首页 > 最新文献

Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association最新文献

英文 中文
American Catholic Philosophical Association Secretary’s Report (2020) 美国天主教哲学协会秘书长报告(2020)
Pub Date : 2020-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/acpaproc202094146
{"title":"American Catholic Philosophical Association Secretary’s Report (2020)","authors":"","doi":"10.5840/acpaproc202094146","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/acpaproc202094146","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71107610","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Perennial Symmetry Arguments: Aristotle’s Heavenly Cosmology and Noether’s First Theorem 常年对称论证:亚里士多德的天堂宇宙论和诺特第一定理
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/ACPAPROC2021427121
Ryan Miller
Attempts to find perennial elements in Aristotle’s cosmology are doomed to failure because his distinction of sub- and supra-lunary realms no longer holds. More fruitful approaches to the contemporary importance of Aristotelian cosmology must focus on parities of reasoning rather than content. This paper highlights the striking parallels between Aristotle’s use of symmetry arguments in cosmology and instances of Noether’s First Theorem in contemporary physics. Both observe simple motion, find symmetries in that motion, argue from those symmetries to notions of conservation, and then conclude to cosmological structure. These parallels reveal an enduring relevance for Aristotelian cosmology that does not depend on positing an enduring content to his cosmological claims.
试图在亚里士多德的宇宙学中找到永恒的元素是注定要失败的,因为他对亚月和超月领域的区分不再成立。对亚里士多德宇宙论的当代重要性来说,更富有成效的方法必须关注推理的对等性,而不是内容。本文强调了亚里士多德在宇宙学中使用对称论证与当代物理学中诺特第一定理实例之间惊人的相似之处。两者都观察简单的运动,发现运动中的对称性,从这些对称性推导出守恒的概念,然后得出宇宙结构的结论。这些相似之处揭示了亚里士多德宇宙论的持久相关性,它并不依赖于为他的宇宙论主张设定持久的内容。
{"title":"Perennial Symmetry Arguments: Aristotle’s Heavenly Cosmology and Noether’s First Theorem","authors":"Ryan Miller","doi":"10.5840/ACPAPROC2021427121","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/ACPAPROC2021427121","url":null,"abstract":"Attempts to find perennial elements in Aristotle’s cosmology are doomed to failure because his distinction of sub- and supra-lunary realms no longer holds. More fruitful approaches to the contemporary importance of Aristotelian cosmology must focus on parities of reasoning rather than content. This paper highlights the striking parallels between Aristotle’s use of symmetry arguments in cosmology and instances of Noether’s First Theorem in contemporary physics. Both observe simple motion, find symmetries in that motion, argue from those symmetries to notions of conservation, and then conclude to cosmological structure. These parallels reveal an enduring relevance for Aristotelian cosmology that does not depend on positing an enduring content to his cosmological claims.","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71108103","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Perennial Theology of Nature 永恒的自然神学
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/ACPAPROC202161130
Anselm Ramelow
However much scientific paradigms shift, the shifts are not so arbitrary that we would relinquish without need the simpler, more economic and elegant theories for more complicated ones. This is not just a matter of convenience but implies an objective fact about the universe, namely a reliable perfection that can only be assumed on the basis of the intelligent design of a benevolent creator God. Earlier thinkers may have been more aware that this is an assumption (e.g., Kant) and presupposes God’s benevolent intentions (Leibniz). This assumption of a unified order of reality in general constitutes itself a perennial consensus through the ages, whether in Aquinas, Leibniz, the German Idealists or American Transcendentalists. Dissenters such as William James or Nietzsche serve to highlight the assumption as theological—an assumption that is fortunately confirmed by our best available evidence, as well as by the way we do science and live our lives.
无论科学范式发生了多大的转变,这种转变都不会武断到我们不需要用更简单、更经济、更优雅的理论来代替更复杂的理论就放弃的地步。这不仅是一个方便的问题,而且暗示了一个关于宇宙的客观事实,即一个可靠的完美,只能在仁慈的造物主上帝的智能设计的基础上假设。早期的思想家可能已经意识到这是一个假设(例如,康德),并预设了上帝的仁慈意图(莱布尼茨)。无论是在阿奎那、莱布尼茨、德国唯心主义者还是美国先验主义者那里,这种对现实的统一秩序的假设本身构成了一个历久弥新的共识。威廉·詹姆斯和尼采等持不同政见者强调了这一假设的神学性——幸运的是,这一假设得到了我们最好的证据的证实,也得到了我们从事科学研究和生活方式的证实。
{"title":"A Perennial Theology of Nature","authors":"Anselm Ramelow","doi":"10.5840/ACPAPROC202161130","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/ACPAPROC202161130","url":null,"abstract":"However much scientific paradigms shift, the shifts are not so arbitrary that we would relinquish without need the simpler, more economic and elegant theories for more complicated ones. This is not just a matter of convenience but implies an objective fact about the universe, namely a reliable perfection that can only be assumed on the basis of the intelligent design of a benevolent creator God. Earlier thinkers may have been more aware that this is an assumption (e.g., Kant) and presupposes God’s benevolent intentions (Leibniz). This assumption of a unified order of reality in general constitutes itself a perennial consensus through the ages, whether in Aquinas, Leibniz, the German Idealists or American Transcendentalists. Dissenters such as William James or Nietzsche serve to highlight the assumption as theological—an assumption that is fortunately confirmed by our best available evidence, as well as by the way we do science and live our lives.","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71108130","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Defense of the Distinction Between Plants and Animals 为植物和动物的区别辩护
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/ACPAPROC2021426117
Marie George
Aristotle’s division of living things into three categories has been challenged of late as to the distinction between plants and animals on the grounds that plants too are sentient. I argue that the life activities that plants carry on go on in us without sentience and would not be carried on any better with sentience, and thus are reasonably thought to go in plants in a non-sentient manner. Complementing this expectation is the fact that research on the various movements of plants accounts for them without reference to sensation, but rather by specifying various physical causes. I also show that certain proponents of plant sentience engage in faulty reasoning, including the fallacy of the accident (e.g., the plant responds to something having a quality that a sentient being would sense; therefore it senses) and equivocation (e.g., plants sense different external cues; therefore they are sentient).
亚里士多德将生物分为三类的观点近来在植物和动物的区别上受到了挑战,因为植物也有知觉。我认为植物进行的生命活动在我们没有知觉的情况下仍在进行,如果有知觉也不会进行得更好,因此可以合理地认为植物以无知觉的方式进行。与这一预期相辅相成的是,对植物各种运动的研究没有涉及到感觉,而是通过指定各种物理原因来解释它们。我还指出,植物感知能力的某些支持者进行了错误的推理,包括事故谬论(例如,植物对具有感知能力的事物做出反应;因此,它感觉)和模棱两可(例如,植物感觉不同的外部线索;因此他们是有知觉的)。
{"title":"A Defense of the Distinction Between Plants and Animals","authors":"Marie George","doi":"10.5840/ACPAPROC2021426117","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/ACPAPROC2021426117","url":null,"abstract":"Aristotle’s division of living things into three categories has been challenged of late as to the distinction between plants and animals on the grounds that plants too are sentient. I argue that the life activities that plants carry on go on in us without sentience and would not be carried on any better with sentience, and thus are reasonably thought to go in plants in a non-sentient manner. Complementing this expectation is the fact that research on the various movements of plants accounts for them without reference to sensation, but rather by specifying various physical causes. I also show that certain proponents of plant sentience engage in faulty reasoning, including the fallacy of the accident (e.g., the plant responds to something having a quality that a sentient being would sense; therefore it senses) and equivocation (e.g., plants sense different external cues; therefore they are sentient).","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71107736","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Aquinas the Avicennian: Prologue to the Commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics 阿维森纳主义者阿奎那:亚里士多德形而上学评注序言
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/ACPAPROC2021428122
R. E. Houser
{"title":"Aquinas the Avicennian: Prologue to the Commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics","authors":"R. E. Houser","doi":"10.5840/ACPAPROC2021428122","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/ACPAPROC2021428122","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71107876","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Significance of Hylomorphism 同形性的意义
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/ACPAPROC2021429124
J. D. Groot
Hylomorphism is a word for Aristotle’s belief that matter and form constitute a unity in natural things. Engaging with the work of Rémi Brague on the cosmos, I propose hylomorphism as central to the contemporary philosophy of nature that Brague seeks. Between the pre-philosophical standpoint and philosophy, there is an intermediate cognitive stage of making initial distinctions that ground philosophical truths. Philosophy of nature is the home of many of these initial distinctions. A key theme introduced in Physics 2.2 is the thinking of things in the way they are capable of existing. Analyses of Physics 2.2. and De Anima 2.3 exhibit the recognition of being as something different from the sheer existing of things. Aristotle points out mistakes in thinking about form and elucidates ontological dependencies. There are implications for the understanding of human disability.
合形说是亚里士多德的一个词,他认为物质和形式构成了自然事物的统一。通过研究拉马米·布拉格关于宇宙的著作,我提出,形同论是布拉格所寻求的当代自然哲学的核心。在前哲学立场和哲学之间,有一个中间的认知阶段,这个阶段是对哲学真理进行初步区分的基础。自然哲学是许多这些最初区别的发源地。物理学2.2中引入的一个关键主题是以事物能够存在的方式来思考事物。物理分析2.2。和《论阿尼玛》第2.3章,都承认存在是不同于事物的纯粹存在的东西。亚里士多德指出了形式思维的错误,并阐明了本体论的依赖性。这对理解人类的残疾有启示。
{"title":"The Significance of Hylomorphism","authors":"J. D. Groot","doi":"10.5840/ACPAPROC2021429124","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/ACPAPROC2021429124","url":null,"abstract":"Hylomorphism is a word for Aristotle’s belief that matter and form constitute a unity in natural things. Engaging with the work of Rémi Brague on the cosmos, I propose hylomorphism as central to the contemporary philosophy of nature that Brague seeks. Between the pre-philosophical standpoint and philosophy, there is an intermediate cognitive stage of making initial distinctions that ground philosophical truths. Philosophy of nature is the home of many of these initial distinctions. A key theme introduced in Physics 2.2 is the thinking of things in the way they are capable of existing. Analyses of Physics 2.2. and De Anima 2.3 exhibit the recognition of being as something different from the sheer existing of things. Aristotle points out mistakes in thinking about form and elucidates ontological dependencies. There are implications for the understanding of human disability.","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71107899","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Secretary’s Report (2019) 秘书报告(2019年)
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/acpaproc201993131
{"title":"Secretary’s Report (2019)","authors":"","doi":"10.5840/acpaproc201993131","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/acpaproc201993131","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71107445","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Generation and Homonymy in Aristotle’s Generation of Animals 亚里士多德《动物的世代》中的世代与同义
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/ACPAPROC2021428123
Ignacio de Ribera-Martin
Discussions on Aristotle’s account of homonymy in natural philosophy have not paid attention to its distinct use in the Generation of animals. I show that Aristotle’s use of homonymy in this treatise is relevant to the question of how to name living substances in the process of generation. In the GA, Aristotle uses homonymy to argue that embryos must have soul. These embryos, when the heart has been distinctly set apart, satisfy the criterion set in Metaph. IX.7 to be an animal in dunamis. In the GA, Aristotle refers to this embryo as an animal—albeit incomplete, because it cannot yet carry out all the functions signified by the name—and not as a homonym. The phenomenon of generation thus calls for a refinement of the principle of Functional Determination, according to which something is what its names signifies only if it can carry out the functions signified by the name.
讨论亚里士多德在自然哲学中关于同义性的论述时,并没有注意到它在《动物的产生》中的独特用法。我表明亚里士多德在这篇论文中使用同音异义是与如何在生成过程中命名生命物质的问题相关的。在GA中,亚里士多德用同音异义来论证胚胎必须有灵魂。这些胚胎,当心脏被明显地分离出来时,满足《元图》中设定的标准。在dunamis里做一只动物。亚里士多德把这个胚胎称为动物——尽管不完整,因为它还不能完成名字所代表的所有功能——而不是一个同音异义词。因此,产生现象要求我们对功能决定原则加以改进。根据功能决定原则,只有当某物能够实现其名称所表示的功能时,它才是其名称所表示的东西。
{"title":"Generation and Homonymy in Aristotle’s Generation of Animals","authors":"Ignacio de Ribera-Martin","doi":"10.5840/ACPAPROC2021428123","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/ACPAPROC2021428123","url":null,"abstract":"Discussions on Aristotle’s account of homonymy in natural philosophy have not paid attention to its distinct use in the Generation of animals. I show that Aristotle’s use of homonymy in this treatise is relevant to the question of how to name living substances in the process of generation. In the GA, Aristotle uses homonymy to argue that embryos must have soul. These embryos, when the heart has been distinctly set apart, satisfy the criterion set in Metaph. IX.7 to be an animal in dunamis. In the GA, Aristotle refers to this embryo as an animal—albeit incomplete, because it cannot yet carry out all the functions signified by the name—and not as a homonym. The phenomenon of generation thus calls for a refinement of the principle of Functional Determination, according to which something is what its names signifies only if it can carry out the functions signified by the name.","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71107890","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
“In As Many Ways As Something Is Predicated . . . in That Many Ways Is Something Signified to Be” “以尽可能多的方式来预测某事……”某种东西在很多方面都意味着存在。”
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/ACPAPROC2021429125
E. Polsky
Thomistic commentators agree that Thomas Aquinas at least nominally allows for “to be” (esse) to signify not only an act contrasted with essence in creatures, but also the essence itself of those creatures. Nevertheless, it is almost unheard of for any author to interpret Thomas’s use of the word “esse” as referring to essence. Against this tendency, this paper argues that Thomas’s In V Metaphysics argument that every predication signifies esse provides an important instance of Thomas using “esse” to signify essence. This reading of In V Metaphysics, which this paper defends against Gyula Klima’s alternative interpretation, suggests significant reinterpretations of Thomas’s technical terms “esse substantiale” and “esse in rerum natura” as well as Thomas’s use of “is,” both as a copula and as a principal predicate.
托马斯主义评论家同意托马斯·阿奎那至少在名义上允许“存在”(esse)不仅表示与生物本质相对的行为,而且表示这些生物的本质本身。然而,这几乎是闻所未闻的任何作者解释托马斯的使用词“esse”指的是本质。针对这一倾向,本文认为托马斯在《形而上学第五篇》中关于每一个预言都意味着本质的论证,是托马斯用“本质”来表示本质的一个重要例证。在第五篇《形而上学》中,本文对Gyula Klima的替代解释进行了辩护,这表明了对托马斯的专业术语“本质”和“本质自然”的重要重新解释,以及托马斯对“是”的使用,既是一个联系词,也是一个主要谓词。
{"title":"“In As Many Ways As Something Is Predicated . . . in That Many Ways Is Something Signified to Be”","authors":"E. Polsky","doi":"10.5840/ACPAPROC2021429125","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/ACPAPROC2021429125","url":null,"abstract":"Thomistic commentators agree that Thomas Aquinas at least nominally allows for “to be” (esse) to signify not only an act contrasted with essence in creatures, but also the essence itself of those creatures. Nevertheless, it is almost unheard of for any author to interpret Thomas’s use of the word “esse” as referring to essence. Against this tendency, this paper argues that Thomas’s In V Metaphysics argument that every predication signifies esse provides an important instance of Thomas using “esse” to signify essence. This reading of In V Metaphysics, which this paper defends against Gyula Klima’s alternative interpretation, suggests significant reinterpretations of Thomas’s technical terms “esse substantiale” and “esse in rerum natura” as well as Thomas’s use of “is,” both as a copula and as a principal predicate.","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71107990","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Relation is not a Category: A Sketch of Relation as a Transcendental 关系不是范畴:论作为先验的关系
Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/ACPAPROC2021426120
Christopher V. Mirus
Working within the Aristotelian tradition, I argue that relation is not a category but a transcendental property of being. By this I mean that all substances are actualized, and hence defined, relationally: all actuality is interactuality.Interactuality is the locus for the relational categories of substance, action, being-affected, number, and most types of quality. The interactuality of corporeal beings is further conditioned by relations of setting; here we find the relational categories of place (where), quantity in the sense of size, quality in the sense of shape, and time (when). In offering a relational account of substance, I distinguish between external relata (physical environment, objects of sensation and knowledge as external) and internal relata (one’s body, objects of sensation and knowledge as internal). This distinction between external and internal relata is transcended in the case of the Trinity, insofar as the divine persons are both perfectly distinct and perfectly united.
根据亚里士多德的传统,我认为关系不是一个范畴,而是存在的先验属性。我的意思是,所有的实体都是实现化的,因此被定义为相互关系的:所有的现实性都是相互现实性。互现实性是物质、行为、被影响、数量和大多数类型的质量等关系范畴的所在地。肉体存在的互现实性进一步受到环境关系的制约;在这里,我们发现了地点(where)、大小意义上的数量、形状意义上的质量和时间(when)等关系范畴。在提供实体的关系描述时,我区分了外部关联(物理环境、感觉对象和作为外部的知识)和内部关联(人的身体、感觉对象和作为内部的知识)。在三位一体的情况下,这种外在和内在关系的区别是超越的,因为神圣的人既完全不同,又完全统一。
{"title":"Relation is not a Category: A Sketch of Relation as a Transcendental","authors":"Christopher V. Mirus","doi":"10.5840/ACPAPROC2021426120","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/ACPAPROC2021426120","url":null,"abstract":"Working within the Aristotelian tradition, I argue that relation is not a category but a transcendental property of being. By this I mean that all substances are actualized, and hence defined, relationally: all actuality is interactuality.Interactuality is the locus for the relational categories of substance, action, being-affected, number, and most types of quality. The interactuality of corporeal beings is further conditioned by relations of setting; here we find the relational categories of place (where), quantity in the sense of size, quality in the sense of shape, and time (when). In offering a relational account of substance, I distinguish between external relata (physical environment, objects of sensation and knowledge as external) and internal relata (one’s body, objects of sensation and knowledge as internal). This distinction between external and internal relata is transcended in the case of the Trinity, insofar as the divine persons are both perfectly distinct and perfectly united.","PeriodicalId":82372,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association","volume":"57 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71107358","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1