首页 > 最新文献

Review of Politics最新文献

英文 中文
Reasonable Accommodation: James Madison and Governmental Noncognizance of Religion 合理调解:詹姆斯·麦迪逊与政府对宗教的不承认
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-07-18 DOI: 10.1017/S0034670522000924
Jonathan Ashbach
Abstract Scholars have long contested James Madison's position on religious liberty. Madison believed in governmental noncognizance of religion. The dominant view, voiced by Vincent Muñoz, interprets that to mean that government should take no notice of religion either to target it or to allow religious objectors exemptions from neutral and generally applicable laws. While there is much to commend Muñoz's view, it fails to accurately convey Madison's position. Noncognizance, for Madison, meant not that government should not notice religion, but that it should assume no authority over it. Consequently, Madison believed government should not interfere with religious duties unless to achieve important ends via carefully tailored policies.
长期以来,学者们一直在争论詹姆斯·麦迪逊对宗教自由的立场。麦迪逊主张政府不承认宗教。由Vincent Muñoz提出的主流观点将其解释为,政府不应该关注宗教,或者针对宗教,或者允许宗教反对者免于中立和普遍适用的法律。虽然Muñoz的观点有很多值得赞扬的地方,但它未能准确地传达麦迪逊的立场。对麦迪逊来说,不承认并不意味着政府不应该注意宗教,而是政府不应该对宗教有任何权威。因此,麦迪逊认为政府不应该干涉宗教义务,除非通过精心制定的政策来达到重要目的。
{"title":"Reasonable Accommodation: James Madison and Governmental Noncognizance of Religion","authors":"Jonathan Ashbach","doi":"10.1017/S0034670522000924","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670522000924","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Scholars have long contested James Madison's position on religious liberty. Madison believed in governmental noncognizance of religion. The dominant view, voiced by Vincent Muñoz, interprets that to mean that government should take no notice of religion either to target it or to allow religious objectors exemptions from neutral and generally applicable laws. While there is much to commend Muñoz's view, it fails to accurately convey Madison's position. Noncognizance, for Madison, meant not that government should not notice religion, but that it should assume no authority over it. Consequently, Madison believed government should not interfere with religious duties unless to achieve important ends via carefully tailored policies.","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"327 - 348"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46553914","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reply to Muñoz Reply to Muñoz
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-07-18 DOI: 10.1017/S0034670523000025
Jonathan Ashbach
I am grateful to Vincent Muñoz for his analysis and critique of my argument. It seems to me, however, that the two criticisms offered here fail to connect with the position I advance. Begin with the second and more fundamental point. Muñoz claims my argument is predicated upon redefining the term “jurisdiction” such that “the state’s absence of jurisdiction over subject matter X means the state cannot pass laws that adversely impact X” (351). I am not sure where this definition is coming from, but it is certainly not coming from me. Undoubtedly, governments may pass all manner of laws that negatively impact religion, on Madison’s terms. Madison’s own advocacy of secular state universities, for example, might well have some negative impact on religion by diverting promising candidates from religious institutions. Neither here nor anywhere else in his corpus, to my knowledge, does Madison make adverse impact a test of jurisdiction. What I did say was that government may not rule religious areas of life, either intentionally or unintentionally: “Something stronger than a duty merely to abstain from targeting religion flows naturally from Madison’s claims. Because reserved rights have not been granted to government, for Madison, the more natural implication is not that government may only infringe upon them if it does so unintentionally, but that government may not infringe upon them at all” (339). Government may not require individuals to take or abstain from actions in violation of their right of religious conscience merely out of oversight or because everyone else is required to do the same thing. Yet the legitimacy of such governmental requirements is the acknowledged upshot of Muñoz’s understanding of noncognizance and the Smith decision it supports. Instead, I present evidence that Madison believed government must actively respect the inalienable rights of conscience to the extent feasible. In short, the difference betweenMuñoz and myself is not that I am unfamiliar with his treatment of inalienable rights, as he suggests. As indicated in the passage just quoted, I agree with it and use it to advance my own case. Nor is the issue that we disagree on the meaning of jurisdiction. Muñoz characterizes the true definition well enough: it means that the state “lacks authority
我感谢文森特·穆尼奥斯对我的论点的分析和批评。然而,在我看来,这里提出的两项批评似乎与我提出的立场不符。从第二个更基本的观点开始。穆尼奥斯声称,我的论点是基于对“管辖权”一词的重新定义,即“国家对主题X缺乏管辖权意味着国家不能通过对X产生不利影响的法律”(351)。我不确定这个定义是从哪里来的,但肯定不是从我这里来的。毫无疑问,按照麦迪逊的说法,政府可能会通过各种对宗教产生负面影响的法律。例如,麦迪逊自己对世俗州立大学的倡导,很可能会将有前途的候选人从宗教机构中转移出来,从而对宗教产生一些负面影响。据我所知,无论是在这里还是在他的语料库中的其他任何地方,麦迪逊都没有将不利影响作为对管辖权的测试。我所说的是,政府可能不会统治生活中的宗教领域,无论是有意还是无意:“麦迪逊的主张自然会产生比仅仅放弃针对宗教的义务更强烈的东西。因为保留权利没有授予政府,对麦迪逊来说,更自然的含义不是政府只有在无意的情况下才可能侵犯这些权利,而是政府可能根本不会侵犯这些权利。”(339)。政府不能仅仅出于监督或因为其他人都被要求做同样的事情,就要求个人采取或放弃侵犯其宗教良心权利的行动。然而,这种政府要求的合法性是穆尼奥斯对不承认的理解及其支持的史密斯决定的公认结果。相反,我提供的证据表明,麦迪逊认为政府必须在可行的范围内积极尊重不可剥夺的良心权利。简言之,穆尼奥斯和我之间的区别并不是我不熟悉他对不可剥夺权利的处理,正如他所说的那样。正如刚才引用的这段话所表明的那样,我同意这一点,并用它来推进我自己的观点。我们对管辖权的含义也不存在分歧。穆尼奥斯很好地描述了真正的定义:这意味着国家“缺乏权威”
{"title":"Reply to Muñoz","authors":"Jonathan Ashbach","doi":"10.1017/S0034670523000025","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670523000025","url":null,"abstract":"I am grateful to Vincent Muñoz for his analysis and critique of my argument. It seems to me, however, that the two criticisms offered here fail to connect with the position I advance. Begin with the second and more fundamental point. Muñoz claims my argument is predicated upon redefining the term “jurisdiction” such that “the state’s absence of jurisdiction over subject matter X means the state cannot pass laws that adversely impact X” (351). I am not sure where this definition is coming from, but it is certainly not coming from me. Undoubtedly, governments may pass all manner of laws that negatively impact religion, on Madison’s terms. Madison’s own advocacy of secular state universities, for example, might well have some negative impact on religion by diverting promising candidates from religious institutions. Neither here nor anywhere else in his corpus, to my knowledge, does Madison make adverse impact a test of jurisdiction. What I did say was that government may not rule religious areas of life, either intentionally or unintentionally: “Something stronger than a duty merely to abstain from targeting religion flows naturally from Madison’s claims. Because reserved rights have not been granted to government, for Madison, the more natural implication is not that government may only infringe upon them if it does so unintentionally, but that government may not infringe upon them at all” (339). Government may not require individuals to take or abstain from actions in violation of their right of religious conscience merely out of oversight or because everyone else is required to do the same thing. Yet the legitimacy of such governmental requirements is the acknowledged upshot of Muñoz’s understanding of noncognizance and the Smith decision it supports. Instead, I present evidence that Madison believed government must actively respect the inalienable rights of conscience to the extent feasible. In short, the difference betweenMuñoz and myself is not that I am unfamiliar with his treatment of inalienable rights, as he suggests. As indicated in the passage just quoted, I agree with it and use it to advance my own case. Nor is the issue that we disagree on the meaning of jurisdiction. Muñoz characterizes the true definition well enough: it means that the state “lacks authority","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"352 - 353"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49529552","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Authors’ Response: Liberal Education and the Restless Soul 作者的回应:博雅教育与不安分的灵魂
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-07-18 DOI: 10.1017/S0034670523000086
B. Storey, Jenna Silber Storey
We are grateful to the contributors for exemplifying the kind of conversation we hoped Why We Are Restless would inspire. Each embraces the spirit of the book, taking seriously our effort to clarify the Tocquevillean paradox: that citizens of modern liberal democracies are freer and more prosperous than almost anyone in human history, yet are restlessly discontent in ways that unsettle both our individual lives and our capacity for free and orderly politics. We seek to understand the origin and nature of this discontent through the work of Montaigne, Pascal, Rousseau, and Tocqueville—who are likewise concerned with inquietude. Zuckert, Halikias, Yarbrough, and Callanan assess our scholarly work by the high standard of their own penetrating readings of those authors. Their lucid summaries of and objections to our arguments helped clarify our own thoughts. In particular, they prompted further thought about two important questions: first, what it means to write in public about the questions our authors raise; and second, what contribution liberal education can make to ameliorating the problems we describe. Zuckert seeks to offer a more Montaignean reading of Montaigne than our own. We welcome this approach and appreciate her attention to the detail of Montaigne’s text, consideration of his intentions, and defense of his distinctiveness as a thinker. Her central criticism concerns our contention that the search for “unmediated approbation” is a central theme of Montaigne’s thought. We use this term to describe the core of Montaigne’s distinctive understanding of friendship, patterned on his experience with Étienne de La Boétie. We believe that thinking about friendship so understood can be useful for assessing some distinctive social aspirations of modern people. Although Zuckert acknowledges that friendship was important to Montaigne, she writes that after La Boétie’s death “there is no evidence in the Essays or his biography that he actively sought another such friend” (379). Instead, she claims that Montaigne retired to the solitude of his estate and that it is “such a solitary life that he recommends to his readers” (379). She is further concerned that our characterization of the aim of Montaignean
我们非常感谢这些贡献者,他们为我们所希望的“为什么我们不安分”的对话提供了例证。每个人都拥抱了本书的精神,认真对待我们为澄清托克维尔悖论所做的努力:现代自由民主国家的公民比人类历史上几乎任何一个国家的公民都更自由、更繁荣,但他们的不满情绪却在某种程度上扰乱了我们的个人生活,也扰乱了我们自由有序政治的能力。我们试图通过蒙田、帕斯卡、卢梭和托克维尔的作品来理解这种不满的根源和本质,他们也同样关注不安。扎克特、哈利基亚斯、亚伯勒和卡拉南通过他们自己对这些作者的深入阅读的高标准来评估我们的学术工作。他们对我们论点的清晰总结和反驳有助于理清我们自己的思路。特别是,它们促使人们进一步思考两个重要的问题:第一,在公开场合写下作者提出的问题意味着什么;第二,通识教育对改善我们所描述的问题有何贡献。扎克特试图提供一种比我们自己的蒙田更蒙田式的解读。我们欢迎这种方法,并感谢她对蒙田文本细节的关注,对他的意图的思考,以及对他作为思想家的独特性的辩护。她的核心批评与我们的论点有关,即寻求“未经调解的认可”是蒙田思想的中心主题。我们用这个词来描述蒙田对友谊的独特理解的核心,这是他在Étienne de La bosamtie的经历的模式。我们相信,这样理解友谊对于评估现代人的一些独特的社会愿望是有用的。尽管扎克特承认友谊对蒙田来说很重要,但她写道,在La bosamtie死后,“在《随笔》或他的传记中没有证据表明他积极寻找另一个这样的朋友”(379)。相反,她声称蒙田隐居在他的庄园里,“他向他的读者推荐的是这样一种孤独的生活”(379)。她进一步关注我们对蒙台安的目标的刻画
{"title":"Authors’ Response: Liberal Education and the Restless Soul","authors":"B. Storey, Jenna Silber Storey","doi":"10.1017/S0034670523000086","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670523000086","url":null,"abstract":"We are grateful to the contributors for exemplifying the kind of conversation we hoped Why We Are Restless would inspire. Each embraces the spirit of the book, taking seriously our effort to clarify the Tocquevillean paradox: that citizens of modern liberal democracies are freer and more prosperous than almost anyone in human history, yet are restlessly discontent in ways that unsettle both our individual lives and our capacity for free and orderly politics. We seek to understand the origin and nature of this discontent through the work of Montaigne, Pascal, Rousseau, and Tocqueville—who are likewise concerned with inquietude. Zuckert, Halikias, Yarbrough, and Callanan assess our scholarly work by the high standard of their own penetrating readings of those authors. Their lucid summaries of and objections to our arguments helped clarify our own thoughts. In particular, they prompted further thought about two important questions: first, what it means to write in public about the questions our authors raise; and second, what contribution liberal education can make to ameliorating the problems we describe. Zuckert seeks to offer a more Montaignean reading of Montaigne than our own. We welcome this approach and appreciate her attention to the detail of Montaigne’s text, consideration of his intentions, and defense of his distinctiveness as a thinker. Her central criticism concerns our contention that the search for “unmediated approbation” is a central theme of Montaigne’s thought. We use this term to describe the core of Montaigne’s distinctive understanding of friendship, patterned on his experience with Étienne de La Boétie. We believe that thinking about friendship so understood can be useful for assessing some distinctive social aspirations of modern people. Although Zuckert acknowledges that friendship was important to Montaigne, she writes that after La Boétie’s death “there is no evidence in the Essays or his biography that he actively sought another such friend” (379). Instead, she claims that Montaigne retired to the solitude of his estate and that it is “such a solitary life that he recommends to his readers” (379). She is further concerned that our characterization of the aim of Montaignean","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"394 - 403"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44318343","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Response to Jonathan Ashbach 对Jonathan Ashbach的回应
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-07-18 DOI: 10.1017/S0034670523000013
V. P. Muñoz
It is satisfying to have one’s work taken seriously by the next generation of scholars. I was pleased to learn in Jonathan Ashbach’s article that I advance “both the most persuasive and the dominant articulation of Madison’s beliefs about religious free exercise in the literature” (329). I was less pleased to read that my interpretation is “mistaken,” “in need of revision,” and “fail[s] to appreciate the implications of social contract theory” (330). Upon review, however, I think my work survives his criticism. I believe that Ashbach makes two errors, which leads him to both misinterpret my scholarship and misunderstand Madison. The issue between us is the proper understanding of Madison’s principle of religious freedom. We focus on the same evidence—primarily, Madison’s “Memorial and Remonstrance”—and read Madison in the same way, as a natural rights, social compact political thinker. We disagree, however, about what Madison’s fundamental principle is. Starting with a 2003 article, further developed in my first book and a subsequent article, I have advanced a “noncognizance” interpretation, contending that Madison held that the state must remain “blind” to religion and thus cannot classify individuals on account of their religious affiliation for purposes of privilege or penalty. Ashbach finds this mistaken because, he
一个人的作品被下一代学者认真对待是令人满意的。我很高兴地从乔纳森·阿什巴赫的文章中了解到,我“在文学作品中提出了麦迪逊关于宗教自由信仰的最具说服力和最主要的表述”(329)。我不太高兴地读到我的解释是“错误的”、“需要修改”和“未能理解社会契约理论的含义”(330)。然而,经过回顾,我认为我的作品经受住了他的批评。我认为阿什巴赫犯了两个错误,这导致他既误解了我的学术,也误解了麦迪逊。我们之间的问题是如何正确理解麦迪逊的宗教自由原则。我们关注同样的证据——主要是麦迪逊的《纪念与劝谏》——并以同样的方式解读麦迪逊,把他视为一个自然权利、社会契约的政治思想家。然而,对于麦迪逊的基本原则是什么,我们意见不一。从2003年的一篇文章开始,在我的第一本书和随后的一篇文章中进一步发展,我提出了一种“不承认”的解释,认为麦迪逊认为国家必须对宗教保持“盲目”,因此不能因为个人的宗教信仰而对其进行分类,以获得特权或惩罚。阿什巴赫发现这是错误的,因为他
{"title":"Response to Jonathan Ashbach","authors":"V. P. Muñoz","doi":"10.1017/S0034670523000013","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670523000013","url":null,"abstract":"It is satisfying to have one’s work taken seriously by the next generation of scholars. I was pleased to learn in Jonathan Ashbach’s article that I advance “both the most persuasive and the dominant articulation of Madison’s beliefs about religious free exercise in the literature” (329). I was less pleased to read that my interpretation is “mistaken,” “in need of revision,” and “fail[s] to appreciate the implications of social contract theory” (330). Upon review, however, I think my work survives his criticism. I believe that Ashbach makes two errors, which leads him to both misinterpret my scholarship and misunderstand Madison. The issue between us is the proper understanding of Madison’s principle of religious freedom. We focus on the same evidence—primarily, Madison’s “Memorial and Remonstrance”—and read Madison in the same way, as a natural rights, social compact political thinker. We disagree, however, about what Madison’s fundamental principle is. Starting with a 2003 article, further developed in my first book and a subsequent article, I have advanced a “noncognizance” interpretation, contending that Madison held that the state must remain “blind” to religion and thus cannot classify individuals on account of their religious affiliation for purposes of privilege or penalty. Ashbach finds this mistaken because, he","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"349 - 351"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46536520","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Gary M. Kelly: The Human Condition in Rousseau's “Essay on the Origin of Languages.” (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 2021. Pp. xviii, 242.) 加里·m·凯利:卢梭《论语言的起源》中的人类状况。(刘易斯顿,纽约:埃德温·梅伦,2021年)。第18页,242页。)
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-06-29 DOI: 10.1017/s003467052300013x
Peter Westmoreland
{"title":"Gary M. Kelly: The Human Condition in Rousseau's “Essay on the Origin of Languages.” (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 2021. Pp. xviii, 242.)","authors":"Peter Westmoreland","doi":"10.1017/s003467052300013x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/s003467052300013x","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"439 - 441"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43806690","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Richard Shorten: The Ideology of Political Reactionaries. (New York: Routledge, 2022. Pp. xiii, 270.) 理查德·肖顿:《政治反动派的意识形态》。(纽约:劳特利奇,2022年。第xiii页,270。)
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-06-14 DOI: 10.1017/S0034670523000116
Robert Goodman
{"title":"Richard Shorten: The Ideology of Political Reactionaries. (New York: Routledge, 2022. Pp. xiii, 270.)","authors":"Robert Goodman","doi":"10.1017/S0034670523000116","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670523000116","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"429 - 431"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47761632","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
David Dyzenhaus: The Long Arc of Legality: Hobbes, Kelsen, Hart. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2022. Pp. xiv, 443.) 大卫·戴赞豪斯:《法律的长弧》:霍布斯,凯尔森,哈特。(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2022。第14页,443页。)
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-06-13 DOI: 10.1017/s0034670523000219
M. Rovira
{"title":"David Dyzenhaus: The Long Arc of Legality: Hobbes, Kelsen, Hart. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2022. Pp. xiv, 443.)","authors":"M. Rovira","doi":"10.1017/s0034670523000219","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/s0034670523000219","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"426 - 429"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44219552","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Bare Life, Facticity, and Biopolitics in Agamben and the Early Heidegger 阿甘本与早期海德格尔的赤裸生命、事实性与生命政治
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-06-13 DOI: 10.1017/S0034670523000098
A. Cimino
Abstract The first book of Agamben's Homo Sacer series contains very few references to Heidegger. Even so, the pages that Agamben devotes to Heidegger in the third part of the book are far from a digression. They touch on a number of crucial topics that are vital to both Heidegger and Agamben, such as the relationship between philosophy and politics, the specific philosophical motivations behind Heidegger's political commitment, and life as a central philosophical theme. This article evaluates Agamben's interpretation of Heidegger in those pages by concentrating on two interrelated questions: (1) whether and to what extent Agamben's biopolitical reading of Heidegger is plausible and persuasive, and (2) how to judge the relationship between their respective accounts of life, which center around the two seminal concepts of “bare life” and “facticity.”
阿甘本的《神圣的人》系列的第一部很少提及海德格尔。即便如此,阿甘本在书的第三部分中对海德格尔的论述远远没有离题。他们触及了许多对海德格尔和阿甘本都至关重要的关键话题,比如哲学与政治之间的关系,海德格尔政治承诺背后的具体哲学动机,以及作为中心哲学主题的生命。本文通过关注两个相互关联的问题来评价阿甘本对海德格尔的解释:(1)阿甘本对海德格尔的生命政治解读是否可信,以及在多大程度上可信和有说服力,以及(2)如何判断他们各自对生活的描述之间的关系,这两个描述围绕着“赤裸裸的生活”和“真实性”这两个开创性的概念。
{"title":"Bare Life, Facticity, and Biopolitics in Agamben and the Early Heidegger","authors":"A. Cimino","doi":"10.1017/S0034670523000098","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670523000098","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The first book of Agamben's Homo Sacer series contains very few references to Heidegger. Even so, the pages that Agamben devotes to Heidegger in the third part of the book are far from a digression. They touch on a number of crucial topics that are vital to both Heidegger and Agamben, such as the relationship between philosophy and politics, the specific philosophical motivations behind Heidegger's political commitment, and life as a central philosophical theme. This article evaluates Agamben's interpretation of Heidegger in those pages by concentrating on two interrelated questions: (1) whether and to what extent Agamben's biopolitical reading of Heidegger is plausible and persuasive, and (2) how to judge the relationship between their respective accounts of life, which center around the two seminal concepts of “bare life” and “facticity.”","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"354 - 374"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45735887","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Areti Giannopoulou: Political Friendship and Degrowth: An Ethical Grounding of an Economy of Human Flourishing. (London: Routledge, 2022. Pp. xi, 168.) 阿雷蒂·詹诺普洛:《政治友谊与堕落:人类繁荣经济的伦理基础》。(伦敦:劳特利奇,2022年。xi页,168。)
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-06-06 DOI: 10.1017/S0034670523000128
P. Digeser
{"title":"Areti Giannopoulou: Political Friendship and Degrowth: An Ethical Grounding of an Economy of Human Flourishing. (London: Routledge, 2022. Pp. xi, 168.)","authors":"P. Digeser","doi":"10.1017/S0034670523000128","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670523000128","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"421 - 423"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44453576","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Paul Sagar: Adam Smith Reconsidered: History, Liberty, and the Foundations of Modern Politics. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2021. Pp. xii, 229.) 保罗·萨加尔:《重新思考亚当·斯密:历史、自由和现代政治的基础》普林斯顿:普林斯顿大学出版社,2021年。第12页,229页。)
Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-06-05 DOI: 10.1017/S0034670523000141
Philip D. Bunn
{"title":"Paul Sagar: Adam Smith Reconsidered: History, Liberty, and the Foundations of Modern Politics. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2021. Pp. xii, 229.)","authors":"Philip D. Bunn","doi":"10.1017/S0034670523000141","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034670523000141","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":52549,"journal":{"name":"Review of Politics","volume":"85 1","pages":"419 - 421"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46094511","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Review of Politics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1