首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania最新文献

英文 中文
Alchemy and the Transformation of Matter in Richard Crashaw’s Poetry (1612-1649) 理查德·克拉肖诗歌中的炼金术与物质转化(1612-1649)
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems202110214
Fabrice Schultz
This paper studies the English poems of Richard Crashaw (1612-1649) from a historicist and formalist perspective. It specifically considers Crashaw’s poetry in its religious but also intellectual and early scien­tific context to investigate the frequently overlooked influence of science on his poetry. Metaphors drawn from alchemy and particularly from the trans­formation of matter to achieve its purification and spiritualisation enrich the poet’s expression of mystical devotion to underline that access to the spiritual as well as mystical union with Christ are deeply rooted in the devotee’s body. Representations of the earth as a chemical laboratory focus on materiality and corporality to emphasise the constant movement animating matter. A form of spiritual alchemy underscores Crashaw’s Christocentrism and references to the metamorphoses of matter consistently aim to express mystical union. A meta-poetic analysis eventually highlights a significant analogy between reading and alchemical processes in order to demonstrate the anagogical aim of Crashaw’s verse and the way his poems work on his reader’s heart to lift his soul. References to liquefaction, distillation or sublimation echo the published works of mystics but alchemical conceits based on symbolically evocative topoï and polysemic vocabulary reinforce the importance of the corporal in the expe­rience of mystical union.
本文从历史主义和形式主义的角度对理查德·克拉肖(1612-1649)的英语诗歌进行了研究。它特别考虑了克拉肖诗歌的宗教背景,也考虑了知识分子和早期科学背景,以调查科学对他的诗歌经常被忽视的影响。来自炼金术的隐喻,特别是来自物质的转化,以实现其净化和灵性化,丰富了诗人对神秘奉献的表达,强调了通往精神的途径以及与基督的神秘结合深深植根于奉献者的身体。地球作为一个化学实验室的表现侧重于物质性和形体性,以强调不断运动的动画物质。一种精神炼金术的形式强调了克拉肖的基督中心主义,并引用了物质的变形,始终旨在表达神秘的结合。元诗歌分析最终突出了阅读和炼金术过程之间的重要类比,以证明克拉什肖诗歌的神秘目的,以及他的诗歌如何影响读者的心灵,提升他的灵魂。提到液化,蒸馏或升华与已出版的神秘主义作品相呼应,但炼金术的幻想基于象征性唤起topoï和多义词汇,强化了肉体在神秘结合体验中的重要性。
{"title":"Alchemy and the Transformation of Matter in Richard Crashaw’s Poetry (1612-1649)","authors":"Fabrice Schultz","doi":"10.5840/jems202110214","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems202110214","url":null,"abstract":"This paper studies the English poems of Richard Crashaw (1612-1649) from a historicist and formalist perspective. It specifically considers Crashaw’s poetry in its religious but also intellectual and early scien­tific context to investigate the frequently overlooked influence of science on his poetry. Metaphors drawn from alchemy and particularly from the trans­formation of matter to achieve its purification and spiritualisation enrich the poet’s expression of mystical devotion to underline that access to the spiritual as well as mystical union with Christ are deeply rooted in the devotee’s body. Representations of the earth as a chemical laboratory focus on materiality and corporality to emphasise the constant movement animating matter. A form of spiritual alchemy underscores Crashaw’s Christocentrism and references to the metamorphoses of matter consistently aim to express mystical union. A meta-poetic analysis eventually highlights a significant analogy between reading and alchemical processes in order to demonstrate the anagogical aim of Crashaw’s verse and the way his poems work on his reader’s heart to lift his soul. References to liquefaction, distillation or sublimation echo the published works of mystics but alchemical conceits based on symbolically evocative topoï and polysemic vocabulary reinforce the importance of the corporal in the expe­rience of mystical union.","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264465","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reasons for the Method in Descartes’ Discours 笛卡尔话语中方法的原因
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20211011
Patrick Brissey
In the practical philosophy of the Discours de la Méthode, before the theoretical metaphysics of Part Four and the Meditationes, Descartes gives us an inductive argument that his method, the procedure and cognitive psychology, is veracious at its inception. His evidence, akin to his Scholastic predecessors, is God, a maximally perfect being, established an ontological foundation for knowledge such that reason and nature are isomorphic. Further, the method, he tells us, is a functional definition of human reason; that is, like other rationalists during this period, he holds the structure of reason maps onto the world. The evidence for this thesis is given in what I call the groundwork to Descartes’ philosophical system, essentially the first half of the Discours, where, through a series of examples in the preamble of Part Two, he, step-by-step, ascends from the perfection of artifacts through the imposition of reason (the Architect Example) to the perfection of a constituent’s use of her cognitive faculties (the Wise-Lawgiver Example), to God perfecting and ordering reality (the Divine Artificer Example). Finally, he descends, establishing the structure of human reason, which undergirds and entails the procedure of the method (the Laws of Sparta Example).
在第四部分的理论形而上学和《沉思录》之前,笛卡尔在实践哲学的《discourse de la m thode》中给出了一个归纳论证,即他的方法、过程和认知心理学从一开始就是正确的。他的证据,类似于他的学术前辈,是上帝,一个最大限度的完美的存在,建立了知识的本体论基础,使理性和自然是同构的。此外,他告诉我们,方法是人类理性的功能性定义;也就是说,像这一时期的其他理性主义者一样,他认为理性的结构映射到了世界上。这个论点的证据是在我所说的笛卡尔哲学体系的基础中给出的,基本上是在《论》的前半部分,在第二部分的序言中,通过一系列的例子,他一步一步地,从通过强加理性的工件的完美(建筑师的例子)上升到成员使用她的认知能力的完美(明智的立法者的例子),再到上帝完善和安排现实(神圣的工匠的例子)。最后,他下降,建立了人类理性的结构,它巩固并包含了方法的程序(斯巴达法例)。
{"title":"Reasons for the Method in Descartes’ Discours","authors":"Patrick Brissey","doi":"10.5840/jems20211011","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20211011","url":null,"abstract":"In the practical philosophy of the Discours de la Méthode, before the theoretical metaphysics of Part Four and the Meditationes, Descartes gives us an inductive argument that his method, the procedure and cognitive psychology, is veracious at its inception. His evidence, akin to his Scholastic predecessors, is God, a maximally perfect being, established an ontological foundation for knowledge such that reason and nature are isomorphic. Further, the method, he tells us, is a functional definition of human reason; that is, like other rationalists during this period, he holds the structure of reason maps onto the world. The evidence for this thesis is given in what I call the groundwork to Descartes’ philosophical system, essentially the first half of the Discours, where, through a series of examples in the preamble of Part Two, he, step-by-step, ascends from the perfection of artifacts through the imposition of reason (the Architect Example) to the perfection of a constituent’s use of her cognitive faculties (the Wise-Lawgiver Example), to God perfecting and ordering reality (the Divine Artificer Example). Finally, he descends, establishing the structure of human reason, which undergirds and entails the procedure of the method (the Laws of Sparta Example).","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264344","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The ‘Necessity’ of Leibniz’s Rejection of Necessitarianism 莱布尼茨对必然性主义的否定的“必然性”
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20211014
J. Anderson
In the Theodicy, Leibniz argues against two impious conceptions of God—a God who makes arbitrary choices and a God who doesn’t make choices at all. Many interpret Leibniz as navigating these dangers by positing a kind of non-Spinozistic necessitarianism. I examine passages from the Theodicy which reject not only blind (Spinozistic) necessitarianism but necessitarianism altogether. Leibniz thinks blind necessitarianism is dangerous due to the conception of God it entails and the implications for morality. Non-Spinozistic necessitarianism avoids many of these criticisms. Leibniz finds that even necessary actions should receive certain rewards and punishments as long as they necessarily lead to a change in future behavior. But Leibniz rejects even non-Spinozistic necessitarianism on the grounds that it is inconsistent with punitive justice. Whether Leibniz successfully avoids necessitarianism, it ought to be clear that he sees his own position as significantly distinct from necessitarianism and not just Spinozism.
在《神正论》中,莱布尼茨反对两种不虔诚的上帝观念——一个做出任意选择的上帝和一个根本不做选择的上帝。许多人认为莱布尼茨通过提出一种非斯宾诺莎式的必然主义来引导这些危险。我考察了《神正论》中的段落,这些段落不仅拒绝盲目的(斯宾诺莎式的)必要主义,而且完全拒绝必要主义。莱布尼茨认为盲目的必要主义是危险的,因为它包含了上帝的概念和道德的含义。非斯宾诺莎主义的必然主义避免了许多这样的批评。莱布尼茨发现,即使是必要的行为,只要它们必然导致未来行为的改变,也应该受到一定的奖励和惩罚。但莱布尼茨甚至拒绝非斯宾诺莎主义的必然主义,理由是它与惩罚性正义不一致。无论莱布尼茨是否成功地避免了必要主义,应该清楚的是,他认为自己的立场与必要主义截然不同,而不仅仅是斯宾诺莎主义。
{"title":"The ‘Necessity’ of Leibniz’s Rejection of Necessitarianism","authors":"J. Anderson","doi":"10.5840/jems20211014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20211014","url":null,"abstract":"In the Theodicy, Leibniz argues against two impious conceptions of God—a God who makes arbitrary choices and a God who doesn’t make choices at all. Many interpret Leibniz as navigating these dangers by positing a kind of non-Spinozistic necessitarianism. I examine passages from the Theodicy which reject not only blind (Spinozistic) necessitarianism but necessitarianism altogether. Leibniz thinks blind necessitarianism is dangerous due to the conception of God it entails and the implications for morality. Non-Spinozistic necessitarianism avoids many of these criticisms. Leibniz finds that even necessary actions should receive certain rewards and punishments as long as they necessarily lead to a change in future behavior. But Leibniz rejects even non-Spinozistic necessitarianism on the grounds that it is inconsistent with punitive justice. Whether Leibniz successfully avoids necessitarianism, it ought to be clear that he sees his own position as significantly distinct from necessitarianism and not just Spinozism.","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264410","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Conservatism of the Counterreformation in Montaigne’s “Apology for Raymond Sebond” 蒙田《为雷蒙德·塞邦德道歉》中反宗教改革的保守主义
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems202110212
Kyle S. Hodge
Montaigne’s “Apology” is a lengthy work the overarching theme of which is the relationship between epistemology, virtue, and vice. It is a commentary on the thesis that science or knowledge “is the mother of all virtue and that all vice is produced by ignorance.” Montaigne’s response is radical and unequivocal: there is no idea more harmful; its consequences are no less than the destruction of inward contentment and the undermining of societal peace and stability. Indeed, Montaigne sees the Protestant Reformation as the instantiation of this terrible thesis, with all of the attendant trouble it had and continued to cause in France. So Montaigne inverts the thesis: ignorance begets virtue and (presumption of ) knowledge vice. Out of this inversion he draws many conservative social and political consequences, and this is one of the most interesting and yet underexplored aspects of the text. Montaigne exhibits the conservatism of the Counterreformation in the “Apology,” and I intend to draw more attention to this theme. I show that Montaigne’s main target in the “Apology” was not dogmatism as such, but Protestantism as a species of dogmatism. I then show that, by using a few elementary epistemic concepts, Montaigne launches a withering skeptical attack on the Reformation. Out of this criticism I draw some important conservative themes that have significant implications for our understanding of Montaigne’s social and political thought, as well as for conservative political theory and its intellectual history.
蒙田的《道歉》是一部很长的作品,其主要主题是认识论,美德和罪恶之间的关系。它是对科学或知识“是一切美德之母,一切罪恶都是无知产生的”这一论点的评论。蒙田的回应是激进而明确的:没有比这更有害的想法了;其后果不亚于破坏内心的满足和破坏社会的和平与稳定。事实上,蒙田认为新教改革就是这个可怕论点的实例,伴随着它在法国造成的所有麻烦。所以蒙田颠倒了这个命题:无知产生美德,知识(假定)产生罪恶。从这种倒置中,他得出了许多保守的社会和政治后果,这是文本中最有趣但尚未被充分探索的方面之一。蒙田在《忏悔者》中展示了反宗教改革的保守主义,我想让人们更多地关注这个主题。我指出蒙田在《道歉》中的主要目标不是教条主义本身,而是作为教条主义一种的新教。然后我展示了,通过使用一些基本的认识论概念,蒙田对宗教改革发起了一场毁灭性的怀疑论攻击。从这些批评中,我得出了一些重要的保守主义主题,这些主题对我们理解蒙田的社会和政治思想,以及保守主义政治理论及其思想史具有重要意义。
{"title":"The Conservatism of the Counterreformation in Montaigne’s “Apology for Raymond Sebond”","authors":"Kyle S. Hodge","doi":"10.5840/jems202110212","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems202110212","url":null,"abstract":"Montaigne’s “Apology” is a lengthy work the overarching theme of which is the relationship between epistemology, virtue, and vice. It is a commentary on the thesis that science or knowledge “is the mother of all virtue and that all vice is produced by ignorance.” Montaigne’s response is radical and unequivocal: there is no idea more harmful; its consequences are no less than the destruction of inward contentment and the undermining of societal peace and stability. Indeed, Montaigne sees the Protestant Reformation as the instantiation of this terrible thesis, with all of the attendant trouble it had and continued to cause in France. So Montaigne inverts the thesis: ignorance begets virtue and (presumption of ) knowledge vice. Out of this inversion he draws many conservative social and political consequences, and this is one of the most interesting and yet underexplored aspects of the text. Montaigne exhibits the conservatism of the Counterreformation in the “Apology,” and I intend to draw more attention to this theme. I show that Montaigne’s main target in the “Apology” was not dogmatism as such, but Protestantism as a species of dogmatism. I then show that, by using a few elementary epistemic concepts, Montaigne launches a withering skeptical attack on the Reformation. Out of this criticism I draw some important conservative themes that have significant implications for our understanding of Montaigne’s social and political thought, as well as for conservative political theory and its intellectual history.","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264376","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Swedenborg’s Religious Rationalism 斯威登堡的宗教理性主义
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems202110215
Hasse Hämäläinen
This article argues that contrary to a received interpretation, Emanuel Swedenborg’s doctrine of correspondences (scientia correspondentiarum), according to which each empirical reality has a corresponding spiritual reality, is closer to Spinozistic monism than Neoplatonic idealism. According to the former, there is only one substance: God, which we can cognize through its spir­itual and material aspects. According to the latter, the material world consists of substances that receive their form through participation in the ideas of the spiri­tual world. The article will show that although some of Swedenborg’s claims can appear as expressing Neoplatonic idealism, his reading of the Bible as a guide for moral improvement, his rejection of the religious mysteries that cannot be rationally understood, his various examples of correspondences, his view that we can cognize God by studying the correspondences, and his definition of God as the only substance, make evident that he does not consider the spiritual realities ideas in the Neoplatonic sense. The article will interpret Swedenborg to think that the spiritual realities are learned concepts that enable us to describe and experience the world as having spiritual significance and thus acquire a fuller cognition of God.
本文认为,与公认的解释相反,伊曼纽尔·斯威登堡的对应学说(scientia correspondenarum)认为,每个经验现实都有相应的精神现实,这更接近于斯宾诺莎的一元论,而不是新柏拉图主义的唯心主义。根据前者,只有一个实体:上帝,我们可以通过其精神和物质方面认识。根据后者,物质世界由物质组成,这些物质通过参与精神世界的观念而获得其形式。文章将显示,尽管Swedenborg的一些声称可以表现为表达新柏拉图主义理想主义,他的阅读圣经作为道德的指导改善,他拒绝宗教神秘无法理性地理解,他的各种通讯的例子,他的观点,我们可以通过研究通讯,认知上帝和他的上帝是唯一的物质的定义,显然,他并不认为新柏拉图主义意义上的精神现实的想法。本文将斯威登堡解释为认为精神现实是一种习得的概念,它使我们能够描述和体验具有精神意义的世界,从而获得对上帝的更全面的认识。
{"title":"Swedenborg’s Religious Rationalism","authors":"Hasse Hämäläinen","doi":"10.5840/jems202110215","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems202110215","url":null,"abstract":"This article argues that contrary to a received interpretation, Emanuel Swedenborg’s doctrine of correspondences (scientia correspondentiarum), according to which each empirical reality has a corresponding spiritual reality, is closer to Spinozistic monism than Neoplatonic idealism. According to the former, there is only one substance: God, which we can cognize through its spir­itual and material aspects. According to the latter, the material world consists of substances that receive their form through participation in the ideas of the spiri­tual world. The article will show that although some of Swedenborg’s claims can appear as expressing Neoplatonic idealism, his reading of the Bible as a guide for moral improvement, his rejection of the religious mysteries that cannot be rationally understood, his various examples of correspondences, his view that we can cognize God by studying the correspondences, and his definition of God as the only substance, make evident that he does not consider the spiritual realities ideas in the Neoplatonic sense. The article will interpret Swedenborg to think that the spiritual realities are learned concepts that enable us to describe and experience the world as having spiritual significance and thus acquire a fuller cognition of God.","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264487","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Religion, Medicine, Politics, and Practice 宗教、医学、政治和实践
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems202110217
B. Goldberg
{"title":"Religion, Medicine, Politics, and Practice","authors":"B. Goldberg","doi":"10.5840/jems202110217","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems202110217","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264159","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ruth Boeker, Locke on Persons and Personal Identity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021 露丝·勃克尔,《洛克论人与人格同一性》,牛津:牛津大学出版社,2021年
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20211017
Diego Lucci
{"title":"Ruth Boeker, Locke on Persons and Personal Identity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021","authors":"Diego Lucci","doi":"10.5840/jems20211017","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20211017","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264195","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Jennifer M. Rampling, The Experimental Fire. Inventing English Alchemy, 1300-1700, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2020 詹妮弗·m·兰普林,《实验之火》《发明英国炼金术,1300-1700年》,芝加哥和伦敦:芝加哥大学出版社,2020年
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20211019
Doina‐Cristina Rusu
{"title":"Jennifer M. Rampling, The Experimental Fire. Inventing English Alchemy, 1300-1700, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2020","authors":"Doina‐Cristina Rusu","doi":"10.5840/jems20211019","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20211019","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264316","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Brian C. Ribeiro, Sextus, Montaigne, Hume: Pyrrhonizers Brian C.Ribeiro,Sextus,Montaigne,Hume:金字塔化者
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems202110218
A. Matytsin
{"title":"Brian C. Ribeiro, Sextus, Montaigne, Hume: Pyrrhonizers","authors":"A. Matytsin","doi":"10.5840/jems202110218","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems202110218","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264793","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Expanding the Corpus of Early Modern Natural Philosophy 扩充早期现代自然哲学的语料库
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20211016
Andrea Sangiacomo, Raluca A. Tanasescu, S. Donker, Hugo Hogenbirk
{"title":"Expanding the Corpus of Early Modern Natural Philosophy","authors":"Andrea Sangiacomo, Raluca A. Tanasescu, S. Donker, Hugo Hogenbirk","doi":"10.5840/jems20211016","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20211016","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"13 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71264059","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1