首页 > 最新文献

Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal最新文献

英文 中文
Jurisdiction: The $64,000 Question 管辖权:价值64,000美元的问题
Pub Date : 2009-11-04 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1500530
Barbara S. Esbin
Matthew Lasar asks the $64,000 question on Ars Technica: "Did Congress really give the FCC power to protect the Net? The jurisdictional question, as Lasar notes, lies at the heart of the viability of the FCC's proposed net neutrality rules. The answer depends on one's view of what regulatory powers Congress bestowed upon the agency in the Communications Act of 1934, as amended: Broadly stated, the FCC was created and given jurisdiction over interstate wire and radio commerce in communication for the purpose of making available "a rapid, efficient, Nationwide, and world-wide wire and radio communication service with adequate facilities at reasonable charges." It is in the understanding of specifically how the FCC was to go about carrying out this broad purpose that reasonable minds disagree.The FCC has made clear its view that it may regulate the network management practices of broadband Internet service providers under its implied or "ancillary jurisdiction."But Congress has never given the FCC any authority to regulate the Internet for the purpose of ensuring net neutrality. In place of explicit congressional authority, we expect the FCC will rely on its "ancillary jurisdiction," a position that amounts to "we can regulate the Internet however we like without waiting for Congress to act." The problem with the doctrine of ancillary jurisdiction is that it is potentially limitless as exercise after exercise takes the FCC further and further away from its core congressionally-delegated regulatory responsibilities. Express delegations of regulatory authority by Congress are important for two reasons: they both give power and limit its exercise in ways agreed upon by our elected representatives through duly-enacted legislation. It is particularly important that unelected government officials stay within the bounds of these delegations. Our individual freedoms as well as our democracy depend on it.
马修·拉萨尔(Matthew Lasar)在Ars Technica网站上问了一个价值6.4万美元的问题:“国会真的赋予了FCC保护网络的权力吗?”正如Lasar所指出的那样,管辖权问题是联邦通信委员会提出的网络中立规则可行性的核心。答案取决于人们对国会在1934年修订的《通信法案》中赋予该机构的监管权力的看法:概括地说,联邦通信委员会的成立并赋予其对州际有线和无线电通信业务的管辖权,目的是“以合理的收费提供快速、高效、全国范围和世界范围的有线和无线电通信服务”。理性的人不同意联邦通信委员会具体如何实现这一广泛目标的理解。联邦通信委员会已经明确表示,它可以在其隐含的或“辅助管辖权”下规范宽带互联网服务提供商的网络管理实践。但国会从未授权联邦通信委员会监管互联网,以确保网络中立性。我们预计,联邦通信委员会将依靠其“辅助管辖权”取代明确的国会权力,这一立场相当于“我们可以按照自己的意愿监管互联网,而无需等待国会采取行动”。辅助管辖权原则的问题在于,它可能是无限的,因为一次又一次的行使使联邦通信委员会越来越远离其国会授权的核心监管责任。国会对监管权力的明确授权之所以重要,有两个原因:它们既赋予权力,又以我们选出的代表通过适当颁布的立法所同意的方式限制权力的行使。特别重要的是,非选举产生的政府官员应留在这些代表团的范围内。我们的个人自由和民主都有赖于此。
{"title":"Jurisdiction: The $64,000 Question","authors":"Barbara S. Esbin","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1500530","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1500530","url":null,"abstract":"Matthew Lasar asks the $64,000 question on Ars Technica: \"Did Congress really give the FCC power to protect the Net? The jurisdictional question, as Lasar notes, lies at the heart of the viability of the FCC's proposed net neutrality rules. The answer depends on one's view of what regulatory powers Congress bestowed upon the agency in the Communications Act of 1934, as amended: Broadly stated, the FCC was created and given jurisdiction over interstate wire and radio commerce in communication for the purpose of making available \"a rapid, efficient, Nationwide, and world-wide wire and radio communication service with adequate facilities at reasonable charges.\" It is in the understanding of specifically how the FCC was to go about carrying out this broad purpose that reasonable minds disagree.The FCC has made clear its view that it may regulate the network management practices of broadband Internet service providers under its implied or \"ancillary jurisdiction.\"But Congress has never given the FCC any authority to regulate the Internet for the purpose of ensuring net neutrality. In place of explicit congressional authority, we expect the FCC will rely on its \"ancillary jurisdiction,\" a position that amounts to \"we can regulate the Internet however we like without waiting for Congress to act.\" The problem with the doctrine of ancillary jurisdiction is that it is potentially limitless as exercise after exercise takes the FCC further and further away from its core congressionally-delegated regulatory responsibilities. Express delegations of regulatory authority by Congress are important for two reasons: they both give power and limit its exercise in ways agreed upon by our elected representatives through duly-enacted legislation. It is particularly important that unelected government officials stay within the bounds of these delegations. Our individual freedoms as well as our democracy depend on it.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"46 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-11-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121743138","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Stopping the Wind that Blows and the Rivers that Run: Connecticut and Rhode Island Reject the Prohibition Amendment 阻止吹着的风和流着的河:康涅狄格和罗德岛拒绝禁酒令修正案
Pub Date : 2009-06-11 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1418009
Henry S. Cohn, Ethan P. Davis
On January 17, 1919, the New York Times reported that "[t]he American nation was voted dry today [January 16, 1919] by Constitutional Amendment when the Legislature of Nebraska, the home of William Jennings Bryan, one of the foremost champions of prohibition, ratified the proposal." This development was a triumph for the Woman's Christian Temperance Union, and even more so for the political lobbying group, the Anti-Saloon League. These groups had successfully guided the constitutional amendment through thirty-six states after the House of Representatives voted on December 17, 1917 by 282 to 128, and the Senate voted on December 18, 1917 by 47 to 8, to adopt a national prohibition amendment. The Acting Secretary of State Frank Polk declared that the amendment had been ratified by the requisite number of states on January 29, 1919. It was to take effect under its terms one year following the adoption. But the dry forces were not done with the ratification. There were two other states beside Nebraska that also ratified on January 16, 1919 - Wyoming and Missouri. In public statements, the proponents of the amendment confidently claimed that the number of states ratifying would rise to forty by January 17, 1919, and the remainder would follow quickly thereafter. Actually, the Drys were only partially correct: it took until 1922 for the forty-sixth state, New Jersey, to ratify, and Connecticut and Rhode Island would never do so. This Article presents the record of rejection by the two hold-out states - Connecticut and Rhode Island. It discusses the pressures on the legislators of the two states to ratify or reject the constitutional amendment as well as the outcome of the debate. The Article relates interesting political developments in each state. Connecticut's two legislative bodies split over the issue of ratification and never chose to pursue it further. Rhode Island decided to argue its position in the United States Supreme Court. In an ironic twist, discussed in this article, Connecticut's leading stand against the amendment was almost lost to history. In the end, Connecticut and Rhode Island, though initially in the minority, emerged victorious as the "noble experiment" ended with the repeal of prohibition in 1933.
1919年1月17日,《纽约时报》报道,“今天(1919年1月16日),禁酒令倡导者之一威廉·詹宁斯·布莱恩的家乡内布拉斯加州的立法机关批准了这项提案,美国国家通过宪法修正案投票决定戒酒。”这一进展是妇女基督教禁酒联盟的胜利,更是政治游说团体反沙龙联盟的胜利。在众议院于1917年12月17日以282票对128票通过宪法修正案,参议院于1917年12月18日以47票对8票通过全国禁酒令修正案之后,这些团体成功地引导宪法修正案通过了36个州。代理国务卿弗兰克·波尔克(Frank Polk)宣布,该修正案已于1919年1月29日得到必要数量的州的批准。它将在通过一年后根据其条款生效。但干旱的力量并没有随着批准而结束。除了内布拉斯加州,还有另外两个州也在1919年1月16日批准了该法案——怀俄明和密苏里。在公开声明中,修正案的支持者自信地声称,到1919年1月17日,批准该修正案的州将增加到40个,其余的州也会很快跟进。实际上,德里夫妇只说对了一部分:直到1922年,第46个州新泽西州才批准了宪法,而康涅狄格和罗德岛州则永远不会批准。本文介绍了两个顽固的州——康涅狄格和罗得岛州的拒绝记录。它讨论了两个州的立法者批准或拒绝宪法修正案的压力以及辩论的结果。这篇文章叙述了每个州有趣的政治发展。康涅狄格的两个立法机构在批准问题上出现分歧,从未选择进一步追究。罗德岛州决定在美国最高法院为自己的立场辩护。具有讽刺意味的是,正如本文所讨论的那样,康涅狄格州反对该修正案的主要立场几乎被历史遗忘了。最后,康涅狄格和罗德岛州虽然一开始是少数派,但随着1933年禁酒令的废除,这场“高尚的实验”最终取得了胜利。
{"title":"Stopping the Wind that Blows and the Rivers that Run: Connecticut and Rhode Island Reject the Prohibition Amendment","authors":"Henry S. Cohn, Ethan P. Davis","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1418009","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1418009","url":null,"abstract":"On January 17, 1919, the New York Times reported that \"[t]he American nation was voted dry today [January 16, 1919] by Constitutional Amendment when the Legislature of Nebraska, the home of William Jennings Bryan, one of the foremost champions of prohibition, ratified the proposal.\" This development was a triumph for the Woman's Christian Temperance Union, and even more so for the political lobbying group, the Anti-Saloon League. These groups had successfully guided the constitutional amendment through thirty-six states after the House of Representatives voted on December 17, 1917 by 282 to 128, and the Senate voted on December 18, 1917 by 47 to 8, to adopt a national prohibition amendment. The Acting Secretary of State Frank Polk declared that the amendment had been ratified by the requisite number of states on January 29, 1919. It was to take effect under its terms one year following the adoption. But the dry forces were not done with the ratification. There were two other states beside Nebraska that also ratified on January 16, 1919 - Wyoming and Missouri. In public statements, the proponents of the amendment confidently claimed that the number of states ratifying would rise to forty by January 17, 1919, and the remainder would follow quickly thereafter. Actually, the Drys were only partially correct: it took until 1922 for the forty-sixth state, New Jersey, to ratify, and Connecticut and Rhode Island would never do so. This Article presents the record of rejection by the two hold-out states - Connecticut and Rhode Island. It discusses the pressures on the legislators of the two states to ratify or reject the constitutional amendment as well as the outcome of the debate. The Article relates interesting political developments in each state. Connecticut's two legislative bodies split over the issue of ratification and never chose to pursue it further. Rhode Island decided to argue its position in the United States Supreme Court. In an ironic twist, discussed in this article, Connecticut's leading stand against the amendment was almost lost to history. In the end, Connecticut and Rhode Island, though initially in the minority, emerged victorious as the \"noble experiment\" ended with the repeal of prohibition in 1933.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"25 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-06-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123273369","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
COPPA 2.0: The New Battle Over Privacy, Age Verification, Online Safety & Free Speech COPPA 2.0:关于隐私,年龄验证,在线安全和言论自由的新战斗
Pub Date : 2009-05-21 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1408204
B. Szoka, Adam Thierer
Online privacy, child safety, free speech and anonymity are on a collision course. The 1998 Children’s Online Privacy Protection Act (COPPA) already mandates certain online privacy protections for children under 13, but many advocate expanding online privacy protections for both adolescents and adults. Furthermore, efforts continue at both the federal and state levels to institute new regulations, such as age verification mandates, aimed at ensuring the safety of children online. There is an inherent tension between these objectives: Attempts to achieve perfectly “safe” online environments will likely require the surrender of some privacy and speech rights, including the right to speak anonymously. These tensions are coming to a head with state-based efforts to expand COPPA, which requires “verifiable parental consent” before certain sites or services may collect, or enable the sharing of, personal information from children under the age of 13. Several proposed state laws would extend COPPA’s parental-consent framework to cover all adolescents under 18. This seemingly small change would require age verification of not only adolescents and their parents, but - for the first time - large numbers of adults, thus raising grave First Amendment concerns. Such broad age verification mandates would, ironically, reduce online privacy by requiring more information to be collected from both adolescents and adults for age verification purposes, while doing little to make adolescents safer. In practical terms, the increased scale of “COPPA 2.0” efforts would present significant implementation and enforcement challenges. Finally, state-level COPPA 2.0 proposals would likely conflict with the Constitution’s Commerce Clause. Despite these profound problems, COPPA expansion has great rhetorical appeal and seems likely to be at the heart of future child safety debates - especially efforts to require mandatory age verification. There are, however, many better ways to protect children online than by expanding COPPA beyond its original, limited purpose.
网络隐私、儿童安全、言论自由和匿名正在发生冲突。1998年的《儿童网络隐私保护法》(COPPA)已经规定了对13岁以下儿童的某些网络隐私保护,但许多人主张扩大对青少年和成年人的网络隐私保护。此外,联邦和州两级仍在努力制定新的法规,例如年龄验证规定,旨在确保儿童上网安全。这些目标之间存在着内在的紧张关系:试图实现完全“安全”的在线环境可能需要放弃一些隐私和言论权利,包括匿名发言的权利。随着各州努力扩大COPPA,这些紧张关系达到了顶峰。COPPA要求某些网站或服务在收集或分享13岁以下儿童的个人信息之前,必须获得“可核实的父母同意”。几个州的法律提案将把COPPA的父母同意框架扩展到所有18岁以下的青少年。这一看似很小的变化不仅需要对青少年及其父母进行年龄验证,而且第一次需要对大量成年人进行年龄验证,从而引发了对宪法第一修正案的严重担忧。具有讽刺意味的是,这种广泛的年龄验证授权要求从青少年和成年人那里收集更多的信息,从而减少了在线隐私,而对青少年的安全却没有什么帮助。实际上,“COPPA 2.0”工作规模的扩大将带来重大的实施和执法挑战。最后,州一级的COPPA 2.0提案可能与宪法的商业条款相冲突。尽管存在这些深刻的问题,COPPA的扩展具有巨大的修辞吸引力,似乎可能成为未来儿童安全辩论的核心-特别是要求强制年龄验证的努力。然而,除了将COPPA扩展到其最初的有限目的之外,还有许多更好的方法来保护在线儿童。
{"title":"COPPA 2.0: The New Battle Over Privacy, Age Verification, Online Safety & Free Speech","authors":"B. Szoka, Adam Thierer","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1408204","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1408204","url":null,"abstract":"Online privacy, child safety, free speech and anonymity are on a collision course. The 1998 Children’s Online Privacy Protection Act (COPPA) already mandates certain online privacy protections for children under 13, but many advocate expanding online privacy protections for both adolescents and adults. Furthermore, efforts continue at both the federal and state levels to institute new regulations, such as age verification mandates, aimed at ensuring the safety of children online. There is an inherent tension between these objectives: Attempts to achieve perfectly “safe” online environments will likely require the surrender of some privacy and speech rights, including the right to speak anonymously. These tensions are coming to a head with state-based efforts to expand COPPA, which requires “verifiable parental consent” before certain sites or services may collect, or enable the sharing of, personal information from children under the age of 13. Several proposed state laws would extend COPPA’s parental-consent framework to cover all adolescents under 18. This seemingly small change would require age verification of not only adolescents and their parents, but - for the first time - large numbers of adults, thus raising grave First Amendment concerns. Such broad age verification mandates would, ironically, reduce online privacy by requiring more information to be collected from both adolescents and adults for age verification purposes, while doing little to make adolescents safer. In practical terms, the increased scale of “COPPA 2.0” efforts would present significant implementation and enforcement challenges. Finally, state-level COPPA 2.0 proposals would likely conflict with the Constitution’s Commerce Clause. Despite these profound problems, COPPA expansion has great rhetorical appeal and seems likely to be at the heart of future child safety debates - especially efforts to require mandatory age verification. There are, however, many better ways to protect children online than by expanding COPPA beyond its original, limited purpose.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-05-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125791085","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
Electoral Competition and Low Contribution Limits 选举竞争和低捐款限额
Pub Date : 2009-05-07 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1400740
K. Williams, Thomas Stratmann, Ciara Torres-Spelliscy
Electoral competition is essential to democracy. Yet the incumbency rate in state-house legislative campaigns is nearly 95 percent. This report examines campaign contribution limits and the impact limits can have on electoral competition. The research on which this report is based was inspired by a 2006 U.S. Supreme Court decision that overturned low contribution limits. The data presented here refutes the Court's assumptions that low contribution limits damage challengers and shows that the lowest contribution limits, those set at $500 or below, enhance challengers' ability to campaign against incumbents in state legislative races. Though public financing systems also increase electoral competition, the Brennan Center's research suggests that incumbents nonetheless continue to opt for public financing systems. Of course, enhanced competition under low limits is only one factor to be considered. Competition, after all, is one key goal in electoral reform, but not the only one. We may wish also to encourage citizen participation and voter engagement. But if we are looking for reasons not to enact low limits, a deleterious impact on competition is not one of them. For this reason, the Supreme Court was wrong in Randall v. Sorrell. Our joint findings make it plain: low contribution limits and public financing substantially narrow the gap between incumbents and challengers. These reforms can be mutually enhancing as reasonable contribution limits are central to a well-functioning public financing system. Incumbency will continue to provide electoral advantages. However, decreasing the vote margins between votes cast for incumbents and their challengers signals greater electoral competiveness and, as such, strengthens democracy.
选举竞争对民主至关重要。然而,在州议会竞选中,现任率接近95%。本报告审查了竞选捐款的限制和限制对选举竞争的影响。这份报告所依据的研究受到了2006年美国最高法院推翻低捐献限额的判决的启发。这里提供的数据驳斥了法院关于低捐款限制损害挑战者的假设,并表明最低捐款限额,即设定在500美元或以下的捐款限额,增强了挑战者在州立法选举中对抗现任者的能力。尽管公共财政系统也增加了选举竞争,但布伦南中心的研究表明,在任者仍然会继续选择公共财政系统。当然,在低限额下加强竞争只是需要考虑的因素之一。毕竟,竞争是选举改革的一个关键目标,但不是唯一的目标。我们也不妨鼓励公民参与和选民参与。但是,如果我们正在寻找不制定低限额的理由,对竞争的有害影响不在其中。出于这个原因,最高法院在兰德尔诉索雷尔案中是错误的。我们的联合研究结果清楚地表明:较低的捐款限制和公共融资大大缩小了现任者与挑战者之间的差距。这些改革可以相互促进,因为合理的捐款限额是一个运作良好的公共融资体系的核心。现任将继续提供选举优势。然而,缩小现任总统与其挑战者之间的票数差距标志着更大的选举竞争力,因此加强了民主。
{"title":"Electoral Competition and Low Contribution Limits","authors":"K. Williams, Thomas Stratmann, Ciara Torres-Spelliscy","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1400740","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1400740","url":null,"abstract":"Electoral competition is essential to democracy. Yet the incumbency rate in state-house legislative campaigns is nearly 95 percent. This report examines campaign contribution limits and the impact limits can have on electoral competition. The research on which this report is based was inspired by a 2006 U.S. Supreme Court decision that overturned low contribution limits. The data presented here refutes the Court's assumptions that low contribution limits damage challengers and shows that the lowest contribution limits, those set at $500 or below, enhance challengers' ability to campaign against incumbents in state legislative races. Though public financing systems also increase electoral competition, the Brennan Center's research suggests that incumbents nonetheless continue to opt for public financing systems. Of course, enhanced competition under low limits is only one factor to be considered. Competition, after all, is one key goal in electoral reform, but not the only one. We may wish also to encourage citizen participation and voter engagement. But if we are looking for reasons not to enact low limits, a deleterious impact on competition is not one of them. For this reason, the Supreme Court was wrong in Randall v. Sorrell. Our joint findings make it plain: low contribution limits and public financing substantially narrow the gap between incumbents and challengers. These reforms can be mutually enhancing as reasonable contribution limits are central to a well-functioning public financing system. Incumbency will continue to provide electoral advantages. However, decreasing the vote margins between votes cast for incumbents and their challengers signals greater electoral competiveness and, as such, strengthens democracy.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":" 19","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-05-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"120834426","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
'Only a Sith Thinks Like That': Llewellyn's 'Dueling Canons,' Seventeen to Twenty “只有西斯才会那样想”:卢埃林的《决斗的大炮》,《17到20》
Pub Date : 2009-04-16 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1387503
M. Sinclair
This is the fourth installment in a series of articles examining the famous twenty eight pairs of “dueling canons” left to us in 1950 by Karl N. Llewellyn, “Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the rules or Canons of about how Statutes are to be Construed,” 3 VANDERBILT L.REV. 395 (1950). After more than half a century, Llewellyn’s assault on the legitimacy of canons remains an imposing landmark in statutory interpretation scholarship. The first three installments of this study, covering pairs 1 through 16, showed that Llewellyn’s thesis that to every canon of construction there was another to opposite effect did not stand up to examination. This study of pairs 17 through 20 continues the pattern. Both Thrust #17 and thrust #18 are very weak presumptive principles, easily countermanded by other principles such as that the legislature should be presumed to have acted consistently (Parry #17), constitutionally (Ashwander), rationally, or to some purpose (Parry #18). Only a determination to deny legislative intention in favor of interpretive formulae can save the contrariety of these pairs. Pair #19 is a complete failure of comparability and contrariety. Thrust #20 is the great (and much maligned) paradigm of canons, expressio unius est exclusio alterius. But it too is merely a presumption, in opposition to Llewellyn’s chosen Parry #20 only if given an unreasonably wooden and universal authority.
这是一系列文章的第四部分,研究了卡尔·卢埃林(Karl N. Llewellyn)在1950年留给我们的著名的28对“决斗法则”,“关于如何解释法规的上诉判决理论和规则的评论”,3 VANDERBILT L.REV。395(1950)。半个多世纪过去了,卢埃林对教规合法性的抨击仍然是法理解释学界的一个重要里程碑。本研究的前三期(从第1对到第16对)表明,Llewellyn关于每一种构造标准都有另一种相反效果的理论是经不起检验的。对17到20对的研究延续了这一模式。第17条和第18条都是非常弱的推定原则,很容易被其他原则所推翻,比如立法机构应该被推定为一贯(第17条)、符合宪法(Ashwander)、理性或出于某种目的(第18条)。只有决心否定立法意图,支持解释性公式,才能挽救这两对的矛盾。第19对是可比性和矛盾性的彻底失败。推力#20是经典的伟大(也是备受诟病的)范例,表达统一即排他性替代。但这也只是一种假设,只有在被赋予不合理的木头人和普遍权威的情况下,它才会与卢埃林选择的第20党相对立。
{"title":"'Only a Sith Thinks Like That': Llewellyn's 'Dueling Canons,' Seventeen to Twenty","authors":"M. Sinclair","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1387503","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1387503","url":null,"abstract":"This is the fourth installment in a series of articles examining the famous twenty eight pairs of “dueling canons” left to us in 1950 by Karl N. Llewellyn, “Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the rules or Canons of about how Statutes are to be Construed,” 3 VANDERBILT L.REV. 395 (1950). After more than half a century, Llewellyn’s assault on the legitimacy of canons remains an imposing landmark in statutory interpretation scholarship. The first three installments of this study, covering pairs 1 through 16, showed that Llewellyn’s thesis that to every canon of construction there was another to opposite effect did not stand up to examination. This study of pairs 17 through 20 continues the pattern. Both Thrust #17 and thrust #18 are very weak presumptive principles, easily countermanded by other principles such as that the legislature should be presumed to have acted consistently (Parry #17), constitutionally (Ashwander), rationally, or to some purpose (Parry #18). Only a determination to deny legislative intention in favor of interpretive formulae can save the contrariety of these pairs. Pair #19 is a complete failure of comparability and contrariety. Thrust #20 is the great (and much maligned) paradigm of canons, expressio unius est exclusio alterius. But it too is merely a presumption, in opposition to Llewellyn’s chosen Parry #20 only if given an unreasonably wooden and universal authority.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"98 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-04-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131721959","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Anonymity, Signaling, and Silence as Speech 匿名,信号和沉默作为语言
Pub Date : 2009-03-16 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1361225
P. Horwitz
This short article responds to a paper delivered by Professor Martin Redish at a symposium on Speech and Silence in American Law at the University of Alabama School of Law; the symposium proceedings will be published by Cambridge University Press. Professor Redish's paper argues for the elimination of First Amendment protection for expressive anonymity in certain cases involving political fraud.This response offers both clarifications and criticisms of Professor Redish's argument. It argues by way of clarification that the general category of "anonymity" is too broad to support useful analysis. Rather, we must consider the implications for Professor Redish's argument of at least two categories of speech: anonymous and pseudonymous speech. I show that even if we accept Professor Redish's account of the dangers of anonymous politically fraudulent speech, our concerns and prescriptions will vary greatly depending on what sort of "anonymous" speech we are talking about. Drawing on signaling theory, this response also offers a more critical treatment of Professor Redish's argument for the prohibition of some forms of anonymous speech. Signaling theory suggests that anonymous speech is not accurately characterized as part of the right of silence; instead, as an attributional decision that sends important signals about the reliability of the speech and the speaker, the choice of anonymity in fact constitutes a highly expressive form of speech. The signaling function of these attribution choices also suggests that Professor Redish's concerns about the misleading nature of anonymous politically fraudulent speech, and his recommendation that we curtail protection for this form of speech, are overstated.The signaling-based account of anonymity as speech has two subsidiary implications. First, contrary to Professor Redish's suggestion, it is impossible to disaggregate the rights of expressive and associational anonymity. Second, this account supports the argument of many writers that the Supreme Court ought to strongly reconsider its tangled jurisprudence concerning the permissibility of mandatory disclosure rules in the campaign finance laws, which is in tension with what the Court has written about anonymous speech in other contexts.
这篇短文回应了Martin Redish教授在阿拉巴马大学法学院美国法律中的言论与沉默研讨会上发表的一篇论文;会议记录将由剑桥大学出版社出版。Redish教授的论文主张在某些涉及政治欺诈的案件中取消第一修正案对表达性匿名的保护。这一回应既对Redish教授的观点进行了澄清,也对其提出了批评。它通过澄清的方式提出,“匿名”的一般范畴过于宽泛,无法支持有用的分析。相反,我们必须考虑Redish教授关于至少两类言论的论点的含义:匿名言论和假名言论。我表明,即使我们接受Redish教授关于匿名政治欺诈言论危险的说法,我们的担忧和对策也会因我们谈论的是哪种“匿名”言论而大不相同。借鉴信号理论,这一回应也为Redish教授关于禁止某些形式的匿名言论的论点提供了更为批判性的处理。信号理论认为,匿名言论不能被准确地定性为沉默权的一部分;相反,作为一种归因决策,匿名的选择实际上构成了一种高度表达的言语形式,它发出了关于言语和说话者可靠性的重要信号。这些归因选择的信号功能也表明,Redish教授对匿名政治欺诈性言论的误导性质的担忧,以及他建议我们减少对这种言论形式的保护,都被夸大了。基于信号的匿名性作为语音的解释有两个附属含义。首先,与Redish教授的建议相反,不可能将表达性匿名权和联想性匿名权分开。其次,这一说法支持了许多作者的观点,即最高法院应该大力重新考虑其关于竞选财务法中强制性披露规则的许可性的复杂判例,这与法院在其他情况下关于匿名言论的规定是紧张的。
{"title":"Anonymity, Signaling, and Silence as Speech","authors":"P. Horwitz","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1361225","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1361225","url":null,"abstract":"This short article responds to a paper delivered by Professor Martin Redish at a symposium on Speech and Silence in American Law at the University of Alabama School of Law; the symposium proceedings will be published by Cambridge University Press. Professor Redish's paper argues for the elimination of First Amendment protection for expressive anonymity in certain cases involving political fraud.This response offers both clarifications and criticisms of Professor Redish's argument. It argues by way of clarification that the general category of \"anonymity\" is too broad to support useful analysis. Rather, we must consider the implications for Professor Redish's argument of at least two categories of speech: anonymous and pseudonymous speech. I show that even if we accept Professor Redish's account of the dangers of anonymous politically fraudulent speech, our concerns and prescriptions will vary greatly depending on what sort of \"anonymous\" speech we are talking about. Drawing on signaling theory, this response also offers a more critical treatment of Professor Redish's argument for the prohibition of some forms of anonymous speech. Signaling theory suggests that anonymous speech is not accurately characterized as part of the right of silence; instead, as an attributional decision that sends important signals about the reliability of the speech and the speaker, the choice of anonymity in fact constitutes a highly expressive form of speech. The signaling function of these attribution choices also suggests that Professor Redish's concerns about the misleading nature of anonymous politically fraudulent speech, and his recommendation that we curtail protection for this form of speech, are overstated.The signaling-based account of anonymity as speech has two subsidiary implications. First, contrary to Professor Redish's suggestion, it is impossible to disaggregate the rights of expressive and associational anonymity. Second, this account supports the argument of many writers that the Supreme Court ought to strongly reconsider its tangled jurisprudence concerning the permissibility of mandatory disclosure rules in the campaign finance laws, which is in tension with what the Court has written about anonymous speech in other contexts.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"39 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-03-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128325083","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Supreme Court's New Implied Repeal Doctrine: Expanding Judicial Power to Rewrite Legislation Under the Ballooning Conception of 'Plain Repugnancy' 最高法院的新默示废除原则:在不断膨胀的“平原反感”概念下扩大司法权以改写立法
Pub Date : 2009-03-12 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1358474
Jesse W. Markham
This article presents a historical, public policy and analytical critique of the United States Supreme Court's revision of the implied repeal doctrine in Credit Suisse Securities (USA) LLC v. Billing, 551 U.S. 264, 127 S. Ct. 2383 (2007). The article takes a historical perspective to demonstrate the sound public policy rationale for the more traditional approach to this canon of statutory interpretation. The article analyzes the decision against the backdrop of more than 400 years of English and American courts traditional application of this doctrine to avoid judicial intrusion into the legislative prerogative. It is argued that the Court's revision of the implied repeal doctrine ignores the long and steady history of the doctrine; that the Court's new approach is bad law and bad policy; and that the Court should move to restore the traditional doctrine fully and clearly.
本文对美国最高法院在瑞士信贷证券(美国)有限责任公司诉Billing案(551 U.S. 264, 127 S. Ct. 2383(2007))中对默示废除原则的修订进行了历史、公共政策和分析性批评。本文从历史的角度论证了更传统的法定解释方法的合理的公共政策依据。本文分析了英美法院400多年来为避免司法侵犯立法特权而对这一原则的传统运用。有人认为,最高法院对默示废除原则的修订忽视了该原则的悠久而稳定的历史;法院的新做法是糟糕的法律和糟糕的政策;法院应该采取行动,全面而明确地恢复传统的原则。
{"title":"The Supreme Court's New Implied Repeal Doctrine: Expanding Judicial Power to Rewrite Legislation Under the Ballooning Conception of 'Plain Repugnancy'","authors":"Jesse W. Markham","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1358474","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1358474","url":null,"abstract":"This article presents a historical, public policy and analytical critique of the United States Supreme Court's revision of the implied repeal doctrine in Credit Suisse Securities (USA) LLC v. Billing, 551 U.S. 264, 127 S. Ct. 2383 (2007). The article takes a historical perspective to demonstrate the sound public policy rationale for the more traditional approach to this canon of statutory interpretation. The article analyzes the decision against the backdrop of more than 400 years of English and American courts traditional application of this doctrine to avoid judicial intrusion into the legislative prerogative. It is argued that the Court's revision of the implied repeal doctrine ignores the long and steady history of the doctrine; that the Court's new approach is bad law and bad policy; and that the Court should move to restore the traditional doctrine fully and clearly.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-03-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131655554","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The Promise of Carolene Products: A Footnote to the Footnote 卡罗琳产品的承诺:脚注的脚注
Pub Date : 2009-02-15 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1375619
Neelanjan Maitra
The Supreme Court’s upholding of Congress’s Filled Milk Act of 1923 which banned the shipment in interstate commerce of skimmed milk compounded with certain fats or oils excited little comment at the time. Yet a seemingly passing observation arising out of the decision has continued to hold enduring, almost obsessive, significance for academics and judges alike. I refer, of course, to Justice Stone’s famous footnote 4 in U.S. v. Carolene Products. That footnote, arguably the most famous in legal history, reads in relevant part: “…It is unnecessary to consider now whether legislation which restricts those political processes which can ordinarily be expected to bring about repeal of undesirable legislation, is to be subjected to more exacting judicial scrutiny under the general prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment than are most other types of legislation…Nor need we enquire whether similar considerations enter into the review of statutes directed at particular religious, or racial minorities…whether prejudice against discrete and insular minorities may be a special condition, which tends seriously to curtail the operation of those political processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities, and which may call for a correspondingly more searching judicial inquiry.”The promise of this brief reference to a heightened role for judicial review where political processes were likely to work against discrete and insular minorities served to inspire John Hart Ely’s Democracy and Distrust. Forty years after Carolene Products had been decided, Ely agreed that “discrete and insular minorities” could often be failed by political processes and that courts should step in to remedy such failures. Ely realized, as Justice Stone did, that discrete and insular minorities could forge political alliances and “mutual defense pacts” with other minorities as well as with broader majorities. He knew, however, that such wheeling and dealing has its limitations – sometimes political allies simply cannot be found.
最高法院支持国会1923年的《填充牛奶法》,该法案禁止在州际贸易中运输含有某些脂肪或油的脱脂牛奶,当时没有引起什么评论。然而,这一判决引发的一个看似短暂的观察,对学者和法官们来说,仍然具有持久的、几乎是强迫性的意义。当然,我指的是斯通大法官在美国诉卡罗琳产品案中著名的脚注。这个注脚可以说是法律史上最著名的注脚,在相关部分是这样写的:“……现在没有必要考虑限制那些通常可以预期会导致不受欢迎的立法被废除的政治过程的立法,是否要在第十四修正案的一般禁止下受到比大多数其他类型的立法更严格的司法审查……我们也不需要调查是否有类似的考虑进入针对特定宗教的法规的审查,或种族少数群体……对离散和孤立的少数群体的偏见是否可能是一种特殊情况,这种情况往往会严重限制通常用来保护少数群体的政治进程的运作,因此可能需要相应地进行更深入的司法调查。”在政治过程可能不利于离散和孤立的少数群体的情况下,这一简短提及司法审查的重要性的承诺,激发了约翰·哈特·伊利的《民主与不信任》。在卡罗琳产品公司被裁定四十年后,伊利同意,“离散和孤立的少数民族”经常会因政治进程而失败,法院应该介入来补救这种失败。和斯通法官一样,伊利也意识到,孤立的少数群体可以与其他少数群体以及更广泛的多数群体建立政治联盟和“共同防御条约”。然而,他知道,这种投机取巧有其局限性——有时根本找不到政治盟友。
{"title":"The Promise of Carolene Products: A Footnote to the Footnote","authors":"Neelanjan Maitra","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1375619","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1375619","url":null,"abstract":"The Supreme Court’s upholding of Congress’s Filled Milk Act of 1923 which banned the shipment in interstate commerce of skimmed milk compounded with certain fats or oils excited little comment at the time. Yet a seemingly passing observation arising out of the decision has continued to hold enduring, almost obsessive, significance for academics and judges alike. I refer, of course, to Justice Stone’s famous footnote 4 in U.S. v. Carolene Products. That footnote, arguably the most famous in legal history, reads in relevant part: “…It is unnecessary to consider now whether legislation which restricts those political processes which can ordinarily be expected to bring about repeal of undesirable legislation, is to be subjected to more exacting judicial scrutiny under the general prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment than are most other types of legislation…Nor need we enquire whether similar considerations enter into the review of statutes directed at particular religious, or racial minorities…whether prejudice against discrete and insular minorities may be a special condition, which tends seriously to curtail the operation of those political processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities, and which may call for a correspondingly more searching judicial inquiry.”The promise of this brief reference to a heightened role for judicial review where political processes were likely to work against discrete and insular minorities served to inspire John Hart Ely’s Democracy and Distrust. Forty years after Carolene Products had been decided, Ely agreed that “discrete and insular minorities” could often be failed by political processes and that courts should step in to remedy such failures. Ely realized, as Justice Stone did, that discrete and insular minorities could forge political alliances and “mutual defense pacts” with other minorities as well as with broader majorities. He knew, however, that such wheeling and dealing has its limitations – sometimes political allies simply cannot be found.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"44 11","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-02-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"120811311","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Government Support for the Terrorism Insurance Industry: Where do We go from Here? 政府对恐怖主义保险业的支持:我们该何去何从?
Pub Date : 2008-08-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1267231
T. Russell, J. Thomas
Federal government support for the terrorism insurance industry has a very brief history. Prior to 9/11, insurers did not take terrorist-related losses into account when underwriting risks. The industry did not even conceive of an attack that could generate such significant losses. The dramatic shift in perception since then has caused many to suggest that terrorism risks are uninsurable. The notion that terrorism risk was uninsurable was part of the rationale advanced for government intervention. When the initial efforts at legislation failed, the industry began to withdraw from the market by adding exclusions for terrorism-related losses to their policies. Reinsurers were the first to adopt such exclusions and their withdrawal left the primary insurers at risk of insolvency in the event of a major terrorism loss. The fundamental problem of terrorism insurance is the impossibility of adequate capital following a large loss. When Congress decided that reduced availability of terrorism insurance was causing a drag on the U.S. economy, the Terrorism Risk Insurance Act (TRIA) was adopted. TRIA provides liquidity through government support to pay terrorism claims. This paper examines the essential features of the TRIA while asking how terrorism insurance could optimally be regulated. It concludes with the suggestion to extend to insurers of terrorism-related loss the same access to public capital as the Federal Reserve provides to banks in times of liquidity crises.
联邦政府对恐怖主义保险行业的支持历史很短。在9/11之前,保险公司在承保风险时并未将与恐怖主义有关的损失考虑在内。该行业甚至没有想到一次攻击会造成如此重大的损失。自那以后,人们对恐怖主义的看法发生了巨大变化,这使得许多人认为恐怖主义风险是不保险的。恐怖主义风险不保险的观念是政府干预的部分理由。当最初的立法努力失败后,保险业开始退出市场,将与恐怖主义有关的损失排除在其政策之外。再保险公司首先采用了这种排除条款,它们的退出使原保险公司在发生重大恐怖主义损失时面临破产的风险。恐怖主义保险的根本问题是,在发生重大损失后不可能获得足够的资本。当国会认为减少恐怖主义保险的可用性对美国经济造成拖累时,通过了《恐怖主义风险保险法》(TRIA)。TRIA通过政府支持支付恐怖主义索赔提供流动性。本文考察了TRIA的基本特征,同时探讨了如何对恐怖主义保险进行最佳监管。报告最后建议,应向遭受恐怖主义相关损失的保险公司提供与美联储(fed)在流动性危机时期向银行提供的同样的公共资本。
{"title":"Government Support for the Terrorism Insurance Industry: Where do We go from Here?","authors":"T. Russell, J. Thomas","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1267231","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1267231","url":null,"abstract":"Federal government support for the terrorism insurance industry has a very brief history. Prior to 9/11, insurers did not take terrorist-related losses into account when underwriting risks. The industry did not even conceive of an attack that could generate such significant losses. The dramatic shift in perception since then has caused many to suggest that terrorism risks are uninsurable. The notion that terrorism risk was uninsurable was part of the rationale advanced for government intervention. When the initial efforts at legislation failed, the industry began to withdraw from the market by adding exclusions for terrorism-related losses to their policies. Reinsurers were the first to adopt such exclusions and their withdrawal left the primary insurers at risk of insolvency in the event of a major terrorism loss. The fundamental problem of terrorism insurance is the impossibility of adequate capital following a large loss. When Congress decided that reduced availability of terrorism insurance was causing a drag on the U.S. economy, the Terrorism Risk Insurance Act (TRIA) was adopted. TRIA provides liquidity through government support to pay terrorism claims. This paper examines the essential features of the TRIA while asking how terrorism insurance could optimally be regulated. It concludes with the suggestion to extend to insurers of terrorism-related loss the same access to public capital as the Federal Reserve provides to banks in times of liquidity crises.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"26 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2008-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128684032","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The Law and Incapacity Determinations: A Conflict of Governance? 法律与无行为能力判定:治理的冲突?
Pub Date : 2008-04-17 DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-2230.2008.00700.x
A. Boyle
This article will consider the highly charged questions raised by two major sets of law reforms in England and Wales, the Mental Capacity Act 2005 and the Mental Health Act 2007, which, although applying to closely related clinical populations, proceeded along entirely separate legislative paths. By justifying its proposals for reform of mental health legislation on the grounds of ‘risk’, the Government failed to take into account the implications of enforced treatment on patients who may retain decision-making capacity.
本文将考虑英格兰和威尔士的两套主要法律改革——《2005年精神能力法》和《2007年精神卫生法》——提出的高度敏感的问题,这两套法律改革虽然适用于密切相关的临床人群,但却沿着完全不同的立法道路进行。政府以"风险"为理由提出改革精神健康立法的建议,但没有考虑到强制治疗对可能保留决策能力的病人的影响。
{"title":"The Law and Incapacity Determinations: A Conflict of Governance?","authors":"A. Boyle","doi":"10.1111/j.1468-2230.2008.00700.x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2230.2008.00700.x","url":null,"abstract":"This article will consider the highly charged questions raised by two major sets of law reforms in England and Wales, the Mental Capacity Act 2005 and the Mental Health Act 2007, which, although applying to closely related clinical populations, proceeded along entirely separate legislative paths. By justifying its proposals for reform of mental health legislation on the grounds of ‘risk’, the Government failed to take into account the implications of enforced treatment on patients who may retain decision-making capacity.","PeriodicalId":166493,"journal":{"name":"Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal","volume":"138 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2008-04-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"116396159","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 8
期刊
Legislation & Statutory Interpretation eJournal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1