首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania最新文献

英文 中文
“Deus vult aliquas esse certas notitias…” “这是一个确定的通知…”
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems2019812
Günter Frank
The theory of notitiae naturales or κοιναὶ ἔννοιαι was part of the ancient Stoic epistemology. It served as precondition of any knowledge. Within the framework of the humanist rediscovery of ancient sources this theory became an important aspect of Philipp Melanchthon’s theological anthropology. This paper examines the polyvalent perspectives of the theory of notitiae naturales in Melanchthon’s philosophy and the role it played among Lutheran and Calvinist scholars, particularly regarding Rom 1: 19, where Paul stated some kind of a natural knowledge of God. The idea of notitiae communes or “common notions” as an a priori precondition of knowledge was widely spread both on the continent and in England in early modernity. It came to an end by John Locke’s critique in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding.
οινα νοιαι是古代斯多葛派认识论的一部分。它是任何知识的前提。在人本主义对古代资料重新发现的框架下,这一理论成为菲利普·梅兰希顿神学人类学的一个重要方面。本文考察了梅兰希顿哲学中自然意识理论的多重视角,以及它在路德宗和加尔文主义学者中所扮演的角色,特别是关于罗马书1章19节,保罗在那里陈述了对上帝的某种自然认识。在近代早期,作为知识的先验前提条件,“共同的公社”或“共同的观念”的观念在欧洲大陆和英国广泛传播。它以约翰·洛克在《论人类理解》中的批判而告终。
{"title":"“Deus vult aliquas esse certas notitias…”","authors":"Günter Frank","doi":"10.5840/jems2019812","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems2019812","url":null,"abstract":"The theory of notitiae naturales or κοιναὶ ἔννοιαι was part of the ancient Stoic epistemology. It served as precondition of any knowledge. Within the framework of the humanist rediscovery of ancient sources this theory became an important aspect of Philipp Melanchthon’s theological anthropology. This paper examines the polyvalent perspectives of the theory of notitiae naturales in Melanchthon’s philosophy and the role it played among Lutheran and Calvinist scholars, particularly regarding Rom 1: 19, where Paul stated some kind of a natural knowledge of God. The idea of notitiae communes or “common notions” as an a priori precondition of knowledge was widely spread both on the continent and in England in early modernity. It came to an end by John Locke’s critique in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding.","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71263086","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Foreigners in Pre-Modernity 前现代性中的外国人
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20198214
Peter Strohschneider
The essay draws on the concept of ‘asymmetric counter-concepts’ as developed by Reinhart Koselleck starting with twin-formulas such as ‘the familiar and the unfamiliar’ which are generally used to establish collective des­ignations of the self and others and which institutionalize the axiological and the epistemological. These counter-concepts can have different semantic temperatures. The focus is on the underlying meaning-production schemes which produce value-asymmetries. The essay tries to show that a process of heating up these value-asymmetries is only one side of the history of such asymmetric counter-concepts from medieval to modern times. Simultaneously a cooling down can be observed in written texts from different periods; examples include the 12th century Rolandslied and the 16th century Essais of Michel de Montaigne. Full negation eliminates uncertainties and value insecurities. But the complexities and contingencies that emerge since Early Modern times then lead to losses of negatability (Negierbarkeitsverluste), which in turn render gains in unfamiliarity. The modern experience of the foreign is indeterminate otherness instead of determined negation that characterized pre-modern alterity. Modern societies therefore need to mediate between validity and contingency under the circumstances of plurality. Interpretational demands and uncertainty about the relevant interpretive frames increase. Foreignness is then experienced as unfamiliarity. This presupposes intellectual attitudes like irritability, curiosity, and willingness to learn. The modern concept of ‘culture’ then is proposed as a comparative pattern where only unavoidable structural asymmetry remains. It explains cultural differences and the experience of foreignness through heterogeneity. Using this specifically modern pattern, there is no longer a legitimate value slope between one’s own position and its negation. The distinction is then between the familiar and the unfamiliar.
本文借鉴了莱因哈特·科塞莱克(Reinhart Koselleck)提出的“不对称反概念”概念,从“熟悉和不熟悉”等双公式开始,这些公式通常用于建立自我和他人的集体命名,并将价值论和认识论制度化。这些反概念可以有不同的语义温度。重点是产生价值不对称的潜在意义生产方案。本文试图表明,这些价值不对称的升温过程只是从中世纪到现代这种不对称反概念历史的一面。同时,在不同时期的书面文本中可以观察到一种冷却;例如12世纪的罗兰德斯利德和16世纪的蒙田随笔。完全否定消除了不确定性和价值不安全感。但是,自近代早期以来出现的复杂性和偶然性导致了可否定性的丧失(Negierbarkeitsverluste),这反过来又带来了不熟悉的收益。外族的现代经验是不确定的他者性,而不是前现代替代性的确定否定性。因此,现代社会需要在多元环境下的有效性和偶然性之间进行调解。对相关解释框架的解释需求和不确定性增加。在这种情况下,外来的体验就是不熟悉。这预设了智力态度,如易怒、好奇和愿意学习。因此,“文化”的现代概念被提出作为一种比较模式,其中只有不可避免的结构不对称仍然存在。它通过异质性来解释文化差异和异域体验。使用这种特殊的现代模式,在一个人自己的立场和它的否定之间不再有合法的价值斜率。于是,熟悉和不熟悉就有了区别。
{"title":"Foreigners in Pre-Modernity","authors":"Peter Strohschneider","doi":"10.5840/jems20198214","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20198214","url":null,"abstract":"The essay draws on the concept of ‘asymmetric counter-concepts’ as developed by Reinhart Koselleck starting with twin-formulas such as ‘the familiar and the unfamiliar’ which are generally used to establish collective des­ignations of the self and others and which institutionalize the axiological and the epistemological. These counter-concepts can have different semantic temperatures. The focus is on the underlying meaning-production schemes which produce value-asymmetries. The essay tries to show that a process of heating up these value-asymmetries is only one side of the history of such asymmetric counter-concepts from medieval to modern times. Simultaneously a cooling down can be observed in written texts from different periods; examples include the 12th century Rolandslied and the 16th century Essais of Michel de Montaigne. Full negation eliminates uncertainties and value insecurities. But the complexities and contingencies that emerge since Early Modern times then lead to losses of negatability (Negierbarkeitsverluste), which in turn render gains in unfamiliarity. The modern experience of the foreign is indeterminate otherness instead of determined negation that characterized pre-modern alterity. Modern societies therefore need to mediate between validity and contingency under the circumstances of plurality. Interpretational demands and uncertainty about the relevant interpretive frames increase. Foreignness is then experienced as unfamiliarity. This presupposes intellectual attitudes like irritability, curiosity, and willingness to learn. The modern concept of ‘culture’ then is proposed as a comparative pattern where only unavoidable structural asymmetry remains. It explains cultural differences and the experience of foreignness through heterogeneity. Using this specifically modern pattern, there is no longer a legitimate value slope between one’s own position and its negation. The distinction is then between the familiar and the unfamiliar.","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71263885","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Common Conceptions and the Metaphysics of Material Substance 共同概念与物质实体的形而上学
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems2019815
H. T. Adriaenssen
This paper explores how, according to three early modern philosophers, philosophical theory should relate to our pre-theoretical picture of reality. Though coming from very different backgrounds, the Spanish scholastic, Domingo de Soto, and the English natural philosopher, Kenelm Digby, agreed that an ability to accommodate our pre-theoretical picture of the world and our ordinary way of speaking about reality is a virtue for a philosophical theory. Yet at the same time, they disagreed on what kind of ontology of the material world is implied by these. The Dutch Cartesian, Johannes de Raey, took a very different approach, and argued that the picture of reality we naturally develop from our early days onwards and the language associated with it have their use in domains such as law and medical practice, but are a poor guide to the ontology of the material world. Thus, if we are to arrive at a proper understanding of the nature of matter, we need to move beyond the picture of reality we naturally develop from our early days onwards in order to come to see that the nature of matter consists in bare extension.
根据三位早期现代哲学家的观点,本文探讨了哲学理论应该如何与我们的理论之前的现实图景联系起来。尽管来自不同的背景,西班牙学者多明戈·德·索托(Domingo de Soto)和英国自然哲学家凯尼姆·迪格比(Kenelm Digby)一致认为,对于哲学理论来说,能够容纳我们在理论之前的世界图景和我们谈论现实的普通方式是一种美德。但与此同时,他们对这些隐含着什么样的物质世界本体论存在分歧。荷兰笛卡尔学派的约翰内斯·德雷(Johannes de Raey)采取了一种截然不同的方法,他认为,我们从早期开始自然形成的现实图景,以及与之相关的语言,在法律和医疗实践等领域都有应用,但对物质世界的本体论却没有什么指导作用。因此,如果我们要达到对物质本质的正确理解,我们需要超越我们从早期自然发展起来的现实图景,以便看到物质的本质包含着纯粹的延伸。
{"title":"Common Conceptions and the Metaphysics of Material Substance","authors":"H. T. Adriaenssen","doi":"10.5840/jems2019815","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems2019815","url":null,"abstract":"This paper explores how, according to three early modern philosophers, philosophical theory should relate to our pre-theoretical picture of reality. Though coming from very different backgrounds, the Spanish scholastic, Domingo de Soto, and the English natural philosopher, Kenelm Digby, agreed that an ability to accommodate our pre-theoretical picture of the world and our ordinary way of speaking about reality is a virtue for a philosophical theory. Yet at the same time, they disagreed on what kind of ontology of the material world is implied by these. The Dutch Cartesian, Johannes de Raey, took a very different approach, and argued that the picture of reality we naturally develop from our early days onwards and the language associated with it have their use in domains such as law and medical practice, but are a poor guide to the ontology of the material world. Thus, if we are to arrive at a proper understanding of the nature of matter, we need to move beyond the picture of reality we naturally develop from our early days onwards in order to come to see that the nature of matter consists in bare extension.","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71263254","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Making Mathematical Culture: University and Print in the Circle of Lefèvre d’Étaples, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018 (Iovan Drehe) 《创造数学文化:左派文学圈的大学与印刷》Étaples,牛津:牛津大学出版社,2018年(Iovan Drehe)
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems2019819
R. Oosterhoff
{"title":"Making Mathematical Culture: University and Print in the Circle of Lefèvre d’Étaples, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018 (Iovan Drehe)","authors":"R. Oosterhoff","doi":"10.5840/jems2019819","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems2019819","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71263540","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Ursula Franke, Baumgartens Erfindung der Asthetik. Mit einem Anhang: Baumgartens Asthetik im Uberblick von Nicolas Kleinschmidt 乌苏拉弗兰克,园艺之父请看一个小故事"绿树花园
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20198217
Alessandro Nannini
{"title":"Ursula Franke, Baumgartens Erfindung der Asthetik. Mit einem Anhang: Baumgartens Asthetik im Uberblick von Nicolas Kleinschmidt","authors":"Alessandro Nannini","doi":"10.5840/jems20198217","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20198217","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71263565","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Cosmos Without a Creator 没有造物主的宇宙
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20198211
P. Omodeo, Zeta Books
In the years after the first circulation of Sidereus Nuncius, Galileo’s Padua anti-Copernican colleague, the staunch Aristotelian philosopher, Cesare Cremonini, published a book on ‘traditional’ cosmology, Disputatio de coelo in tres partes divisa (Venice, 1613) which puzzled the Roman authorities of the Inquisition and the Index much more than any works on celestial novelties and ‘neo-Pythagorean’ astronomy. Cremonini’s disputation on the heavens has the form of an over-intricate comment of Aristotle’s conceptions, in the typi­cally argumentative style of Scholasticism. Nonetheless, it immediately raised the concern of Cardinal Bellarmin, the Pope and other Inquisitors. At a close reading, Cremonini’s interpretation of Aristotle’s cosmos proved radically anti- Christian. It represented a radicalization of Pomponazzian Alexandrism. In fact, Cremonini did not only circulate Aristotelian principles used by Pom­ponazzi to argue for the soul’s mortality (first, no thought is possible without imagination and the latter faculty is dependent on the body; secondly, all that is generated will eventually perish). He also wiped away all transcendence from the Aristotelian cosmos. In fact, he marginalized the function of the motive Intelligences by explaining heavenly motions through the action of animal-like inseparable souls although he did not erase nor reduced all Intelligences to only one, in accordance with Alexander. Also, he put at the center of Aristotle’s cosmos the idea of its eternity, a thesis which he explicitly connected with the rejection of the idea of God the Creator. Cremonini assumed that the univer­sal efficiens, that is the efficient cause of all motion and change in the world, is nothing but the first heaven. As a result of this radically naturalist reading of Aristotle, he banned God from the cosmos, reduced Him to the final cause of the world, and deprived Him of any efficiency and will. This essay on less ex­plored sources of Renaissance astronomical debates considers the institutional, cultural and religious setting of Cremonini’s teaching and conceptions. It as­sesses the reasons for his troubles with the religious authorities, and the politi­cal support he was granted by the Serenissima Republic of Venice inspite of the scandalous opinions he circulated as a university professor. My reconstruction of his views is based on the Disputatio de coelo of 1613 and later works, which are directly connected with cosmo-theological polemics with the religious au­thorities: his Apologia dictorum Aristotelis de quinta coeli substantia (1616) and the unpublished book De coeli efficientia, two manuscript copies of which are preserved in the libraries of Padua and Venice.
伽利略的帕多瓦反哥白尼派同事、坚定的亚里士多德哲学家切萨雷·克雷莫尼尼(Cesare Cremonini)出版了一本关于“传统”宇宙学的书《论论》(Disputatio de coelo In treres partes divisa, 1613年,威尼斯),这本书比任何关于天体新奇事物和“新毕达哥拉斯”天文学的著作更让罗马宗教法庭和索引当局感到困惑。克雷莫尼尼关于天堂的辩论,以典型的经院哲学论辩风格,对亚里士多德的概念进行了过于复杂的评论。尽管如此,它立即引起了红衣主教贝拉明、教皇和其他宗教裁判官的关注。仔细一读,克雷莫尼尼对亚里士多德宇宙的解释被证明是完全反基督教的。它代表了庞庞纳齐派亚历山大主义的激进化。事实上,克雷莫尼尼不仅传播了庞帕纳齐用来论证灵魂死亡的亚里士多德原则(首先,没有想象力就不可能有思想,想象力依赖于身体;其次,所有产生的东西最终都会消亡。他还从亚里士多德的宇宙中抹去了所有的超越性。事实上,他通过动物般的不可分割的灵魂的活动来解释天堂的运动,从而边缘化了动机智能的功能,尽管他没有抹去也没有将所有智能简化为一个,这与亚历山大的观点一致。此外,他把宇宙的永恒性观念置于亚里士多德的宇宙理论的中心,他明确地把这个论点与拒绝上帝是创造者的观念联系起来。克雷莫尼尼假定宇宙效率,即世界上一切运动和变化的有效原因,只不过是第一个天堂。这种对亚里士多德的极端自然主义解读的结果是,他将上帝排除在宇宙之外,将他贬为世界的最终原因,并剥夺了他的任何效率和意志。这篇关于文艺复兴时期天文学辩论的较少探索的来源的文章考虑了克雷莫尼尼的教学和概念的制度,文化和宗教背景。书中分析了他与宗教当局之间的矛盾,以及尽管他作为一名大学教授散布着一些诽谤性言论,但威尼斯塞雷尼西马共和国仍给予他政治支持的原因。我对他的观点的重建是基于1613年的《论辩》(Disputatio de coelo)和后来的作品,这些作品与与宗教权威的宇宙神学论战直接相关:他的《亚里士多德的辩词》(Apologia dictorum Aristotelis de quinta coeli substantia, 1616)和未出版的《效率论》(de coeli efficientia),两本手稿副本保存在帕多瓦和威尼斯的图书馆。
{"title":"A Cosmos Without a Creator","authors":"P. Omodeo, Zeta Books","doi":"10.5840/jems20198211","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20198211","url":null,"abstract":"In the years after the first circulation of Sidereus Nuncius, Galileo’s Padua anti-Copernican colleague, the staunch Aristotelian philosopher, Cesare Cremonini, published a book on ‘traditional’ cosmology, Disputatio de coelo in tres partes divisa (Venice, 1613) which puzzled the Roman authorities of the Inquisition and the Index much more than any works on celestial novelties and ‘neo-Pythagorean’ astronomy. Cremonini’s disputation on the heavens has the form of an over-intricate comment of Aristotle’s conceptions, in the typi­cally argumentative style of Scholasticism. Nonetheless, it immediately raised the concern of Cardinal Bellarmin, the Pope and other Inquisitors. At a close reading, Cremonini’s interpretation of Aristotle’s cosmos proved radically anti- Christian. It represented a radicalization of Pomponazzian Alexandrism. In fact, Cremonini did not only circulate Aristotelian principles used by Pom­ponazzi to argue for the soul’s mortality (first, no thought is possible without imagination and the latter faculty is dependent on the body; secondly, all that is generated will eventually perish). He also wiped away all transcendence from the Aristotelian cosmos. In fact, he marginalized the function of the motive Intelligences by explaining heavenly motions through the action of animal-like inseparable souls although he did not erase nor reduced all Intelligences to only one, in accordance with Alexander. Also, he put at the center of Aristotle’s cosmos the idea of its eternity, a thesis which he explicitly connected with the rejection of the idea of God the Creator. Cremonini assumed that the univer­sal efficiens, that is the efficient cause of all motion and change in the world, is nothing but the first heaven. As a result of this radically naturalist reading of Aristotle, he banned God from the cosmos, reduced Him to the final cause of the world, and deprived Him of any efficiency and will. This essay on less ex­plored sources of Renaissance astronomical debates considers the institutional, cultural and religious setting of Cremonini’s teaching and conceptions. It as­sesses the reasons for his troubles with the religious authorities, and the politi­cal support he was granted by the Serenissima Republic of Venice inspite of the scandalous opinions he circulated as a university professor. My reconstruction of his views is based on the Disputatio de coelo of 1613 and later works, which are directly connected with cosmo-theological polemics with the religious au­thorities: his Apologia dictorum Aristotelis de quinta coeli substantia (1616) and the unpublished book De coeli efficientia, two manuscript copies of which are preserved in the libraries of Padua and Venice.","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71263591","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Emergence of Modern Aesthetic Theory: Religion and Morality in Enlightenment Germany and Scotland 现代美学理论的兴起:启蒙时期德国和苏格兰的宗教与道德
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2018-10-01 DOI: 10.5840/JEMS20187218
Eduard Ghiţă, Zeta Books
{"title":"The Emergence of Modern Aesthetic Theory: Religion and Morality in Enlightenment Germany and Scotland","authors":"Eduard Ghiţă, Zeta Books","doi":"10.5840/JEMS20187218","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JEMS20187218","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"7 1","pages":"124-127"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49606459","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Indecorous Thinking: Figures of Speech in Early Modern Poetics 不雅思维:现代早期诗学的修辞
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2018-10-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20187215
R. Vuillemin, Zeta Books
{"title":"Indecorous Thinking: Figures of Speech in Early Modern Poetics","authors":"R. Vuillemin, Zeta Books","doi":"10.5840/jems20187215","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20187215","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"7 1","pages":"107-111"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42598769","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
L’ateismo dei moderni. Filosofia e negazione di Dio da Spinoza a d’Holbach 现代无神论。哲学与对上帝的否定——从斯宾诺莎到德霍尔巴赫
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2018-10-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20187217
Diego Lucci, Zeta Books
{"title":"L’ateismo dei moderni. Filosofia e negazione di Dio da Spinoza a d’Holbach","authors":"Diego Lucci, Zeta Books","doi":"10.5840/jems20187217","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20187217","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"7 1","pages":"118-124"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45717958","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Philosophical Duelism: Fencing in Early Modern Thought 哲学决斗:近代早期思想中的剑术
IF 0.2 0 HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2018-10-01 DOI: 10.5840/jems20187212
K. Delapp, Zeta Books
{"title":"Philosophical Duelism: Fencing in Early Modern Thought","authors":"K. Delapp, Zeta Books","doi":"10.5840/jems20187212","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/jems20187212","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":53837,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania","volume":"7 1","pages":"31-54"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2018-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44486337","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of Early Modern Studies-Romania
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1