首页 > 最新文献

Rivista di Estetica最新文献

英文 中文
The concept: a map for generations 其理念是:为几代人绘制地图
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5529
Snežana Vesnić, Miloš Ćipranić
The concept features as a vital element in architectural protocol and its vocabulary. If architecture and philosophy are defined as creation of concepts, then they are the terra nullius shared by both disciplines. By distinguishing the architectural concept from its philosophical counterpart, this paper analyzes the former as an entity that animates and directs a project as the documental prefiguration of an architectural object. In a more radical move, we consider architecture itself as a concept, that is, what makes architecture what it is and what this discipline can become tomorrow. In addition to decisively participating in the process of generating an object yet to be constructed (the fetus of a building), on a correlative level, the concept has an essential role in theoretical self-thematization of architecture and guards the future of the architectural profession as an autonomous intellectual discipline.
该概念是体系结构协议及其词汇表中的一个重要元素。如果建筑和哲学被定义为概念的创造,那么它们就是两个学科共同的无主之地。通过将建筑概念与哲学概念区分开来,本文分析了建筑概念作为一个实体,作为一个建筑对象的文献预设,对一个项目进行动画化和指导。更激进的做法是,我们将建筑本身视为一个概念,也就是说,是什么让建筑成为现在的样子,以及这门学科明天会变成什么样子。除了决定性地参与生成待建造对象(建筑的胎儿)的过程外,在相关层面上,这一概念在建筑的理论自主题化中发挥着重要作用,并作为一门自主的知识学科捍卫着建筑专业的未来。
{"title":"The concept: a map for generations","authors":"Snežana Vesnić, Miloš Ćipranić","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5529","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5529","url":null,"abstract":"The concept features as a vital element in architectural protocol and its vocabulary. If architecture and philosophy are defined as creation of concepts, then they are the terra nullius shared by both disciplines. By distinguishing the architectural concept from its philosophical counterpart, this paper analyzes the former as an entity that animates and directs a project as the documental prefiguration of an architectural object. In a more radical move, we consider architecture itself as a concept, that is, what makes architecture what it is and what this discipline can become tomorrow. In addition to decisively participating in the process of generating an object yet to be constructed (the fetus of a building), on a correlative level, the concept has an essential role in theoretical self-thematization of architecture and guards the future of the architectural profession as an autonomous intellectual discipline.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41980098","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Dar luogo a ciò che non ha luogo: utopia e prototyping 引发没有发生的事情:乌托邦和原型
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5576
R. Ríspoli, Ester Jordana Lluch
The purpose of this paper is to re-explore the relationship between utopia and architecture, trying first and foremost to challenge the way utopia has been conceived by architectural thought: i.e., as the prefiguration of a future seen as an ‘otherness’ distinct from the present, as far as the totality of its spatial, social, and political dimensions are concerned. Such vision – as we will argue – turns out to be deeply linked to a design logic of ‘projection’ and ‘prescription’; this, however, is not the only possible logic of design. Through a reflection upon some contemporary architectural practices, we will try to highlight a new horizon for design action, in which even utopia abandons its traditional ‘projective’ role and takes on a new meaning: rather than being the non-place of a possible future, utopia stands for what doesn’t have place in the present but can emerge from its alteration. Such notion of utopia as a form of ‘situated critique’, in a concrete space and time, helps to dig more deeply into the political potential of many contemporary forms of architectural and urban design.
本文的目的是重新探索乌托邦和建筑之间的关系,首先试图挑战建筑思想对乌托邦的设想方式:即,就其空间、社会和政治维度的整体而言,乌托邦是一个被视为与现在不同的“另类”的未来的预启。正如我们将要争论的那样,这种愿景与“投影”和“处方”的设计逻辑紧密相连;然而,这并不是设计的唯一可能逻辑。通过对一些当代建筑实践的反思,我们将试图突出一个设计行动的新视野,在这个视野中,即使是乌托邦也放弃了传统的“投射”角色,赋予了一种新的意义:乌托邦代表的不是一个可能的未来,而是一个在当下没有立足之地,但可以从它的改变中出现的东西。这种乌托邦概念作为一种“情境批判”形式,在具体的空间和时间中,有助于更深入地挖掘许多当代建筑和城市设计形式的政治潜力。
{"title":"Dar luogo a ciò che non ha luogo: utopia e prototyping","authors":"R. Ríspoli, Ester Jordana Lluch","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5576","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5576","url":null,"abstract":"The purpose of this paper is to re-explore the relationship between utopia and architecture, trying first and foremost to challenge the way utopia has been conceived by architectural thought: i.e., as the prefiguration of a future seen as an ‘otherness’ distinct from the present, as far as the totality of its spatial, social, and political dimensions are concerned. Such vision – as we will argue – turns out to be deeply linked to a design logic of ‘projection’ and ‘prescription’; this, however, is not the only possible logic of design. Through a reflection upon some contemporary architectural practices, we will try to highlight a new horizon for design action, in which even utopia abandons its traditional ‘projective’ role and takes on a new meaning: rather than being the non-place of a possible future, utopia stands for what doesn’t have place in the present but can emerge from its alteration. Such notion of utopia as a form of ‘situated critique’, in a concrete space and time, helps to dig more deeply into the political potential of many contemporary forms of architectural and urban design.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42339141","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Futuri anteriori: il tempo del progetto 上一篇期货:项目时间
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5481
G. Pasqui
In its "futural" use, the future perfect represents the past of the future. In the architectural and urban project, which imagines the future of cities and territories, a future perfect is always at stake: there is past in the future, there is future in the past. The project of a spatial transformation, always happening as a rupture in the temporal continuum, doesn't deploy an homogeneous and linear time, but rather a bundle of temporalities working according to different paces. In such a perspective the project has less to be meant as an image of a future state of the world, rather than an action orientation. The project can become an opening and a “social experimentation”, beyond the strictly technical and bureaucratic rationale, but also beyond the practice and market boundaries.
在“未来”的用法中,未来的完美代表了未来的过去。在设想城市和领土未来的建筑和城市项目中,未来的完美总是岌岌可危:未来中有过去,过去中有未来。空间变换的项目总是作为时间连续体的断裂而发生,它不是部署一个均匀的线性时间,而是根据不同的步伐工作的一束时间。从这样的角度来看,该项目与其说是世界未来状态的图像,不如说是行动导向。该项目可以成为一种开放和“社会实验”,超越严格的技术和官僚理论,也超越实践和市场边界。
{"title":"Futuri anteriori: il tempo del progetto","authors":"G. Pasqui","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5481","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5481","url":null,"abstract":"In its \"futural\" use, the future perfect represents the past of the future. In the architectural and urban project, which imagines the future of cities and territories, a future perfect is always at stake: there is past in the future, there is future in the past. The project of a spatial transformation, always happening as a rupture in the temporal continuum, doesn't deploy an homogeneous and linear time, but rather a bundle of temporalities working according to different paces. In such a perspective the project has less to be meant as an image of a future state of the world, rather than an action orientation. The project can become an opening and a “social experimentation”, beyond the strictly technical and bureaucratic rationale, but also beyond the practice and market boundaries.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48527310","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Designing a pension system 设计养老金制度
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.5747
V. Galasso
Designing a pension system is both a complex endeavor and a long lasting legacy. Complexity stems from the many trade-offs that conceiving a pension system entail and from how these initial decisions affect the social and economic behavioral responses of workers and retirees. Policy-makers planning a pension system have to evaluate its internal economic consistency, but also these feedbacks. Economic and demographic models that allow a quantitative evaluation of these costs and benefits are required. More than ever at the initial stage of design, since pension systems are persistent. Yet, pension systems are not monolith, but living entities that change over time. Some of these modifications are produced by individuals’ reactions to incentives built in the system, and need to be foreseen during the initial planning. Other changes are induced by reform measures and constitute the policy responses to unpredicted exogenous shocks – such as population aging. Re-designing the pension system to cope with new demands, while being limited by existing constraints, is a difficult task. Recent reforms of the Italian pension system are discussed in detail to highlight the policy trade-offs and the economic motivations behind the decision of the reform policies.
设计养老金制度既是一项复杂的工作,也是一项长期的遗产。复杂性源于设想养老金制度所需要的许多权衡,以及这些最初的决定如何影响工人和退休人员的社会和经济行为反应。计划养老金制度的政策制定者必须评估其内部经济一致性,但也要评估这些反馈。需要能够对这些成本和效益进行定量评价的经济和人口模型。在设计的初始阶段比以往任何时候都要多,因为养老金制度是持久的。然而,养老金制度并不是一成不变的,而是随着时间而变化的活生生的实体。其中一些修改是由个人对系统内置激励的反应产生的,需要在最初的计划中加以预见。其他变化是由改革措施引起的,并构成了对不可预测的外部冲击(如人口老龄化)的政策反应。重新设计养老金制度以应对新的需求,同时又受到现有制约因素的限制,是一项艰巨的任务。本文详细讨论了意大利养老金制度最近的改革,以突出政策权衡和改革政策决策背后的经济动机。
{"title":"Designing a pension system","authors":"V. Galasso","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.5747","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.5747","url":null,"abstract":"Designing a pension system is both a complex endeavor and a long lasting legacy. Complexity stems from the many trade-offs that conceiving a pension system entail and from how these initial decisions affect the social and economic behavioral responses of workers and retirees. Policy-makers planning a pension system have to evaluate its internal economic consistency, but also these feedbacks. Economic and demographic models that allow a quantitative evaluation of these costs and benefits are required. More than ever at the initial stage of design, since pension systems are persistent. Yet, pension systems are not monolith, but living entities that change over time. Some of these modifications are produced by individuals’ reactions to incentives built in the system, and need to be foreseen during the initial planning. Other changes are induced by reform measures and constitute the policy responses to unpredicted exogenous shocks – such as population aging. Re-designing the pension system to cope with new demands, while being limited by existing constraints, is a difficult task. Recent reforms of the Italian pension system are discussed in detail to highlight the policy trade-offs and the economic motivations behind the decision of the reform policies.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47525397","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The acts of project(ion) / project acts or projacts 项目的行为/项目行为或项目
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5521
P. Bojanić
I am interested in the epistemological status of «project(ion)», that is, the «act» or «strategy» of project(ion) in relation to various didactic protocols usually associated with an «author» and her intention or production. What is a plan, program, plot, platform, concept, conception, or even «meta-project»? Is a project or projection necessarily an «architectural matter»? Is it a prototypically Western or European procedure of specific use of time and space (literally, throwing forth into space/time)? I will attempt to explain some passages from Eisenman, Cacciari, as well as a theory recently put forth by Armando and Durbiano (Teoria del progetto architettonico).
我对“项目”的认识论地位感兴趣,也就是说,项目的“行为”或“策略”与通常与“作者”及其意图或生产相关的各种教学协议有关。什么是计划、程序、情节、平台、概念、构想,甚至是“元项目”?一个项目或投影一定是一个“建筑问题”吗?它是一种典型的西方或欧洲对时间和空间的特定使用程序(字面上,扔进空间/时间)吗?我将尝试解释艾森曼、卡西亚里的一些段落,以及阿曼多和德比亚诺最近提出的一个理论(Teoria del progetto architettonico)。
{"title":"The acts of project(ion) / project acts or projacts","authors":"P. Bojanić","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5521","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5521","url":null,"abstract":"I am interested in the epistemological status of «project(ion)», that is, the «act» or «strategy» of project(ion) in relation to various didactic protocols usually associated with an «author» and her intention or production. What is a plan, program, plot, platform, concept, conception, or even «meta-project»? Is a project or projection necessarily an «architectural matter»? Is it a prototypically Western or European procedure of specific use of time and space (literally, throwing forth into space/time)? I will attempt to explain some passages from Eisenman, Cacciari, as well as a theory recently put forth by Armando and Durbiano (Teoria del progetto architettonico).","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48070068","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Filosofia e progetto. Breve storia di una vicenda attuale 哲学与设计。当前事件的简史
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5549
Edoardo Fregonese
italianoIn questo articolo si delinea la costituzione di un campo disciplinare che prende il nome di ‘filosofia del progetto’. La radici di questo settore filosofico possono essere rintracciate in una delle prime considerazione teoriche intorno alle “scienze dell’artificiale” (Simon 1996 [1969]) – che in opposizione alle scienze della natura dovrebbero occuparsi delle entita non-naturali che popolano il nostro mondo, cioe gli artefatti. Tali considerazioni sono state poi ampliate e discusse a partire da un programma di ricerca indirizzato a un cambio di rotta all’interno della filosofia della tecnologia: la cosiddetta “svolta empirica in filosofia della tecnologia” (Kroes & Meijers 2000). A seguito di cio due questioni negli anni successivi sono state dibattute: la prima e legata alla definizione di ‘progetto’ e alle domande filosofiche che sorgono (come il problema del riferimento dei termini progettuali e il loro valore di verita); la seconda e un problema di demarcazione fra scienza e progetto (sono queste due attivita identiche o differenti?). Scopo dell’articolo e presentare una rassegna del dibattito mostrando alcuni possibili sviluppi futuri per la filosofia del progetto. EnglishThis article outlines the constitution of a disciplinary field called ‘philosophy of design’. The roots of this philosophical branch can be traced back to the one of the first theoretical consideration about the “sciences of the artificial” (Simon 1996 [1969]) – which in opposition to natural sciences should deal with non-natural entities which populates our world, namely artifacts. These considerations have been extended and discussed starting from a research program aimed at changing the route within philosophy of technology: the so called “empirical turn in philosophy of technology” (Kroes, Meijers 2000). Following this, two issues have been debated in the subsequent years: the first is related to the definition of ‘design’ and to the philosophical questions that arise (like the reference of design terms and their truth-value); the second is a problem of demarcation between science and design (are these two activities different?). The aim of the article is presenting an overview of the debate and showing some possible future developments for the philosophy of design.
意大利这篇文章概述了一个以“项目哲学”为名的学科领域的构成。这一哲学领域的根源可以追溯到围绕“人工科学”(Simon 1996[1969])的最早理论考虑之一——与自然科学相反,人工科学应该处理我们世界中的非自然实体,即人工制品。然后,在一项旨在改变技术哲学路线的研究计划的基础上,对这些考虑进行了扩展和讨论:所谓的“技术哲学的经验转折点”(Kroes&Meijers,2000年)。因此,在接下来的几年里,人们对两个问题进行了辩论:第一个问题与“项目”的定义和出现的哲学问题有关(例如设计术语的参考及其真理价值的问题);第二个问题是科学和设计之间的界限问题(这两种活动是相同的还是不同的?)。这篇文章的目的是对辩论进行回顾,展示该项目哲学的一些可能的未来发展。这篇文章概述了一个叫做“设计哲学”的学科领域的构成。这一哲学分支的根源可以追溯到关于“人造科学”的第一次理论思考(Simon 1996[1969])——与自然科学相反,它应该处理充斥我们世界的非自然实体,即人工制品。从一个旨在改变技术哲学路线的研究项目开始,这些考虑因素得到了扩展和讨论:所谓的“技术哲学的实证转向”(Kroes,Meijers 2000)。在此之后,在接下来的几年里,有两个问题进行了辩论:第一个问题与“设计”的定义和出现的哲学问题有关(如设计术语的引用及其真实价值);第二个问题是科学和设计之间的界限问题(这两种活动不同吗?)。这篇文章的目的是概述这场争论,并展示设计哲学未来可能的发展。
{"title":"Filosofia e progetto. Breve storia di una vicenda attuale","authors":"Edoardo Fregonese","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5549","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5549","url":null,"abstract":"italianoIn questo articolo si delinea la costituzione di un campo disciplinare che prende il nome di ‘filosofia del progetto’. La radici di questo settore filosofico possono essere rintracciate in una delle prime considerazione teoriche intorno alle “scienze dell’artificiale” (Simon 1996 [1969]) – che in opposizione alle scienze della natura dovrebbero occuparsi delle entita non-naturali che popolano il nostro mondo, cioe gli artefatti. Tali considerazioni sono state poi ampliate e discusse a partire da un programma di ricerca indirizzato a un cambio di rotta all’interno della filosofia della tecnologia: la cosiddetta “svolta empirica in filosofia della tecnologia” (Kroes & Meijers 2000). A seguito di cio due questioni negli anni successivi sono state dibattute: la prima e legata alla definizione di ‘progetto’ e alle domande filosofiche che sorgono (come il problema del riferimento dei termini progettuali e il loro valore di verita); la seconda e un problema di demarcazione fra scienza e progetto (sono queste due attivita identiche o differenti?). Scopo dell’articolo e presentare una rassegna del dibattito mostrando alcuni possibili sviluppi futuri per la filosofia del progetto. EnglishThis article outlines the constitution of a disciplinary field called ‘philosophy of design’. The roots of this philosophical branch can be traced back to the one of the first theoretical consideration about the “sciences of the artificial” (Simon 1996 [1969]) – which in opposition to natural sciences should deal with non-natural entities which populates our world, namely artifacts. These considerations have been extended and discussed starting from a research program aimed at changing the route within philosophy of technology: the so called “empirical turn in philosophy of technology” (Kroes, Meijers 2000). Following this, two issues have been debated in the subsequent years: the first is related to the definition of ‘design’ and to the philosophical questions that arise (like the reference of design terms and their truth-value); the second is a problem of demarcation between science and design (are these two activities different?). The aim of the article is presenting an overview of the debate and showing some possible future developments for the philosophy of design.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43242127","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Engaging with works of fiction 阅读小说
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-04-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5170
W. Huemer
The contemporary debate in the philosophy of literature is strongly shaped by the anti-cognitivist challenge, according to which works of literary fiction (that contain propositions that are neither literally true nor affirmed by the author) cannot impart (relevant) knowledge to the readers or enrich their worldly understanding. Anti-cognitivists appreciate works of literary fiction for their aesthetic values and so risk to reduce them to mere ornaments that are entertaining, but eventually useless. Many philosophers have reacted to this challenge by pointing at ways in which works of literary fiction can be informative even though they lack worldly reference: it has been argued, for example, that fictions work like thought experiments; that they add not to our theoretical knowledge, but to our know-how or to our phenomenal knowledge; or that that they help readers to understand the perspectives of others. A stubborn defense of literary cognitivism, however, risks to collapse into an instrumental understanding of literature. In my paper I will suggest that both sides in the debate focus too narrowly on semantic features of the works in question that are tied to what I will call the “referential picture” of language. A shift of perspective is needed: for one, we ought to fully appreciate that the term “literature” does not refer to a homogeneous phenomenon, but rather to a very heterogeneous and multifarious set of works that are read by many different readers for many different reasons in many different ways. Second, we need to understand that these works have in common much more than the semantic peculiarity of lacking worldly reference: they are a unique means of communication between authors and readers – and in particular the role of the latter is often neglected in contemporary debate. These two points should help us to get a more comprehensive understanding of the practice of literature and the vast range of values we can find in works of literary fiction – and the interplay between them.
当代文学哲学的争论受到反认知主义挑战的强烈影响,根据这种挑战,文学小说作品(包含的命题既不是字面上正确的,也不是作者肯定的)不能向读者传授(相关的)知识,也不能丰富他们的世俗理解。反认知主义者欣赏文学小说作品的审美价值,因此冒险将其简化为纯粹的娱乐装饰,但最终毫无用处。许多哲学家对这一挑战作出了回应,指出文学小说作品在缺乏世俗参考的情况下也能提供信息:例如,有人认为,小说就像思想实验;它们不是增加我们的理论知识,而是增加我们的实际知识或现象知识;或者他们帮助读者理解他人的观点。然而,对文学认知主义的顽固辩护有可能崩溃为对文学的工具性理解。在我的论文中,我将提出,辩论双方都过于狭隘地关注所讨论作品的语义特征,这些特征与我所说的语言的“参考图片”有关。我们需要换个角度:首先,我们应该充分认识到,“文学”一词并不是指一种同质的现象,而是指一组非常异质和多样化的作品,这些作品被许多不同的读者出于许多不同的原因以许多不同的方式阅读。其次,我们需要明白,这些作品的共同点远远超过缺乏世俗参考的语义特性:它们是作者和读者之间沟通的独特手段——尤其是后者的作用在当代辩论中经常被忽视。这两点应该有助于我们更全面地理解文学实践和我们可以在文学小说作品中找到的广泛价值,以及它们之间的相互作用。
{"title":"Engaging with works of fiction","authors":"W. Huemer","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5170","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5170","url":null,"abstract":"The contemporary debate in the philosophy of literature is strongly shaped by the anti-cognitivist challenge, according to which works of literary fiction (that contain propositions that are neither literally true nor affirmed by the author) cannot impart (relevant) knowledge to the readers or enrich their worldly understanding. Anti-cognitivists appreciate works of literary fiction for their aesthetic values and so risk to reduce them to mere ornaments that are entertaining, but eventually useless. Many philosophers have reacted to this challenge by pointing at ways in which works of literary fiction can be informative even though they lack worldly reference: it has been argued, for example, that fictions work like thought experiments; that they add not to our theoretical knowledge, but to our know-how or to our phenomenal knowledge; or that that they help readers to understand the perspectives of others. A stubborn defense of literary cognitivism, however, risks to collapse into an instrumental understanding of literature. In my paper I will suggest that both sides in the debate focus too narrowly on semantic features of the works in question that are tied to what I will call the “referential picture” of language. A shift of perspective is needed: for one, we ought to fully appreciate that the term “literature” does not refer to a homogeneous phenomenon, but rather to a very heterogeneous and multifarious set of works that are read by many different readers for many different reasons in many different ways. Second, we need to understand that these works have in common much more than the semantic peculiarity of lacking worldly reference: they are a unique means of communication between authors and readers – and in particular the role of the latter is often neglected in contemporary debate. These two points should help us to get a more comprehensive understanding of the practice of literature and the vast range of values we can find in works of literary fiction – and the interplay between them.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42157657","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Natura multimodale e creatività del linguaggio poetico 诗歌语言的多模态性与创造性
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-04-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5125
Francesca Ervas
The exceptional nature of poetic language – testified by its patent untranslatability – represents a problem for philosophy, and particularly for analytic philosophy, which aims to provide an overarching explanation of ordinary language. It is difficult to explain the peculiar creativity of poetic language, starting from a finite basic vocabulary and a finite set of rules to be used by an interpreter who has finite powers. Poetry seems indeed not to respect the semantic innocence, spreading new meanings not only according to the context, but even to the graphic and phonological form of the words. Mechanisms, such as quotation and conversational implicatures, have been used to respect semantic innocence and to show at the same time that poetic language is not deviant from the ordinary use of language. This article suggests an alternative route, “imagistic”, to account for the specific creativity of poetic language, without violating the principle of semantic innocence and without hypothesizing a discontinuity with ordinary language. Particularly referring to metaphor, it aims to show that poetic language does not convey as much further meanings, implicit in the use of literal terms, but rather images, evoked by and dependent on these terms, which could explain both poetry emergent properties and untranslatability. “Imageability” is not a feature of the “poetic word”, but rather of any word and, particularly, of concrete words. The creativity of poetic language lies in deepening the multimodal nature of concrete language, which is different from the abstract and conceptual nature of philosophical language.
诗歌语言的特殊性——其专利的不可翻译性证明了这一点——代表了哲学的一个问题,尤其是分析哲学,它旨在为普通语言提供全面的解释。从一个有限的基本词汇和一套有限的规则开始,很难解释诗歌语言的独特创造力,而这些规则是由一个拥有有限能力的口译员使用的。诗歌似乎确实不尊重语义的天真,不仅根据上下文,甚至根据单词的图形和语音形式传播新的含义。引用和会话含义等机制被用来尊重语义的无辜,同时表明诗歌语言并没有偏离语言的正常使用。本文提出了一种替代途径,即“意象主义”,以解释诗歌语言的特定创造性,而不违反语义无辜原则,也不假设与普通语言的不连续性。特别是在隐喻方面,它旨在表明诗歌语言并没有传达更多隐含在字面术语使用中的意义,而是传达由这些术语唤起并依赖于这些术语的图像,这些图像可以解释诗歌的涌现特性和不可译性。“可想象性”不是“诗意的词”的特征,而是任何词的特征,尤其是具体词的特征。诗歌语言的创造性在于深化具体语言的多模态性,这与哲学语言的抽象性和概念性不同。
{"title":"Natura multimodale e creatività del linguaggio poetico","authors":"Francesca Ervas","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5125","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5125","url":null,"abstract":"The exceptional nature of poetic language – testified by its patent untranslatability – represents a problem for philosophy, and particularly for analytic philosophy, which aims to provide an overarching explanation of ordinary language. It is difficult to explain the peculiar creativity of poetic language, starting from a finite basic vocabulary and a finite set of rules to be used by an interpreter who has finite powers. Poetry seems indeed not to respect the semantic innocence, spreading new meanings not only according to the context, but even to the graphic and phonological form of the words. Mechanisms, such as quotation and conversational implicatures, have been used to respect semantic innocence and to show at the same time that poetic language is not deviant from the ordinary use of language. This article suggests an alternative route, “imagistic”, to account for the specific creativity of poetic language, without violating the principle of semantic innocence and without hypothesizing a discontinuity with ordinary language. Particularly referring to metaphor, it aims to show that poetic language does not convey as much further meanings, implicit in the use of literal terms, but rather images, evoked by and dependent on these terms, which could explain both poetry emergent properties and untranslatability. “Imageability” is not a feature of the “poetic word”, but rather of any word and, particularly, of concrete words. The creativity of poetic language lies in deepening the multimodal nature of concrete language, which is different from the abstract and conceptual nature of philosophical language.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47318638","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Incomprensibilità e ironia. Filosofia e letteratura in Friedrich Schlegel e Paul de Man 无法理解且具有讽刺意味。施莱格尔与德曼的哲学与文学
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-04-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5045
M. Cometa
The philosophy of irony has had, since its romantic origins, no good reputation because of its methodological and logical inconclusiveness and its contamination with literature. Whether we talk about Friedrich Schlegel or Paul de Man, about Soren Kierkegaard or Friedrich Nietzsche, Richard Rorty or Peter Sloterdijk, the “ironists” are hated because of their ability to say, even on the verge of death: “however”. The charge that philosophy makes against ironists is based on three “suspicions”: 1) that they are not philosophically consistent and, therefore, that they, ultimately, do not know how to ironize themselves; 2) that their irony is only a disguised “egology”, as Hegel would claim and assumes literary forms; 3) finally that they are vitiated by a sort of anthropological “lack of commitment”, or – as Rorty would say – a “lack of solidarity”, and, therefore, they are quite often ineffective and even harmful from a social and political point of view. In the following pages I will try to dissolve these “suspicions” through a close and “ironic” reading of two texts that belong to this tradition of cultural (not only literary) analysis, telling the story of an elective affinity between two emblematic thinkers: Friedrich Schlegel and Paul de Man.
反讽哲学自其浪漫起源以来,由于其方法论和逻辑上的不确定性以及与文学的沾染,一直没有什么好名声。无论我们谈论的是弗里德里希·施莱格尔还是保罗·德曼,是索伦·克尔凯郭尔还是弗里德里希·尼采,是理查德·罗蒂还是彼得·斯洛特戴克,“讽刺家”都是令人讨厌的,因为他们即使在死亡边缘也能说:“然而”。哲学对讽刺家的指控是基于三个“怀疑”:1)他们在哲学上不一致,因此,他们最终不知道如何讽刺自己;(2)他们的反讽只是一种伪装的“自我论”,正如黑格尔所主张的那样,并采用了文学形式;3)最后,它们被一种人类学上的“缺乏承诺”所破坏,或者——正如罗蒂所说——“缺乏团结”,因此,从社会和政治的角度来看,它们往往是无效的,甚至是有害的。在接下来的几页中,我将试图通过对两篇属于这种文化(不仅仅是文学)分析传统的文本的密切和“讽刺”的阅读来消除这些“怀疑”,讲述弗里德里希·施莱格尔和保罗·德曼这两位象征性思想家之间的选择性亲和力的故事。
{"title":"Incomprensibilità e ironia. Filosofia e letteratura in Friedrich Schlegel e Paul de Man","authors":"M. Cometa","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5045","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5045","url":null,"abstract":"The philosophy of irony has had, since its romantic origins, no good reputation because of its methodological and logical inconclusiveness and its contamination with literature. Whether we talk about Friedrich Schlegel or Paul de Man, about Soren Kierkegaard or Friedrich Nietzsche, Richard Rorty or Peter Sloterdijk, the “ironists” are hated because of their ability to say, even on the verge of death: “however”. The charge that philosophy makes against ironists is based on three “suspicions”: 1) that they are not philosophically consistent and, therefore, that they, ultimately, do not know how to ironize themselves; 2) that their irony is only a disguised “egology”, as Hegel would claim and assumes literary forms; 3) finally that they are vitiated by a sort of anthropological “lack of commitment”, or – as Rorty would say – a “lack of solidarity”, and, therefore, they are quite often ineffective and even harmful from a social and political point of view. In the following pages I will try to dissolve these “suspicions” through a close and “ironic” reading of two texts that belong to this tradition of cultural (not only literary) analysis, telling the story of an elective affinity between two emblematic thinkers: Friedrich Schlegel and Paul de Man.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43025439","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Patrick Hayes and Jan Wilm, Beyond the Ancient Quarrel. Literature, Philosophy, and J.M. Coetzee 帕特里克·海斯和简·威尔姆,《超越古老的争吵》文学、哲学和J.M.库切
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2019-04-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.5270
Viviana Vozzo
Sebbene la ricchezza espressiva e la versatilita della scrittura di J.M. Coetzee si prestino ad una varieta di studi e considerazioni che riescono a coinvolgere molteplici discipline, solo i saggi che compongono il presente volume si impongono come un primo importante studio volto a comprendere, in maniera piu sistematica, l’ampia pluralita di voci che caratterizza la critica coetziana. Il volume, dunque, riesce a superare le analisi meramente settoriali e unilaterali perche, cogliendo le pro...
尽管J·M·库切作品表现力的丰富性和多样性有助于进行涉及多个学科的各种研究和思考,但只有撰写本卷的文章才将自己视为第一个重要的研究,旨在以更系统的方式理解库切批评的广泛多样性。因此,该卷成功地克服了纯粹的部门和单方面分析,因为抓住了优势。。。
{"title":"Patrick Hayes and Jan Wilm, Beyond the Ancient Quarrel. Literature, Philosophy, and J.M. Coetzee","authors":"Viviana Vozzo","doi":"10.4000/estetica.5270","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.5270","url":null,"abstract":"Sebbene la ricchezza espressiva e la versatilita della scrittura di J.M. Coetzee si prestino ad una varieta di studi e considerazioni che riescono a coinvolgere molteplici discipline, solo i saggi che compongono il presente volume si impongono come un primo importante studio volto a comprendere, in maniera piu sistematica, l’ampia pluralita di voci che caratterizza la critica coetziana. Il volume, dunque, riesce a superare le analisi meramente settoriali e unilaterali perche, cogliendo le pro...","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2019-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49123703","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Rivista di Estetica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1