of an existential understanding of ‘what it means to exist’ by way of self-relation and its relation to other beings. Moreover, Dasein is the entity which makes its very Being an issue (and the meaning of Being) and so, cares.3. ‘existentialia’ i.e. the existential structures of Dasein. HEIDEGGER (Citation2001, §9, 71) states that “Existentialia andcategories are the two basic possibilities for characters of Being. The entities which correspond to them require different kinds of primary interrogation respectively: any entity is either a ‘who’ (existence) or a ‘what’ (presence-at-hand in the broadest sense)”. Therefore, we need existentialia to interpret the Being of Dasein, its existence.4. Here, it is significant to distinguish what ontological (i.e. ontologico-existential) and ontical (ontico-existentiell) inquiries mean. In the footnote of their translation of B&T, Macquarrie & Robinson define the terms as follows: the ontical one is “concerned with the entities and the facts about them and the ontological one is ‘concerned primarily with Being’5. As the translators of B&T, Macquarrie and Robinson, clarified in a footnote that the German Stimmung is ‘the usual word for one’s mood or humour’ and they prefer to translat","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135059184","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Anschlag auf Olympia. Was 1972 in München wirklich geschah 炸了奥林匹亚1972年慕尼黑到底发生了什么
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-14 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2256985
Jacob Kornbeck
Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1. The planners hadn’t yet reached today’s belief in banning cars from city centres, but rather took the functional separation of Le Corbusier to the next stage, by sending cars underground and reserving the open spaces for pedestrians, just like they were two a decade later in Louvain-la-Neuve, the Belgian university city planned and build to host the francophone half of the old Catholic University of Leuven who had been expelled thence following the events of 1968 (where 1968 didn’t mean the same as in the rest of the global West). My pictures from that warm summer evening—during a summer regularly featuring the highest temperatures recorded to date—seem to have captured what I felt during that evening walk.2. There is a curious reticence in Germany to use the army for domestic security purposes, usually backed up by woolly references to ‘German history’. Such explanations are flawed, as Hitler did not take power through a military coup, while the big street fights of the Weimar Republic were carried out by heavily armoured and motorised police forces, not the army, yet the taboo persists, although mass-scale repression through troops has not happened since 1848.
点击增大图片尺寸点击减小图片尺寸披露声明作者未发现潜在的利益冲突。当时的规划者还没有达到今天禁止汽车进入城市中心的理念,而是将勒·柯布西耶的功能分离带入了下一个阶段,将汽车送到地下,并为行人保留开放空间,就像20年后在卢万-拉-纽夫所做的那样,这座比利时大学城的规划和建设是为了容纳在1968年事件后被驱逐的旧天主教鲁汶大学讲法语的一半(1968年与全球其他西方国家的意义不同)。我在那个温暖的夏夜拍摄的照片,似乎捕捉到了我在那个夜晚散步时的感受。奇怪的是,在德国,为了国内安全目的而动用军队是一种沉默,通常以模糊的“德国历史”作为佐证。这种解释是有缺陷的,因为希特勒不是通过军事政变夺取政权的,而魏玛共和国的大规模街头战斗是由全副武装的机动警察部队而不是军队进行的,尽管自1848年以来没有发生过大规模的军队镇压,但禁忌仍然存在。
{"title":"Anschlag auf Olympia. Was 1972 in München wirklich geschah","authors":"Jacob Kornbeck","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2256985","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2256985","url":null,"abstract":"Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1. The planners hadn’t yet reached today’s belief in banning cars from city centres, but rather took the functional separation of Le Corbusier to the next stage, by sending cars underground and reserving the open spaces for pedestrians, just like they were two a decade later in Louvain-la-Neuve, the Belgian university city planned and build to host the francophone half of the old Catholic University of Leuven who had been expelled thence following the events of 1968 (where 1968 didn’t mean the same as in the rest of the global West). My pictures from that warm summer evening—during a summer regularly featuring the highest temperatures recorded to date—seem to have captured what I felt during that evening walk.2. There is a curious reticence in Germany to use the army for domestic security purposes, usually backed up by woolly references to ‘German history’. Such explanations are flawed, as Hitler did not take power through a military coup, while the big street fights of the Weimar Republic were carried out by heavily armoured and motorised police forces, not the army, yet the taboo persists, although mass-scale repression through troops has not happened since 1848.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134913030","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
“Nothing is funnier than suffering”. Sport as a comic and perverse aesthetic practice “没有什么比受苦更有趣的了”。体育是一种滑稽而反常的审美实践
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-12 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2256988
Andy Harvey
The article takes up diverse strands of psychoanalytic thinking to investigate how desire is manifested in male team sporting environments. In particular, it is posited that sporting desire shares a remarkable structural similarity to the joking relationship in that they both work through the overcoming of obstacles. In doing so unconscious desires are long-circuited and only emerge in radically altered form, upending traditional gender and sexual subjectivities in the process. The paper explores the concept of desire from perspectives that are either straightforwardly psychoanalytic or heavily influenced by psychoanalytic thought. Initially, I examine desire from a Freudian viewpoint before looking at how Jacques Lacan extended Freudian analysis through a linguistic lens. I then explore desire in terms developed by Gilles Deleuze before turning, in the second part of the paper, to an examination of the work of George Bataille to consider the desire of sport through the mechanism of the joke to trace the complex routing that it often takes.
本文采用不同的精神分析思维来研究欲望是如何在男性团队运动环境中表现出来的。特别是,有人认为运动欲望与开玩笑的关系有着显著的结构相似性,因为它们都是通过克服障碍来工作的。在这样做的过程中,无意识的欲望是长期循环的,只会以根本改变的形式出现,在这个过程中颠覆了传统的性别和性主体性。本文从直接精神分析或受精神分析思想严重影响的角度探讨了欲望的概念。首先,我从弗洛伊德的观点来审视欲望,然后再看雅克·拉康如何通过语言的视角来扩展弗洛伊德的分析。然后,我用吉尔·德勒兹提出的术语来探讨欲望,然后在论文的第二部分,转向乔治·巴塔耶的研究工作,通过笑话的机制来考虑运动的欲望,以追踪它经常采取的复杂路线。
{"title":"“Nothing is funnier than suffering”. Sport as a comic and perverse aesthetic practice","authors":"Andy Harvey","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2256988","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2256988","url":null,"abstract":"The article takes up diverse strands of psychoanalytic thinking to investigate how desire is manifested in male team sporting environments. In particular, it is posited that sporting desire shares a remarkable structural similarity to the joking relationship in that they both work through the overcoming of obstacles. In doing so unconscious desires are long-circuited and only emerge in radically altered form, upending traditional gender and sexual subjectivities in the process. The paper explores the concept of desire from perspectives that are either straightforwardly psychoanalytic or heavily influenced by psychoanalytic thought. Initially, I examine desire from a Freudian viewpoint before looking at how Jacques Lacan extended Freudian analysis through a linguistic lens. I then explore desire in terms developed by Gilles Deleuze before turning, in the second part of the paper, to an examination of the work of George Bataille to consider the desire of sport through the mechanism of the joke to trace the complex routing that it often takes.","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135826362","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Why the rules do not prohibit cheating in sports 为什么规则不禁止体育作弊
IF 1.3 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-07 DOI: 10.1080/17511321.2023.2254941
Sinclair A. MacRae
{"title":"Why the rules do not prohibit cheating in sports","authors":"Sinclair A. MacRae","doi":"10.1080/17511321.2023.2254941","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2023.2254941","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51786,"journal":{"name":"Sport Ethics and Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2023-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80820502","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Sport Ethics and Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1