首页 > 最新文献

Disputatio (Spain)最新文献

英文 中文
Blame and Fault: Toward a New Conative Theory of Blame 责备与过错:论一种新的责备理论
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0018
László Bernáth
Abstract This paper outlines a new conative theory of blame. I argue that the best-known conative approaches to blame (Scanlon 1998, 2008, Sher 2006a) misrepresent the cognitive and dispositional components of blame. Section 1 argues, against Scanlon and Sher, that blaming involves the judgment that an act or state is the fault of the blamed. I also propose an alternative dispositional condition on which blaming only occurs if it matters to the blamer whether the blamed gets the punishment that she deserves. In Section 2, I discuss objections to judgment-based accounts of blame (that they cannot tell the difference between blaming and judging to be blameworthy, that they cannot explain why blame is often accompanied by emotion, and that they cannot make sense of irrational blame), and I argue that my proposal can handle all of them.
摘要本文提出了一种新的过失论。我认为,最著名的责备方法(Scanlon 1998,2008, Sher 2006a)歪曲了责备的认知和性格成分。第一节反驳了斯坎伦和谢尔的观点,认为指责包括判断一个行为或国家是被指责者的过错。我还提出了另一种性格条件,即只有当被责备者是否得到应有的惩罚对责备者来说很重要时,责备才会发生。在第2节中,我讨论了对基于判断的指责的反对意见(他们无法区分指责和判断应该受到指责之间的区别,他们无法解释为什么指责经常伴随着情绪,他们无法理解非理性的指责),我认为我的建议可以处理所有这些问题。
{"title":"Blame and Fault: Toward a New Conative Theory of Blame","authors":"László Bernáth","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0018","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0018","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This paper outlines a new conative theory of blame. I argue that the best-known conative approaches to blame (Scanlon 1998, 2008, Sher 2006a) misrepresent the cognitive and dispositional components of blame. Section 1 argues, against Scanlon and Sher, that blaming involves the judgment that an act or state is the fault of the blamed. I also propose an alternative dispositional condition on which blaming only occurs if it matters to the blamer whether the blamed gets the punishment that she deserves. In Section 2, I discuss objections to judgment-based accounts of blame (that they cannot tell the difference between blaming and judging to be blameworthy, that they cannot explain why blame is often accompanied by emotion, and that they cannot make sense of irrational blame), and I argue that my proposal can handle all of them.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"39 1","pages":"371 - 394"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74337309","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Logic in Natural Language: Commitments and Constraints 自然语言中的逻辑:承诺与约束
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0014
Gil Sagi
Abstract In his new book, Logical Form, Andrea Iacona distinguishes between two different roles that have been ascribed to the notion of logical form: the logical role and the semantic role. These two roles entail a bifurcation of the notion of logical form. Both notions of logical form, according to Iacona, are descriptive, having to do with different features of natural language sentences. I agree that the notion of logical form bifurcates, but not that the logical role is merely descriptive. In this paper, I focus on formalization, a process by which logical form, on its logical role, is attributed to natural language sentences. According to some, formalization is a form of explication, and it involves normative, pragmatic, as well as creative aspects. I present a view by which formalization involves explicit commitments on behalf of a reasoner or an interpreter, which serve the normative grounds for the evaluation of a given text. In previous work, I proposed the framework of semantic constraints for the explication of logical consequence. Here, I extend the framework to include formalization constraints. The various constraints then serve the role of commitments. I discuss specific issues raised by Iacona concerning univocality, co-reference and equivocation, and I show how our views on these matters diverge as a result of our different starting assumptions.
在Andrea Iacona的新书《逻辑形式》中,他区分了逻辑形式概念的两种不同角色:逻辑角色和语义角色。这两个角色导致了逻辑形式概念的分叉。根据Iacona的说法,逻辑形式的两个概念都是描述性的,与自然语言句子的不同特征有关。我同意逻辑形式的概念是分岔的,但不同意逻辑角色仅仅是描述性的。在本文中,我将重点放在形式化上,这是一个将逻辑形式及其逻辑作用归因于自然语言句子的过程。根据一些人的观点,形式化是一种解释的形式,它涉及规范性、语用性和创造性方面。我提出了一种观点,通过这种观点,形式化涉及代表推理者或解释者的明确承诺,这些承诺为评估给定文本提供了规范性依据。在之前的工作中,我提出了语义约束框架来解释逻辑结果。在这里,我扩展了框架以包含形式化约束。然后,各种约束就起到了承诺的作用。我讨论了Iacona提出的关于单一性、共同指称和模棱两可的具体问题,并展示了我们对这些问题的看法是如何由于我们不同的初始假设而产生分歧的。
{"title":"Logic in Natural Language: Commitments and Constraints","authors":"Gil Sagi","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0014","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In his new book, Logical Form, Andrea Iacona distinguishes between two different roles that have been ascribed to the notion of logical form: the logical role and the semantic role. These two roles entail a bifurcation of the notion of logical form. Both notions of logical form, according to Iacona, are descriptive, having to do with different features of natural language sentences. I agree that the notion of logical form bifurcates, but not that the logical role is merely descriptive. In this paper, I focus on formalization, a process by which logical form, on its logical role, is attributed to natural language sentences. According to some, formalization is a form of explication, and it involves normative, pragmatic, as well as creative aspects. I present a view by which formalization involves explicit commitments on behalf of a reasoner or an interpreter, which serve the normative grounds for the evaluation of a given text. In previous work, I proposed the framework of semantic constraints for the explication of logical consequence. Here, I extend the framework to include formalization constraints. The various constraints then serve the role of commitments. I discuss specific issues raised by Iacona concerning univocality, co-reference and equivocation, and I show how our views on these matters diverge as a result of our different starting assumptions.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"26 1","pages":"277 - 308"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78517647","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Two Informational Theories of Memory: a case from Memory-Conjunction Errors 记忆的两种信息理论:以记忆连接错误为例
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0019
D. Dantas
Abstract The causal and simulation theories are often presented as very distinct views about declarative memory, their major difference lying on the causal condition. The causal theory states that remembering involves an accurate representation causally connected to an earlier experience (the causal condition). In the simulation theory, remembering involves an accurate representation generated by a reliable memory process (no causal condition). I investigate how to construe detailed versions of these theories that correctly classify memory errors (DRM, “lost in the mall”, and memory-conjunction errors) as misremembering or confabulation. Neither causalists nor simulationists have paid attention to memory-conjunction errors, which is unfortunate because both theories have problems with these cases. The source of the difficulty is the background assumption that an act of remembering has one (and only one) target. I fix these theories for those cases. The resulting versions are closely related when implemented using tools of information theory, differing only on how memory transmits information about the past. The implementation provides us with insights about the distinction between confabulatory and non-confabulatory memory, where memory-conjunction errors have a privileged position.
因果理论和模拟理论通常被认为是陈述性记忆的两种截然不同的观点,它们的主要区别在于因果条件。因果理论指出,记忆涉及到与先前经历(因果条件)有因果关系的准确表征。在模拟理论中,记忆包括由可靠的记忆过程(无因果条件)产生的准确表征。我研究了如何解释这些理论的详细版本,以正确地将记忆错误(DRM、“在商场迷路”和记忆连接错误)分类为错误记忆或虚构。因果主义者和模拟主义者都没有注意到记忆连接错误,这是不幸的,因为这两种理论在这些情况下都有问题。困难的来源是背景假设,即记忆行为有一个(且只有一个)目标。我根据这些案例修正这些理论。当使用信息理论工具实现时,所得到的版本是密切相关的,不同的只是记忆如何传递关于过去的信息。该实现为我们提供了关于虚构记忆和非虚构记忆之间区别的见解,其中记忆连接错误具有特权地位。
{"title":"Two Informational Theories of Memory: a case from Memory-Conjunction Errors","authors":"D. Dantas","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0019","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0019","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The causal and simulation theories are often presented as very distinct views about declarative memory, their major difference lying on the causal condition. The causal theory states that remembering involves an accurate representation causally connected to an earlier experience (the causal condition). In the simulation theory, remembering involves an accurate representation generated by a reliable memory process (no causal condition). I investigate how to construe detailed versions of these theories that correctly classify memory errors (DRM, “lost in the mall”, and memory-conjunction errors) as misremembering or confabulation. Neither causalists nor simulationists have paid attention to memory-conjunction errors, which is unfortunate because both theories have problems with these cases. The source of the difficulty is the background assumption that an act of remembering has one (and only one) target. I fix these theories for those cases. The resulting versions are closely related when implemented using tools of information theory, differing only on how memory transmits information about the past. The implementation provides us with insights about the distinction between confabulatory and non-confabulatory memory, where memory-conjunction errors have a privileged position.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"75 1","pages":"395 - 431"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77411219","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Early Modern Origins of Pragmatism 近代早期实用主义的起源
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0020
P. Szałek
Abstract This paper considers the alleged pragmatism of Berkeley’s philosophy using the two Sellarsian categories of ‘manifest’ and ‘scientific’ images of the world and human beings. The ‘manifest’ image is regarded as a refinement of the ordinary way of conceiving things, and the scientific image is seen as a theoretical picture of the world provided by science. The paper argues that the so-called Berkeleian pragmatism was an effect of Berkeley’s work towards a synthesis of ‘manifest’ and ‘scientific’ images through the creation of one unified synoptic vision of the world and was a part of a new conceptual framework within which these two images could be combined.
摘要本文运用塞拉式的世界和人类的“显象”和“科学”两个范畴来考察贝克莱哲学的实用主义。“显象”被看作是对一般事物的认识方式的改进,而“科学象”则被看作是科学所提供的关于世界的理论图景。这篇论文认为,所谓的贝克莱实用主义是贝克莱通过创造一个统一的对世界的概要性视觉,将“明显的”和“科学的”图像综合起来的工作的结果,是一个新的概念框架的一部分,在这个框架内,这两个图像可以结合起来。
{"title":"The Early Modern Origins of Pragmatism","authors":"P. Szałek","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0020","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0020","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This paper considers the alleged pragmatism of Berkeley’s philosophy using the two Sellarsian categories of ‘manifest’ and ‘scientific’ images of the world and human beings. The ‘manifest’ image is regarded as a refinement of the ordinary way of conceiving things, and the scientific image is seen as a theoretical picture of the world provided by science. The paper argues that the so-called Berkeleian pragmatism was an effect of Berkeley’s work towards a synthesis of ‘manifest’ and ‘scientific’ images through the creation of one unified synoptic vision of the world and was a part of a new conceptual framework within which these two images could be combined.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"7 1","pages":"433 - 456"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75724570","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Anaphoric Dependence and Logical Form 回指依存与逻辑形式
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0013
M. García‐Carpintero
Abstract In the core chapters 4–6, Iacona (2018) argues against the “Uniqueness Thesis” (UT), stating that “there is a unique notion of logical form that fulfils both the logical role and the semantic role” (39), where the former “concerns the formal explanation of logical properties and logical relations, such as validity or contradiction” (37), and the latter “concerns the formulation of a compositional theory of meaning” (ibid.). He argues for this on the basis of relations of coreference among referential expressions, names and indexicals. From what I take to be a fundamental agreement on most relevant issues, here I will nonetheless press him to clarify the notions of intrinsicness and the logical and semantic role of logical form on which he relies.
在核心章节4-6中,Iacona(2018)反对“唯一性命题”(UT),指出“存在一种独特的逻辑形式概念,它既满足逻辑角色,也满足语义角色”(39),其中前者“涉及逻辑属性和逻辑关系的形式解释,例如有效性或矛盾性”(37),后者“涉及意义组合理论的形成”(同上)。他在指称表达式、名称和索引之间的共指关系的基础上论证了这一点。从我所认为的在大多数相关问题上的基本共识出发,我将在这里敦促他澄清内在的概念,以及他所依赖的逻辑形式的逻辑和语义角色。
{"title":"Anaphoric Dependence and Logical Form","authors":"M. García‐Carpintero","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0013","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0013","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In the core chapters 4–6, Iacona (2018) argues against the “Uniqueness Thesis” (UT), stating that “there is a unique notion of logical form that fulfils both the logical role and the semantic role” (39), where the former “concerns the formal explanation of logical properties and logical relations, such as validity or contradiction” (37), and the latter “concerns the formulation of a compositional theory of meaning” (ibid.). He argues for this on the basis of relations of coreference among referential expressions, names and indexicals. From what I take to be a fundamental agreement on most relevant issues, here I will nonetheless press him to clarify the notions of intrinsicness and the logical and semantic role of logical form on which he relies.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"138 1","pages":"265 - 276"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89913911","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Minding Strangers’ Business 管陌生人的事
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0017
Yotam Benziman
Abstract When should we interfere in the course of a stranger’s life? While philosophers have discussed at length extreme cases of assisting poor people in famine stricken countries, much less attention has been given to casual, everyday episodes. If I overhear two people discussing a place they are about to visit, and know that it is closed for renovation, should I interfere and tell them so? If I stand next to a customer who has not been given enough change in the supermarket, should I point that out or mind my own business? Using the Kantian notions of love and respect, I answer such questions. I claim that Kant’s terminology is ill-suited for instructing us how to deal with others with whom we are personally involved, but is important for our encounters with strangers. I suggest that we take seriously Kant’s claim that we are “united in one dwelling place”. When around others, keep an open eye to the possibility that they might need help. If there is good reason to suppose that you may help, knock on their door. Let them decide whether they want to open it. They are totally entitled to decline the offer, but should keep in mind that it was given as part of the joint venture of living together with others. The interference should therefore not be regarded as an infringement of privacy.
什么时候我们应该干预一个陌生人的生活?虽然哲学家们已经详细讨论了在饥荒肆虐的国家帮助穷人的极端案例,但很少有人关注日常生活中的偶然事件。如果我无意中听到两个人在谈论他们即将参观的一个地方,并且知道它已经关闭进行装修,我应该干涉并告诉他们吗?如果站在我旁边的顾客在超市里没有得到足够的零钱,我应该指出这一点还是少管闲事?我用康德关于爱和尊重的概念来回答这些问题。我认为康德的术语并不适合指导我们如何处理与我们个人有关的人,但对于我们与陌生人的接触却很重要。我建议我们认真对待康德的主张,即我们“团结在一个居所”。当你和别人在一起的时候,留心他们是否需要帮助。如果有很好的理由认为你可以帮忙,那就去敲他们的门。让他们决定是否要打开它。他们完全有权拒绝这一提议,但应记住,这是作为与他人共同生活的共同事业的一部分而给予的。因此,这种干涉不应被视为侵犯隐私。
{"title":"Minding Strangers’ Business","authors":"Yotam Benziman","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0017","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0017","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract When should we interfere in the course of a stranger’s life? While philosophers have discussed at length extreme cases of assisting poor people in famine stricken countries, much less attention has been given to casual, everyday episodes. If I overhear two people discussing a place they are about to visit, and know that it is closed for renovation, should I interfere and tell them so? If I stand next to a customer who has not been given enough change in the supermarket, should I point that out or mind my own business? Using the Kantian notions of love and respect, I answer such questions. I claim that Kant’s terminology is ill-suited for instructing us how to deal with others with whom we are personally involved, but is important for our encounters with strangers. I suggest that we take seriously Kant’s claim that we are “united in one dwelling place”. When around others, keep an open eye to the possibility that they might need help. If there is good reason to suppose that you may help, knock on their door. Let them decide whether they want to open it. They are totally entitled to decline the offer, but should keep in mind that it was given as part of the joint venture of living together with others. The interference should therefore not be regarded as an infringement of privacy.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"12 1","pages":"357 - 370"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78135552","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Dynamic Theory of Time and Time Travel to the Past 时间动力学理论和回到过去的时间旅行
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-11-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0006
N. Markosian
Abstract I argue that time travel to the past is impossible, given a certain metaphysical theory, namely, The Dynamic Theory of Time. I first spell out my particular way of capturing the difference between The Dynamic Theory of Time and its rival, The Static Theory of Time. Next I offer four different arguments for the conclusion that The Dynamic Theory is inconsistent with the possibility of time travel to the past. Then I argue that, even if I am wrong about this, it will still be true that The Dynamic Theory entails that you should not want to travel back to the past. Finally, I conclude by considering a puzzle that arises for those who believe that time travel to the past is metaphysically impossible: What exactly are we thinking about when we seem to be thinking about traveling back in time? For it certainly does not feel like we are thinking about something that is metaphysically impossible.
摘要:在一定的形而上学理论,即时间动力学理论的前提下,我认为穿越到过去是不可能的。首先,我将阐述我的独特方式,以捕捉《动态时间理论》与其竞争对手《静态时间理论》之间的差异。接下来,我提供了四个不同的论据来证明动力学理论与过去时间旅行的可能性不一致。然后我会说,即使我在这一点上是错的,但动力学理论仍然是正确的,即你不应该想要回到过去。最后,对于那些认为穿越到过去在形而上学上是不可能的人来说,我想提出一个难题:当我们似乎在思考穿越到过去的时候,我们到底在想什么?因为我们肯定不会觉得我们在思考形而上学上不可能的事情。
{"title":"The Dynamic Theory of Time and Time Travel to the Past","authors":"N. Markosian","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0006","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract I argue that time travel to the past is impossible, given a certain metaphysical theory, namely, The Dynamic Theory of Time. I first spell out my particular way of capturing the difference between The Dynamic Theory of Time and its rival, The Static Theory of Time. Next I offer four different arguments for the conclusion that The Dynamic Theory is inconsistent with the possibility of time travel to the past. Then I argue that, even if I am wrong about this, it will still be true that The Dynamic Theory entails that you should not want to travel back to the past. Finally, I conclude by considering a puzzle that arises for those who believe that time travel to the past is metaphysically impossible: What exactly are we thinking about when we seem to be thinking about traveling back in time? For it certainly does not feel like we are thinking about something that is metaphysically impossible.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"50 1","pages":"137 - 165"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79137630","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Simply Finding Answers, or the Entirety of Inquiry While Standing on One Foot 简单地寻找答案,或者单脚站立时的全部询问
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-11-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0008
Nicholas Smith
Abstract I argue that inquiry can be defined without reference to the attitudes inquirers have during inquiry. Inquiry can instead be defined by its aim: it is the activity that has the aim of answering a question. I call this approach to defining inquiry a “naive” account. I present the naive account of inquiry in contrast to a prominent contemporary account of inquiry most notably defended by Jane Friedman. According to this view of inquiry, which I call an attitude-centric view, inquiry is appropriately defined not by the aim of the activity but by the attitudes that inquirers have during inquiry. After developing the naive view, I defend it against the objection that it collapses into the attitude-centric view.
摘要本文认为探究的定义可以不参考探究者在探究过程中的态度。探究可以用它的目的来定义:它是一种以回答问题为目的的活动。我把这种定义探究的方法称为“天真”的说法。我提出了一种关于探究的朴素描述,与简·弗里德曼(Jane Friedman)最著名的当代探究描述形成对比。根据这种我称之为“态度中心观”的探究观,探究的恰当定义不是由活动的目的,而是由调查者在探究过程中所持的态度。在发展朴素观点之后,我为它辩护,反对它瓦解为态度中心观点。
{"title":"Simply Finding Answers, or the Entirety of Inquiry While Standing on One Foot","authors":"Nicholas Smith","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0008","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract I argue that inquiry can be defined without reference to the attitudes inquirers have during inquiry. Inquiry can instead be defined by its aim: it is the activity that has the aim of answering a question. I call this approach to defining inquiry a “naive” account. I present the naive account of inquiry in contrast to a prominent contemporary account of inquiry most notably defended by Jane Friedman. According to this view of inquiry, which I call an attitude-centric view, inquiry is appropriately defined not by the aim of the activity but by the attitudes that inquirers have during inquiry. After developing the naive view, I defend it against the objection that it collapses into the attitude-centric view.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"24 1","pages":"181 - 198"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90353097","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Descriptive Rules and Normativity 描述性规则和规范性
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-11-01 DOI: 10.2478/disp-2020-0007
Adriana Placani
Abstract This work offers a challenge to the orthodox view that descriptive rules are non-normative and passive in their role and usage. It does so by arguing that, although lacking in normativity themselves, descriptive rules can be sources of normativity by way of the normative attitudes that can develop around them. That is, although descriptive rules typically depict how things are, they can also play a role in how things ought to be. In this way, the limited role that this type of rule can play as either a basis for the development of normative reasons, or as explanatory reasons for action is identified and clarified. One desirable outcome of the analysis is a more complete view of what descriptive rules are and how they are utilized by agents.
摘要本文对描述性规则在其作用和使用中是非规范性和被动的正统观点提出了挑战。它通过论证,尽管描述性规则本身缺乏规范性,但它可以成为规范性的来源通过围绕它们形成的规范性态度。也就是说,尽管描述性规则通常描述事物是怎样的,但它们也可以在事物应该是怎样的方面发挥作用。这样,这种类型的规则既可以作为发展规范性理由的基础,也可以作为行动的解释性理由,其有限的作用得到了确认和澄清。分析的一个理想结果是更完整地了解什么是描述性规则以及代理如何使用它们。
{"title":"Descriptive Rules and Normativity","authors":"Adriana Placani","doi":"10.2478/disp-2020-0007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2478/disp-2020-0007","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This work offers a challenge to the orthodox view that descriptive rules are non-normative and passive in their role and usage. It does so by arguing that, although lacking in normativity themselves, descriptive rules can be sources of normativity by way of the normative attitudes that can develop around them. That is, although descriptive rules typically depict how things are, they can also play a role in how things ought to be. In this way, the limited role that this type of rule can play as either a basis for the development of normative reasons, or as explanatory reasons for action is identified and clarified. One desirable outcome of the analysis is a more complete view of what descriptive rules are and how they are utilized by agents.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"40 1","pages":"167 - 180"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74691184","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Revolt Against Expertise: Pseudoscience, Right-Wing Populism, and Post-Truth Politicst 对专家的反抗:伪科学、右翼民粹主义和后真相政治家
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-06-30 DOI: 10.5281/ZENODO.3567166
T. Edis
While concern about public irrationality and antiscientific movements is not new, the increasing power of right-wing populist movements that promote distrust of expertise and of scientific institutions gives such concerns a new context. Experience with classic pseudosciences such as creationism, and the long-running efforts by defenders of science to oppose such pseudosciences, may also help us understand today’s post-truth populism. The politics of creationism and science education in the United States and in Turkey does not, however, suggest easy answers. Moreover, there are important features of politics in liberal democracies that drive a populist backlash, which makes it counterproductive for defenders of science to call for deference to all forms of expertise claimed by professionals. There is a danger that the rhetoric of reason that is used to defend science will become part of a more general apologetics for an unsustainable status quo.
虽然对公众非理性和反科学运动的担忧并不新鲜,但右翼民粹主义运动日益强大,助长了对专业知识和科学机构的不信任,这给这种担忧带来了新的背景。对神创论等经典伪科学的经验,以及科学捍卫者反对此类伪科学的长期努力,也可能有助于我们理解今天的后真相民粹主义。然而,美国和土耳其的神创论政治和科学教育并没有给出简单的答案。此外,自由民主国家的一些重要政治特征会引发民粹主义的反弹,这使得科学捍卫者呼吁尊重专业人士声称的所有形式的专业知识,会适得其反。有一种危险是,用来为科学辩护的理性修辞,将成为对不可持续现状的更普遍辩护的一部分。
{"title":"A Revolt Against Expertise: Pseudoscience, Right-Wing Populism, and Post-Truth Politicst","authors":"T. Edis","doi":"10.5281/ZENODO.3567166","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5281/ZENODO.3567166","url":null,"abstract":"While concern about public irrationality and antiscientific movements is not new, the increasing power of right-wing populist movements that promote distrust of expertise and of scientific institutions gives such concerns a new context. Experience with classic pseudosciences such as creationism, and the long-running efforts by defenders of science to oppose such pseudosciences, may also help us understand today’s post-truth populism. The politics of creationism and science education in the United States and in Turkey does not, however, suggest easy answers. Moreover, there are important features of politics in liberal democracies that drive a populist backlash, which makes it counterproductive for defenders of science to call for deference to all forms of expertise claimed by professionals. There is a danger that the rhetoric of reason that is used to defend science will become part of a more general apologetics for an unsustainable status quo.","PeriodicalId":52369,"journal":{"name":"Disputatio (Spain)","volume":"19 1","pages":"67-95"},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-06-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84748488","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
期刊
Disputatio (Spain)
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1