首页 > 最新文献

Rivista di Estetica最新文献

英文 中文
Musil in a loop: the other condition and the extended mind 陷入循环:另一种状态和扩展的思维
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-04-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5067
E. D. Bona, S. Ercolino
In this paper, we propose a reading of Robert Musil’s controversial notion of the “other condition” in light of the basic features of the philosophical doctrine of externalism, as formulated in the classical account of the extended mind proposed by Andy Clark and David Chalmers (1998). Our reading is not meant to exhaust the complexity and polysemy of the idea of the other condition, but merely aims to open up a possible perspective on the interpretation of a concept that is as elusive as it is central in Musil’s thinking.
在本文中,我们根据外部主义哲学学说的基本特征,提出了对罗伯特·穆希尔有争议的“他者条件”概念的解读,正如安迪·克拉克和大卫·查默斯(1998)提出的扩展思维的经典描述所阐述的那样。我们的阅读并不是要穷尽另一种情况的复杂性和多义性,而只是为了打开一个可能的视角来解释一个概念,这个概念是难以捉摸的,因为它是Musil思想的中心。
{"title":"Musil in a loop: the other condition and the extended mind","authors":"E. D. Bona, S. Ercolino","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5067","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5067","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, we propose a reading of Robert Musil’s controversial notion of the “other condition” in light of the basic features of the philosophical doctrine of externalism, as formulated in the classical account of the extended mind proposed by Andy Clark and David Chalmers (1998). Our reading is not meant to exhaust the complexity and polysemy of the idea of the other condition, but merely aims to open up a possible perspective on the interpretation of a concept that is as elusive as it is central in Musil’s thinking.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48739896","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dalla letteratura alla filosofia. Il Proust di Deleuze 从文学到哲学。德勒兹的普鲁斯特
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-04-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.5030
D. Angelucci
The present paper traces some of the main articulations of the book Marcel Proust and the signs (1964), in which the French philosopher Gilles Deleuze affirms the superiority of literature on classical rationalist philosophy in the search for truth. Proust’s work rivals the philosophy itself, since it brings into play the involuntary nature of memory and intelligence – a condition which lies at the beginning of every thought – which can grasp the truth only solicited and forced by chance encounters. Classical rationalist philosophy as a methodical exercise, induced by the good will of the thinker, can instead reach only abstract and conventional truths. The paper underlines how, according to Deleuze, Proust’s work will represent the model of authentic philosophy, the one that comes to produce with violence new concepts forced by problems and urgencies that impose themselves from outside. In fact, in Difference and Repetition (1968), the characteristics ascribed to the Proustian Recherche are explicitly attributed to a philosophy of Difference, which is posited by the author as the real need of his own time. In 1991, Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari posed the question: What is philosophy? The attributes previously assigned to the literature, reappeared in the answer to such a question. A paradoxical necessity – reached through contingent encounters on one side, and the involuntary nature of thought on the other side – will appear at the center of the book that closes the theoretical trajectory of Deleuze: such a paradox shows itself as the only condition for the “invention of concepts”, which is at the same time the definition and ultimate task of philosophical practice.
本文追溯了法国哲学家吉勒·德勒兹(Gilles Deleuze)在1964年出版的《普鲁斯特与符号》(Marcel Proust and The signs)一书中的一些主要论述,在该书中,他肯定了文学在寻找真理方面优于古典理性主义哲学。普鲁斯特的作品可以与哲学本身相媲美,因为它发挥了记忆和智慧的非自愿性质——这是每一个想法开始时的一种条件——只有在偶然的相遇中才能抓住真相。古典理性主义哲学作为一种有条理的实践,由思想家的善意引导,只能达到抽象和传统的真理。德勒兹认为,这篇论文强调了普鲁斯特的作品将如何代表真实哲学的模式,这种模式是由外部强加的问题和紧迫性强行产生的新概念。事实上,在《差异与重复》(1968)中,普鲁斯特研究所具有的特征被明确地归因于一种差异哲学,作者认为这是他自己时代的真正需要。1991年,Gilles Deleuze和Felix Guattari提出了一个问题:什么是哲学?以前赋予文献的属性,再次出现在对这样一个问题的回答中。一种矛盾的必然性——一方面是偶然的遭遇,另一方面是思想的非自愿性质——将出现在这本书的中心,这本书关闭了德勒兹的理论轨迹:这样的悖论表明自己是“概念发明”的唯一条件,这既是哲学实践的定义,也是哲学实践的终极任务。
{"title":"Dalla letteratura alla filosofia. Il Proust di Deleuze","authors":"D. Angelucci","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.5030","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.5030","url":null,"abstract":"The present paper traces some of the main articulations of the book Marcel Proust and the signs (1964), in which the French philosopher Gilles Deleuze affirms the superiority of literature on classical rationalist philosophy in the search for truth. Proust’s work rivals the philosophy itself, since it brings into play the involuntary nature of memory and intelligence – a condition which lies at the beginning of every thought – which can grasp the truth only solicited and forced by chance encounters. Classical rationalist philosophy as a methodical exercise, induced by the good will of the thinker, can instead reach only abstract and conventional truths. The paper underlines how, according to Deleuze, Proust’s work will represent the model of authentic philosophy, the one that comes to produce with violence new concepts forced by problems and urgencies that impose themselves from outside. In fact, in Difference and Repetition (1968), the characteristics ascribed to the Proustian Recherche are explicitly attributed to a philosophy of Difference, which is posited by the author as the real need of his own time. In 1991, Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari posed the question: What is philosophy? The attributes previously assigned to the literature, reappeared in the answer to such a question. A paradoxical necessity – reached through contingent encounters on one side, and the involuntary nature of thought on the other side – will appear at the center of the book that closes the theoretical trajectory of Deleuze: such a paradox shows itself as the only condition for the “invention of concepts”, which is at the same time the definition and ultimate task of philosophical practice.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43243400","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Art, Moral Understanding, Radical Changes 艺术、道德理解、根本变革
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2018-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.3666
E. Baccarini
Empirical methods interact with moral philosophy in several ways. In this paper I remark the role of experience, as well as formative experience, in moral epistemology. I defend the thesis that abstract reasoning is not sufficient in morality. Experiences are needed for refined moral judgments. In particular, I focus on experience and formative experience through engagement with artworks. I endorse a form of art cognitivism, the thesis that we can learn through experiences of artworks, but here I remain neutral toward whether the cognitive value of artworks contributes to their artistic value. In my view, learning from artworks is not detached from abstract reasoning, but complementary to it. This is needed in order to reply to an objection directed at art cognitivism, one which appeals to the fact that the properties of artworks can improve our moral cognitive capacities, as well as reduce them. I reply to this objection by saying that although art is one resource of moral learning, it is not the only resource. This is why we must not passively endorse insights that are derived from experiences of artworks. We must critically analyse these by comparing them with other beliefs and experiences. Experiences of artworks are a source of moral learning, but insights that are derived from them must be reflective and critically examined. The model is a kind of reflective equilibrium, where various sources of learning interact and support, as well as check, each other for moral learning.
实证方法在几个方面与道德哲学相互作用。在这篇文章中,我评论了经验以及形成性经验在道德认识论中的作用。我为抽象推理在道德上是不够的这一论点辩护。精细的道德判断需要经验。特别是,我通过参与艺术品来关注经验和形成经验。我赞同艺术认知主义的一种形式,即我们可以通过艺术品的经验来学习的论点,但在这里,我对艺术品的认知价值是否有助于其艺术价值保持中立。在我看来,从艺术品中学习并不是脱离抽象推理,而是对抽象推理的补充。这是为了回应针对艺术认知主义的反对意见,即艺术品的属性可以提高我们的道德认知能力,也可以降低它们。我对这一反对意见的回应是,尽管艺术是道德学习的一种资源,但它并不是唯一的资源。这就是为什么我们不能被动地认可从艺术品经验中获得的见解。我们必须通过将它们与其他信仰和经历进行比较来批判性地分析它们。艺术品的经验是道德学习的源泉,但从中获得的见解必须是反思和批判性的。该模型是一种反思性平衡,在这种平衡中,各种学习来源相互作用,相互支持,也相互制约道德学习。
{"title":"Art, Moral Understanding, Radical Changes","authors":"E. Baccarini","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.3666","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.3666","url":null,"abstract":"Empirical methods interact with moral philosophy in several ways. In this paper I remark the role of experience, as well as formative experience, in moral epistemology. I defend the thesis that abstract reasoning is not sufficient in morality. Experiences are needed for refined moral judgments. In particular, I focus on experience and formative experience through engagement with artworks. I endorse a form of art cognitivism, the thesis that we can learn through experiences of artworks, but here I remain neutral toward whether the cognitive value of artworks contributes to their artistic value. In my view, learning from artworks is not detached from abstract reasoning, but complementary to it. This is needed in order to reply to an objection directed at art cognitivism, one which appeals to the fact that the properties of artworks can improve our moral cognitive capacities, as well as reduce them. I reply to this objection by saying that although art is one resource of moral learning, it is not the only resource. This is why we must not passively endorse insights that are derived from experiences of artworks. We must critically analyse these by comparing them with other beliefs and experiences. Experiences of artworks are a source of moral learning, but insights that are derived from them must be reflective and critically examined. The model is a kind of reflective equilibrium, where various sources of learning interact and support, as well as check, each other for moral learning.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2018-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48538810","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Metaphysics as Logic 作为逻辑的形而上学
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2018-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.3637
A. Strollo
Philosophy, and analytic metaphysics in particular, is usually described as an armchair discipline, and exactly for such an armchair methodology it has been the target of ferocious criticisms. In this paper, I argue that the theoretical right to conduct metaphysics from the armchair can be defended understanding metaphysics as a form of Logic (broadly understood as including applied logics, philosophical logics and, especially, philosophy of logic). So characterized, the typical practice of metaphysics is not more problematic than the armchair methodology routinely employed in the study of Logic.
哲学,尤其是分析形而上学,通常被描述为一门纸上谈兵的学科,正是因为这种纸上谈机的方法论,它一直是猛烈批评的目标。在本文中,我认为在扶手椅上进行形而上学的理论权利可以被捍卫,将形而上学理解为一种逻辑形式(广泛理解为包括应用逻辑、哲学逻辑,尤其是逻辑哲学)。因此,形而上学的典型实践并不比逻辑学研究中经常使用的纸上谈兵的方法论更有问题。
{"title":"Metaphysics as Logic","authors":"A. Strollo","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.3637","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.3637","url":null,"abstract":"Philosophy, and analytic metaphysics in particular, is usually described as an armchair discipline, and exactly for such an armchair methodology it has been the target of ferocious criticisms. In this paper, I argue that the theoretical right to conduct metaphysics from the armchair can be defended understanding metaphysics as a form of Logic (broadly understood as including applied logics, philosophical logics and, especially, philosophy of logic). So characterized, the typical practice of metaphysics is not more problematic than the armchair methodology routinely employed in the study of Logic.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2018-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44240832","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Fact of Reason, Social Facts, and Evidence 理性的事实,社会事实和证据
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2018-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.3747
P. Bojanić, Igor Cvejić
The place of evidence regarding joint commitment and plural action is mostly reserved for documents and explicit linguistic expressions. This paper considers the problem of evidence in cases of engaged (jointly committed) social acts where there is no explicit expression or binding document, yet can still be ascribed to a plural subject. The argument rests on the double meaning of the term factum as fact (factum brutum) and deed (factum practica), as well as contemporary debates about the topic of fact of reason in Kant. The text seeks to show that in certain cases, the execution of an act or the obligation produced by it can be considered evidence of a plural subject. Thus, these facts deserve a special position in relation to scientific evidence.
关于共同承诺和多重行为的证据大多保留在文件和明确的语言表达中。本文考虑了在没有明确表述或具有约束力的文件,但仍可归属于复数主体的从事(共同实施)社会行为案件中的证据问题。争论的基础是“事实”一词作为事实(factum brutum)和行为(factum practica)的双重含义,以及当代关于康德理性事实主题的争论。案文试图表明,在某些情况下,行为的执行或由此产生的义务可以被视为复数主语的证据。因此,这些事实应该在科学证据中占有特殊的地位。
{"title":"Fact of Reason, Social Facts, and Evidence","authors":"P. Bojanić, Igor Cvejić","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.3747","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.3747","url":null,"abstract":"The place of evidence regarding joint commitment and plural action is mostly reserved for documents and explicit linguistic expressions. This paper considers the problem of evidence in cases of engaged (jointly committed) social acts where there is no explicit expression or binding document, yet can still be ascribed to a plural subject. The argument rests on the double meaning of the term factum as fact (factum brutum) and deed (factum practica), as well as contemporary debates about the topic of fact of reason in Kant. The text seeks to show that in certain cases, the execution of an act or the obligation produced by it can be considered evidence of a plural subject. Thus, these facts deserve a special position in relation to scientific evidence.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2018-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42536086","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Conceptual Analysis and Empirical Data 概念分析与实证数据
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2018-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.3627
P. Bojanić, S. Iaquinto, G. Torrengo
Suppose you want to find out whether truth is a necessary condition for knowledge. What method should you apply? According to many philosophers, it is hard to see what kind of empirical data you could ever rely on. The best way to proceed – they continue – is to examine hypothetical circumstances in order to test our intuitions as to the correct application of the concept of knowledge. Can you imagine a case in which a given cognitive agent knows something false? Would you say, for instance, ...
假设你想知道真理是否是知识的必要条件。你应该采用什么方法?根据许多哲学家的说法,很难看出你可以依赖什么样的经验数据。最好的方法是——他们继续——检查假设的情况,以测试我们对知识概念正确应用的直觉。你能想象一个特定的认知主体知道一些错误的事情吗?例如,你会说。。。
{"title":"Conceptual Analysis and Empirical Data","authors":"P. Bojanić, S. Iaquinto, G. Torrengo","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.3627","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.3627","url":null,"abstract":"Suppose you want to find out whether truth is a necessary condition for knowledge. What method should you apply? According to many philosophers, it is hard to see what kind of empirical data you could ever rely on. The best way to proceed – they continue – is to examine hypothetical circumstances in order to test our intuitions as to the correct application of the concept of knowledge. Can you imagine a case in which a given cognitive agent knows something false? Would you say, for instance, ...","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2018-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46343743","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Is beauty in the folk intuition of the beholder? Some thoughts on experimental philosophy and aesthetics 美在旁观者的民间直觉中吗?关于实验哲学与美学的几点思考
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2018-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.3661
E. Arielli
In this paper I will discuss some issues related to a recent trend in experimental philosophy (or x-phi), and try to show the reasons of its late (and scarce) involvement with aesthetics, compared to other areas of philosophical investigation. In order to do this, it is first necessary to ask how an autonomous experimental philosophy of aesthetics could be related to the long-standing tradition of psychological experimental aesthetics. After distinguishing between a “narrow” and a “broad” approach of experimental philosophy, I will then make a distinction between topics in aesthetics pertaining to perceptual and cognitive processes, and traditional issues involved in the analysis of general and culturally-laden concepts. The narrow program of experimental philosophy, focused on the investigation of folk intuitions, is particularly effective only when two general conditions are met: the use of hypothetical scenarios (testing of thought experiments) and the heuristic role of folk intuitions in drawing philosophically relevant conclusions. I will argue that, when aesthetics is concerned, these requirements are not easily met. These difficulties notwithstanding, I will support a pluralistic view where aesthetics is revealed as an instructive example of how experimental approaches and traditional “armchair” philosophy integrate, and enrich each other.
在本文中,我将讨论与实验哲学(或x-phi)的最新趋势有关的一些问题,并试图说明与其他哲学研究领域相比,它与美学的关系较晚(而且很少)的原因。为了做到这一点,首先有必要问一个问题,一个自主的实验美学哲学如何与长期存在的心理实验美学传统联系起来。在区分了实验哲学的“狭义”和“广义”方法之后,我将区分与感知和认知过程有关的美学主题,以及涉及一般和文化负载概念分析的传统问题。专注于民间直觉调查的实验哲学的狭隘程序,只有在满足两个一般条件时才特别有效:使用假设情景(思想实验的测试)和民间直觉在得出哲学相关结论时的启发式作用。我认为,当涉及到美学时,这些要求并不容易满足。尽管存在这些困难,我还是支持一种多元化的观点,在这种观点中,美学被揭示为一个有启发性的例子,说明实验方法和传统的“扶手椅”哲学是如何相互融合和丰富的。
{"title":"Is beauty in the folk intuition of the beholder? Some thoughts on experimental philosophy and aesthetics","authors":"E. Arielli","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.3661","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.3661","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper I will discuss some issues related to a recent trend in experimental philosophy (or x-phi), and try to show the reasons of its late (and scarce) involvement with aesthetics, compared to other areas of philosophical investigation. In order to do this, it is first necessary to ask how an autonomous experimental philosophy of aesthetics could be related to the long-standing tradition of psychological experimental aesthetics. After distinguishing between a “narrow” and a “broad” approach of experimental philosophy, I will then make a distinction between topics in aesthetics pertaining to perceptual and cognitive processes, and traditional issues involved in the analysis of general and culturally-laden concepts. The narrow program of experimental philosophy, focused on the investigation of folk intuitions, is particularly effective only when two general conditions are met: the use of hypothetical scenarios (testing of thought experiments) and the heuristic role of folk intuitions in drawing philosophically relevant conclusions. I will argue that, when aesthetics is concerned, these requirements are not easily met. These difficulties notwithstanding, I will support a pluralistic view where aesthetics is revealed as an instructive example of how experimental approaches and traditional “armchair” philosophy integrate, and enrich each other.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2018-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47268937","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Agency Evidentialism: Trust and Doxastic Voluntarism 代理证据主义:信任与多克主义自愿主义
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2018-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.3701
Snjezana Prijic-Samarzija
In debates about trust and testimony, epistemologists have traditionally been divided into two groups: those who hold that accepting the testimony of other people should be a kind of credulity without evidence (anti-reductivism) and those who assert that we shouldn't recognize any testimony as true or justified without appropriate evidence (reductivism). I will argue in favour of the evidentialist position about trust, or the stance that epistemically responsible trust is a matter of evidence, but also in favour of the thesis that the position assumed by anti-reductivists is not necessarily an anti-evidentialist position. The crucial difference between anti-reductivism and reductivism does not pertain to the question of evidence, but to epistemic agency. Finally, I will argue against anti-reductivism and in favour of agency evidentialism, wherein it is assumed that accepting testimony is a kind of agency where our (reflective) control is strong enough to ensure that our trust is responsible. The version of agency evidentialism which I here support presumes: (i) doxastic voluntarism, or the existence of intellectual freedom in the sense that we have to be capable of certain intellectual choices or decisions, and (ii) virtue epistemology, or the normative approach according to which the target of epistemic evaluation is an epistemic agent to whom we ascribe epistemic or intellectual virtues or vices (epistemic responsibility, epistemic conscientiousness or like.)
在关于信任和证词的辩论中,认识论者传统上分为两类:一类认为接受他人证词应该是一种没有证据的轻信(反还原主义),另一类认为我们不应该在没有适当证据的情况下承认任何证词是真实或合理的(还原主义)。我将支持关于信任的证据主义立场,或者支持认识上负责任的信任是证据问题的立场,但也支持反还原主义者所采取的立场不一定是反证据主义立场的论点。反还原论和还原论的关键区别不在于证据问题,而在于认识能动性。最后,我将反对反还原主义,支持代理证据主义,即认为接受证词是一种我们(反思性)控制足够强大的机构,以确保我们的信任是负责任的。我在这里支持的代理证据主义的版本假设:(I)多论的自愿主义,或在我们必须能够做出某些智力选择或决定的意义上的智力自由的存在,以及(ii)美德认识论,或者规范方法,根据该方法,认知评估的目标是一个认知主体,我们将其归因于认知或智力上的美德或恶习(认知责任、认知尽责等)
{"title":"Agency Evidentialism: Trust and Doxastic Voluntarism","authors":"Snjezana Prijic-Samarzija","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.3701","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.3701","url":null,"abstract":"In debates about trust and testimony, epistemologists have traditionally been divided into two groups: those who hold that accepting the testimony of other people should be a kind of credulity without evidence (anti-reductivism) and those who assert that we shouldn't recognize any testimony as true or justified without appropriate evidence (reductivism). I will argue in favour of the evidentialist position about trust, or the stance that epistemically responsible trust is a matter of evidence, but also in favour of the thesis that the position assumed by anti-reductivists is not necessarily an anti-evidentialist position. The crucial difference between anti-reductivism and reductivism does not pertain to the question of evidence, but to epistemic agency. Finally, I will argue against anti-reductivism and in favour of agency evidentialism, wherein it is assumed that accepting testimony is a kind of agency where our (reflective) control is strong enough to ensure that our trust is responsible. The version of agency evidentialism which I here support presumes: (i) doxastic voluntarism, or the existence of intellectual freedom in the sense that we have to be capable of certain intellectual choices or decisions, and (ii) virtue epistemology, or the normative approach according to which the target of epistemic evaluation is an epistemic agent to whom we ascribe epistemic or intellectual virtues or vices (epistemic responsibility, epistemic conscientiousness or like.)","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2018-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45056968","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Forma e immagine: una lettura critica 形状与图像:批判性解读
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2018-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.3925
Filippo Contesi
In a recent book, Immagine, Alberto Voltolini offers a rich and carefully written discussion of theories of depiction, which have drawn so much attention in recent Anglophone philosophy. Although Voltolini’s book has indisputable virtues, it also makes some questionable formal choices. The present essay presents a formal analysis of the book.
阿尔贝托·沃尔托里尼(Alberto Voltolini)在他的新书《想象》(imagine)中,对描写理论进行了丰富而细致的讨论,这些理论在最近的英语哲学中引起了如此多的关注。尽管Voltolini的书有无可争议的优点,但它也做出了一些可疑的正式选择。这篇文章是对这本书的正式分析。
{"title":"Forma e immagine: una lettura critica","authors":"Filippo Contesi","doi":"10.4000/estetica.3925","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.3925","url":null,"abstract":"In a recent book, Immagine, Alberto Voltolini offers a rich and carefully written discussion of theories of depiction, which have drawn so much attention in recent Anglophone philosophy. Although Voltolini’s book has indisputable virtues, it also makes some questionable formal choices. The present essay presents a formal analysis of the book.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2018-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47018472","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Public reason, civic trust and conclusions of science 公共理性、公民信任与科学结论
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2018-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.3783
Nebojša Zelič
Rawlsian idea of public reason refers to the boundaries on political justification of coercive laws and public policies that have wide impact on lives of citizens. The boundaries of public reason means that political justification should be based on reasons we can expect every citizen can reasonably accept independently of any comprehensive religious, philosophical or moral doctrine to which she adhere. In modern liberal democracies characterized by reasonable pluralism of comprehensive doctrines it is unjustified for political argumentation to be based on claims that many citizens can not accept. As I understand it, the point of idea of public reason is to strengthen the relationship of civic trust or civic friendship that can ensure inherent stability of just political regime. An important part of the idea of public reason is how it incorporates scientific claims in political argumentation. Rawls writes that citizens are to base their public justification on „presently accepted general beliefs and forms of reasoning found in common sense, and the methods and conclusions of science when those are not controversial.“ If the idea of public reason is the source of political stability it is necessary to answer what it means that conclusions of science are controversial in political and social context? First, scientific controversy is different from controversy of comprehensive doctrines. Science stands outside of comprehensive doctrines so conclusions of science will not be controversial because they clash with comprehensive beliefs, but they will be controversial if they rely on comprehensive beliefs. Second, if conclusions of science are controversial within scientific community, if there are some expert witness disputing its validity, then maybe value-judgments can enter to set standards for certification of the scientific claim. If potential consequences of scientific claim are bad for welfare of some group in society than standards of evidence that will certify this claim must go up. Finally, even if some scientific claim has been certified it still can be controversial as a premise in political justification. The reason can be that certification has not been transparent and many citizens do not realize that this claim is part of scientific consensus. Again, the criterion for controversy of scientific conclusions in political context is connected to the notion of trust and not to the validity of scientific claim or supportive evidence by itself.
罗尔斯的公共理性思想是指对公民生活产生广泛影响的强制性法律和公共政策的政治正当性界限。公共理性的界限意味着,政治正当性应该基于我们可以期望每个公民都能合理接受的理由,而不依赖于她所坚持的任何全面的宗教、哲学或道德学说。在现代自由民主国家,其特点是全面学说的合理多元化,政治论证基于许多公民无法接受的主张是不合理的。据我所知,公共理性的意义在于加强公民信任或公民友谊的关系,以确保公正政治制度的内在稳定。公共理性思想的一个重要部分是它如何将科学主张纳入政治论证中。罗尔斯写道,公民的公共辩护应建立在“目前公认的普遍信仰和常识中的推理形式,以及没有争议的科学方法和结论”的基础上。“如果公共理性是政治稳定的源泉,那么有必要回答科学结论在政治和社会背景下有争议意味着什么?首先,科学争议不同于综合学说的争议。科学站在综合学说之外,因此科学结论不会因为与政治和社会环境相冲突而引起争议i综合信仰,但如果他们依赖于综合信仰,就会引起争议。其次,如果科学结论在科学界存在争议,如果有一些专家证人对其有效性提出质疑,那么也许可以通过价值判断来制定科学主张的认证标准。如果科学主张的潜在后果对社会上某些群体的福利不利,那么证明这一主张的证据标准必须提高。最后,即使一些科学主张得到了证实,作为政治论证的前提,它仍然可能存在争议。原因可能是认证不透明,许多公民没有意识到这一说法是科学共识的一部分。同样,在政治背景下对科学结论进行争议的标准与信任的概念有关,而不是与科学主张或支持性证据本身的有效性有关。
{"title":"Public reason, civic trust and conclusions of science","authors":"Nebojša Zelič","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.3783","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.3783","url":null,"abstract":"Rawlsian idea of public reason refers to the boundaries on political justification of coercive laws and public policies that have wide impact on lives of citizens. The boundaries of public reason means that political justification should be based on reasons we can expect every citizen can reasonably accept independently of any comprehensive religious, philosophical or moral doctrine to which she adhere. In modern liberal democracies characterized by reasonable pluralism of comprehensive doctrines it is unjustified for political argumentation to be based on claims that many citizens can not accept. As I understand it, the point of idea of public reason is to strengthen the relationship of civic trust or civic friendship that can ensure inherent stability of just political regime. An important part of the idea of public reason is how it incorporates scientific claims in political argumentation. Rawls writes that citizens are to base their public justification on „presently accepted general beliefs and forms of reasoning found in common sense, and the methods and conclusions of science when those are not controversial.“ If the idea of public reason is the source of political stability it is necessary to answer what it means that conclusions of science are controversial in political and social context? First, scientific controversy is different from controversy of comprehensive doctrines. Science stands outside of comprehensive doctrines so conclusions of science will not be controversial because they clash with comprehensive beliefs, but they will be controversial if they rely on comprehensive beliefs. Second, if conclusions of science are controversial within scientific community, if there are some expert witness disputing its validity, then maybe value-judgments can enter to set standards for certification of the scientific claim. If potential consequences of scientific claim are bad for welfare of some group in society than standards of evidence that will certify this claim must go up. Finally, even if some scientific claim has been certified it still can be controversial as a premise in political justification. The reason can be that certification has not been transparent and many citizens do not realize that this claim is part of scientific consensus. Again, the criterion for controversy of scientific conclusions in political context is connected to the notion of trust and not to the validity of scientific claim or supportive evidence by itself.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2018-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49628201","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
Rivista di Estetica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1