首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry最新文献

英文 中文
Deleuze: Concepts as Continuous Variation 德勒兹:连续变化的概念
Pub Date : 2010-03-18 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105116
Daniel W. Smith
(Justin S. Litaker interviewed Daniel W. Smith. Mr. Litaker focused his questions on continuous variation of concepts in Deleuze). JSL: How did you come to be interested in the work of Gilles Deleuze, and what sustains your interest? [ILLUSTRATION OMITTED] DWS: I first became interested in Deleuze when I was in graduate school. I was reading Nietzsche when the English translation of Deleuze's Nietzsche and Philosophy came out. So I read the book and was amazed at the way Deleuze had systematized Nietzsche's thought. At the time, there weren't many translations of Deleuze's works available, so I went to the library at the University of Chicago and discovered Difference and Repetition on the shelves. I thought it must contain the secret of Deleuze's work, which was only hinted at in Nietzsche and Philosophy. So right at the start, Nietzsche and Philosophy instilled in me a kind of conviction that Deleuze was worth reading, and that there was much more in his work that I needed to find out about. I had also been reading Vincent Descombes' book Modern French Philosophy, and he had isolated Derrida and Deleuze as the focal points of contemporary French philosophy. So I knew that Deleuze was more than a historian of philosophy, and that he had a project of his own, which was, at the very least, oriented around the concept of difference. There and then, I decided that I needed to learn French in order to read Difference and Repetition. You asked what has sustained my interest in Deleuze through the years. For one, I've never tired of reading Deleuze. Even now, I don't think I have a complete sense of what Deleuze is up to. I think this is partly because of his manner of writing, which has been described as "free indirect discourse." Deleuze has written numerous monographs in the history of philosophy-on Hume, Nietzsche, Kant, Leibniz, Bergson, and so on-but in each book he is also reading and using these thinkers toward his own philosophical ends, so that in Nietzsche and Philosophy, for instance, there is a becoming-Nietzsche of Deleuze as well as a becoming-Deleuze of Nietzsche. Readers are thus caught up in what Deleuze would call a becoming, or a zone of indiscernibility. Reading Deleuze is more like following a trajectory or a continuous movement that you never have done with, rather than arriving at a set of doctrines or positions that would lie at the heart of Deleuze's thought. JSL: Has this process of becoming or continuous movement affected your own reading of Deleuze? DWS: Absolutely. Right now I'm trying to write a book on Deleuze. At one point, Deleuze says that he still believes in philosophy as a system, and I initially thought, well great, I'll try to elucidate Deleuze's system of philosophy. I thought I'd approach Deleuze's system using Kant as a model, since Kant has a very architectonic idea of what philosophy is. So I borrowed five rubrics from Kant's system: aesthetics (the theory of space and time, the theory of art, the theory of
(Justin S. Litaker采访了Daniel W. Smith。利塔克的问题集中在德勒兹(Deleuze)的概念的不断变化上。JSL:你是如何对吉尔·德勒兹的作品产生兴趣的,是什么让你保持这种兴趣的?DWS:我第一次对德勒兹产生兴趣是在我读研究生的时候。德勒兹的《尼采与哲学》英译本出版时,我正在读尼采。所以我读了这本书,对德勒兹系统化尼采思想的方式感到惊讶。当时,德勒兹作品的译本不多,所以我去了芝加哥大学的图书馆,在书架上发现了《差异与重复》。我想它一定包含了德勒兹作品的秘密,而这只是在《尼采与哲学》中有所暗示。所以从一开始,尼采和哲学就给我灌输了一种信念,即德勒兹值得一读,他的作品中有很多东西我需要去了解。我也读过文森特·德库姆的《现代法国哲学》,他把德里达和德勒兹作为当代法国哲学的焦点。所以我知道德勒兹不仅仅是一位哲学史家,他有自己的研究项目,至少,是围绕差异的概念展开的。当时,我决定我需要学习法语,以便阅读《差异与重复》。你问是什么让我这么多年来一直对德勒兹感兴趣。首先,我对德勒兹的阅读不厌其烦。即使是现在,我也不认为我能完全理解德勒兹在做什么。我认为这部分是因为他的写作方式,被称为“自由间接话语”。德勒兹在哲学史上写了许多专著——关于休谟、尼采、康德、莱布尼茨、柏格森等等——但在每一本书中,他也阅读并利用这些思想家来达到自己的哲学目的,因此,例如,在《尼采与哲学》中,有一个成为德勒兹的尼采,也有一个成为德勒兹的尼采。因此,读者陷入了德勒兹所说的“变”或“不可分辨的地带”。阅读德勒兹更像是沿着一条轨迹或一个你从未经历过的连续运动,而不是到达德勒兹思想核心的一套理论或立场。JSL:这种形成的过程或持续的运动是否影响了你对德勒兹的阅读?DWS:当然。现在我正在写一本关于德勒兹的书。有一次,德勒兹说他仍然相信哲学是一个体系,我一开始想,很好,我要试着阐明德勒兹的哲学体系。我想我应该以康德为模型来研究德勒兹的体系,因为康德对哲学有一个非常架构化的概念。因此,我从康德的体系中借用了五个准则:美学(时空理论、艺术理论、感性理论)、分析学(先验演绎中的概念理论)、辩证法(理念理论)、伦理学和政治学。我想我会从康德开始,然后展示德勒兹是如何修改康德的,在这个过程中,我就能写出德勒兹体系的某个版本。至少,这是我写这本书的最初想法。当然,事实证明一切都比这复杂得多。尽管德勒兹说他对哲学作为一个体系感兴趣,他也说他认为他自己的体系是"异质的"也就是说,它本身就是异质的起源,是新事物的产生,是差异的产生。这意味着德勒兹自己的体系在其发展过程中不断自我修正。德勒兹在他的《感觉的逻辑》意大利语译本的序言中举了一个例子,他以自己的强度概念为例。…
{"title":"Deleuze: Concepts as Continuous Variation","authors":"Daniel W. Smith","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105116","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105116","url":null,"abstract":"(Justin S. Litaker interviewed Daniel W. Smith. Mr. Litaker focused his questions on continuous variation of concepts in Deleuze). JSL: How did you come to be interested in the work of Gilles Deleuze, and what sustains your interest? [ILLUSTRATION OMITTED] DWS: I first became interested in Deleuze when I was in graduate school. I was reading Nietzsche when the English translation of Deleuze's Nietzsche and Philosophy came out. So I read the book and was amazed at the way Deleuze had systematized Nietzsche's thought. At the time, there weren't many translations of Deleuze's works available, so I went to the library at the University of Chicago and discovered Difference and Repetition on the shelves. I thought it must contain the secret of Deleuze's work, which was only hinted at in Nietzsche and Philosophy. So right at the start, Nietzsche and Philosophy instilled in me a kind of conviction that Deleuze was worth reading, and that there was much more in his work that I needed to find out about. I had also been reading Vincent Descombes' book Modern French Philosophy, and he had isolated Derrida and Deleuze as the focal points of contemporary French philosophy. So I knew that Deleuze was more than a historian of philosophy, and that he had a project of his own, which was, at the very least, oriented around the concept of difference. There and then, I decided that I needed to learn French in order to read Difference and Repetition. You asked what has sustained my interest in Deleuze through the years. For one, I've never tired of reading Deleuze. Even now, I don't think I have a complete sense of what Deleuze is up to. I think this is partly because of his manner of writing, which has been described as \"free indirect discourse.\" Deleuze has written numerous monographs in the history of philosophy-on Hume, Nietzsche, Kant, Leibniz, Bergson, and so on-but in each book he is also reading and using these thinkers toward his own philosophical ends, so that in Nietzsche and Philosophy, for instance, there is a becoming-Nietzsche of Deleuze as well as a becoming-Deleuze of Nietzsche. Readers are thus caught up in what Deleuze would call a becoming, or a zone of indiscernibility. Reading Deleuze is more like following a trajectory or a continuous movement that you never have done with, rather than arriving at a set of doctrines or positions that would lie at the heart of Deleuze's thought. JSL: Has this process of becoming or continuous movement affected your own reading of Deleuze? DWS: Absolutely. Right now I'm trying to write a book on Deleuze. At one point, Deleuze says that he still believes in philosophy as a system, and I initially thought, well great, I'll try to elucidate Deleuze's system of philosophy. I thought I'd approach Deleuze's system using Kant as a model, since Kant has a very architectonic idea of what philosophy is. So I borrowed five rubrics from Kant's system: aesthetics (the theory of space and time, the theory of art, the theory of ","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"22 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2010-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125292061","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Importance of Sound in Poetry 诗歌中声音的重要性
Pub Date : 2010-03-18 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105117
Yubraj Aryal
{"title":"Importance of Sound in Poetry","authors":"Yubraj Aryal","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105117","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105117","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2010-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130308037","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Active/reactive Body in Deleuze and Foucault 德勒兹和福柯的主动/被动身体
Pub Date : 2010-03-18 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201051110
Sergey Toymentsev
Deleuze's Nietzsche and Philosophy may be considered as one of the earliest studies that presents Nietzsche as a philosopher rather than a poetic thinker by foregrounding the systematic element of his legacy. As a result, Deleuze's Nietzsche turns out to be impersonally objective and rigorously scientific/mathematical: his science is the concrete physics of forces that studies the formation of bodies as the effects of the dynamic relations of forces. As I'll attempt to show, it is Nietzsche's physics of forces that lays the foundation for the divergent yet complimentary methodologies of Deleuze and Foulcault. 1. Deleuze's Reading of Nietzsche's Theory of Active and Reactive Forces Active and reactive forces are the basic functions of Nietzsche's calculus where one force is necessarily viewed in relation to its opposite. According to Nietzsche's hierarchy of forces, active forces are those of domination and form-giving; while reactive ones are those of obedience and form-receiving. In reality, however, the interpretation of what kinds of forces are involved in the formation of the body is complicated by the fact that reactive forces prevail over active ones and thereby shape a reactive body. In history, the original hierarchy of forces is therefore inverted: reactive forces are dominant, while active ones are dominated. To illuminate the dynamic of force struggles, Deleuze-Nietzsche introduces the concept of the will to power, an inner motive force whose more primordial qualities of affirmation and negation determine the qualities of forces in a given relation. The affirming will to power expresses itself through active forces (by affirming itself); while the negating will to power, or the will to nothingness, through reactive forces (by negating the other). Furthermore, "affirmation and negation extend beyond action and reaction because they are the immediate qualities of becoming itself. Affirmation is ... the power of becoming active ... Negation is ... a becoming reactive." (1) Therefore, depending on what quality constitutes the nature of the will to power (which, in turn, determines the qualities of forces), the becoming of forces can be either reactive or active: through the will to nothingness, all forces become reactive; through the affirmative will to power, all forces become active. However, the becoming-reactive of all forces is, according to Deleuze-Nietzsche, the only becoming of forces we know; and it is this becoming that constitutes the essence of man and universal history. How do reactive forces triumph over active ones? As Deleuze emphasizes, reactive forces do not triumph by forming a superior force; they always remain inferior in quantity and reactive in quality. The root of their triumph lies in the inversion of the differential genetic element, from which both active and reactive forces emerge. The differential origin of forces is seen differently from both sides of active and reactive forces: for active forces, the differen
德勒兹的《尼采与哲学》可能被认为是最早的研究之一,通过突出尼采遗产的系统因素,将尼采呈现为哲学家而不是诗意思想家。因此,德勒兹的尼采变成了客观客观和严格的科学/数学:他的科学是具体的力的物理学,研究物体的形成作为力的动态关系的影响。正如我将试图展示的那样,正是尼采的力的物理学为德勒兹和福柯的不同而又互补的方法论奠定了基础。主动力和被动力是尼采微积分的基本功能,其中一种力必然与它的对立面相联系。根据尼采的力量等级论,积极的力量是支配和给予形式的力量;而反应性的则是服从和接受形式。然而,在现实中,由于反作用力胜过主动作用力,从而形成了一个反作用力,所以对何种力参与了物体的形成的解释是复杂的。因此,在历史上,原来的力量等级被颠倒了:被动力量占主导地位,而主动力量占主导地位。为了阐明力量斗争的动态,德勒兹-尼采引入了权力意志的概念,这是一种内在的动力,其更原始的肯定和否定的性质决定了特定关系中力量的性质。肯定的权力意志通过积极的力量(通过肯定自己)来表达自己;而否定的权力意志,或虚无意志,通过反作用力(通过否定对方)。此外,“肯定和否定超越了行动和反应,因为它们是成为自身的直接品质。”肯定是……变得积极的力量……否定是……变得被动。”(1)因此,根据构成权力意志的性质的性质(权力意志又决定力的性质),力的形成可以是被动的,也可以是主动的:通过对虚无的意志,一切力都变成被动的;通过对权力的肯定意志,一切力量都变得活跃起来。然而,根据德勒兹-尼采的说法,所有力的变反作用是我们所知道的唯一力的变;正是这种变化构成了人类和世界历史的本质。被动力量是如何战胜主动力量的?正如德勒兹所强调的那样,反作用力不会通过形成优势力量而取得胜利;他们总是在数量上处于劣势,在质量上处于被动。他们胜利的根源在于不同的遗传因素的颠倒,主动和被动的力量都是从这些因素中产生的。从主动力量和被动力量的两个方面来看,力的不同的起源是不同的:对于主动力量来说,在起源上的不同是肯定和享受的源泉;对于反作用力,则是否定和挫折。对于前者来说,它的表现本身就是一种差别,与对方无关;对于后者来说,这是一种需要压制/中和的对立或矛盾。因此,在反作用力的镜子中,作用力的系谱要素(即差异本身)是颠倒的;自我的肯定被颠倒为他者的否定。被动力量的职业生涯取决于这种被动形象的发展,或起源的虚构,它被投射到积极力量身上,从而将他们与他们所能做的分开。因此,主动力量就反作用于它自己,从而剥夺了它的表现形式。脱离了它的能力,主动力量就变成了被动力量。在这种力关系的最终反转中,反作用力不再被作用,只被感觉(即被反应);我……
{"title":"Active/reactive Body in Deleuze and Foucault","authors":"Sergey Toymentsev","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201051110","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201051110","url":null,"abstract":"Deleuze's Nietzsche and Philosophy may be considered as one of the earliest studies that presents Nietzsche as a philosopher rather than a poetic thinker by foregrounding the systematic element of his legacy. As a result, Deleuze's Nietzsche turns out to be impersonally objective and rigorously scientific/mathematical: his science is the concrete physics of forces that studies the formation of bodies as the effects of the dynamic relations of forces. As I'll attempt to show, it is Nietzsche's physics of forces that lays the foundation for the divergent yet complimentary methodologies of Deleuze and Foulcault. 1. Deleuze's Reading of Nietzsche's Theory of Active and Reactive Forces Active and reactive forces are the basic functions of Nietzsche's calculus where one force is necessarily viewed in relation to its opposite. According to Nietzsche's hierarchy of forces, active forces are those of domination and form-giving; while reactive ones are those of obedience and form-receiving. In reality, however, the interpretation of what kinds of forces are involved in the formation of the body is complicated by the fact that reactive forces prevail over active ones and thereby shape a reactive body. In history, the original hierarchy of forces is therefore inverted: reactive forces are dominant, while active ones are dominated. To illuminate the dynamic of force struggles, Deleuze-Nietzsche introduces the concept of the will to power, an inner motive force whose more primordial qualities of affirmation and negation determine the qualities of forces in a given relation. The affirming will to power expresses itself through active forces (by affirming itself); while the negating will to power, or the will to nothingness, through reactive forces (by negating the other). Furthermore, \"affirmation and negation extend beyond action and reaction because they are the immediate qualities of becoming itself. Affirmation is ... the power of becoming active ... Negation is ... a becoming reactive.\" (1) Therefore, depending on what quality constitutes the nature of the will to power (which, in turn, determines the qualities of forces), the becoming of forces can be either reactive or active: through the will to nothingness, all forces become reactive; through the affirmative will to power, all forces become active. However, the becoming-reactive of all forces is, according to Deleuze-Nietzsche, the only becoming of forces we know; and it is this becoming that constitutes the essence of man and universal history. How do reactive forces triumph over active ones? As Deleuze emphasizes, reactive forces do not triumph by forming a superior force; they always remain inferior in quantity and reactive in quality. The root of their triumph lies in the inversion of the differential genetic element, from which both active and reactive forces emerge. The differential origin of forces is seen differently from both sides of active and reactive forces: for active forces, the differen","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2010-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133068702","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
On Speed: Its Lure, Its Limits and the Question, Whether Or Not Time Has Come to Slow Things Down 论速度:它的诱惑,它的限制和问题,时间是否已经到来放慢速度
Pub Date : 2010-03-18 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105119
K. V. Dijk
{"title":"On Speed: Its Lure, Its Limits and the Question, Whether Or Not Time Has Come to Slow Things Down","authors":"K. V. Dijk","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105119","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105119","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"50 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2010-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131476547","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An Approach to Difference and Repetition 差异与重复的方法
Pub Date : 2010-03-18 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105115
John Protevi
Truer words were never spoken than when Deleuze said of Difference and Repetition in his 1973 "Letter to a Harsh Critic," "it's still full of academic elements, it's heavy going." (1) I'll say! (Part of that academicism comes from Deleuze having submitted Difference and Repetition to his jury as the primary thesis for the doctorat d'Etat; the secondary thesis was the big Spinoza book). The context of these remarks is useful: Deleuze has just been noting that "the history of philosophy plays a patently repressive role in philosophy, it's philosophy's own version of the Oedipus complex." (2) Deleuze continues that he tried to subvert this repressive force by various means: (3) (1) by writing on authors such as Lucretius, Hume, Spinoza and Nietzsche who contested the rationalist tradition by the "critique of negativity, the cultivation of joy, the hatred of interiority, the externality of forces and relations, the denunciation of power [pouvoir]"; (2) by enculage / immaculate conception: making the author say something in their own words that would be monstrous. These are famous lines, and the last is certainly fun in an epater les bourgeois sort of way. But what is really important in my view comes next, when Deleuze explains what it means to finally write "in your own name," as he claims he first did in Difference and Repetition: Individuals find a real name for themselves ... only through the harshest exercises in depersonalization, by opening themselves up to the multiplicities everywhere w/in them, to the intensities running through them. [This is] a depersonalization through love rather than through subjection. (4) So that's our challenge in introducing Difference and Repetition: can we help our students avoid subjecting themselves to it as a monument in the history of philosophy, as is the case with an Oedipal relation to the history of philosophy in which you give yourself up to be a mere repetiteur: an old occupational title in the French academic system? Rather, can we help them turn their reading of it into a "harsh exercise in depersonalization," that is, an opening up of themselves to the multiplicities and intensities within them, indeed, within all of us, student and teacher alike? Can our encounter with it be a depersonalization through love? Can we learn from it, rather than gain knowledge from it? Luckily, Difference and Repetition contains a discussion of learning; it thematizes the challenge it poses to us. The discussion of learning occurs at a key point in Difference and Repetition, at the turning point of the book, the end of the middle chapter, "The Image of Thought." Let's look at the architecture of the book, which after the Preface, has a pleasing and significant asymmetry: Introduction: Repetition and Difference Chapter One: Difference in Itself Chapter Two: Repetition for Itself Chapter Three: The Image of Thought Chapter Four: Ideal Synthesis of Difference Chapter Five: Asymmetrical Synthesis of Sensibility Conclusion:
德勒兹在他1973年的《给一个严厉批评家的信》中谈到差异与重复时说:“它仍然充满了学术元素,很沉重。”这是最真实不过的话了。我会说!(这种学术主义的一部分来自于德勒兹把《差异与重复》作为他的博士论文的主要论题提交给他的评委会;第二篇论文是斯宾诺莎的巨著)。这些评论的背景是有用的:德勒兹刚刚注意到“哲学史在哲学中扮演着明显的压抑角色,这是哲学自己版本的俄狄浦斯情结。”(2)德勒兹继续说,他试图通过各种手段颠覆这种压抑的力量:(3)(1)通过对卢克莱修、休谟、斯宾诺莎和尼采等作家的著述,这些作家通过“批判消极、培养快乐、憎恨内在、力量和关系的外部性、谴责权力(pouvoir)”来挑战理性主义传统;通过鼓励/完美的构思:让作者用自己的话说出一些可怕的话。这些都是著名的台词,最后一句当然很有趣,以一种不那么资产阶级的方式。但在我看来,真正重要的是接下来,当德勒兹解释最终“以自己的名义”写作意味着什么时,正如他声称他第一次在《差异与重复》中所做的那样:个人为自己找到了一个真正的名字……只有通过最严酷的去人格化练习,通过向他们周围的多样性敞开心扉,向贯穿其中的强度敞开心扉。这是一种通过爱而不是通过臣服来实现的去人格化。(4)所以,这就是我们在介绍差异与重复时所面临的挑战:我们能否帮助学生避免把它当作哲学史上的一座纪念碑,就像在哲学史上的俄狄浦斯关系中,你把自己变成了一个纯粹的重复者:法国学术体系中的一个古老的职业头衔?相反,我们能不能帮助他们把他们的阅读变成一种“去人格化的严酷练习”,也就是说,向他们内心的多样性和强度敞开心扉,实际上,向我们所有人,学生和老师敞开心扉?我们与它的相遇能通过爱成为人格解体吗?我们能从中学习,而不是从中获得知识吗?幸运的是,《差异与重复》包含了关于学习的讨论;它把它给我们带来的挑战主题化了。关于学习的讨论出现在《差异与重复》的一个关键点上,在这本书的转折点上,在中间一章“思想的形象”的末尾。让我们来看看这本书的结构,在序言之后,它有一个令人愉快的和显著的不对称:引言:重复和差异第一章:差异本身第二章:重复本身第三章:思想的形象第四章:差异的理想综合第五章:情感的不对称综合结论:差异和重复乍一看,我们看到这本书的标题/主题,差异和重复,构成了这本书。结论部分不同地重复了引言部分,第四章重复了第一章,第五章重复了第二章。第三章是本书的中心,是全书的支点。蒂姆·墨菲(Tim Murphy)将在一篇有用的文章中宣称,这是一种“停顿”,一种纯粹而空洞的时间形式,它打破了赤裸裸的重复,开辟了通往全新未来的道路,一种与众不同的重复。(5)我们应该注意到,在1988年的一次采访中,德勒兹说,“本体学”或对思维形象的研究是“哲学的导论”。(6)因此,粗略地说,我们可以说这本书的第一部分(引言和第一章和第二章)是德勒兹在哲学史上的去人格化之旅(以不同的方式重复,他对他所写的哲学家的鼓励)。…
{"title":"An Approach to Difference and Repetition","authors":"John Protevi","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105115","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20105115","url":null,"abstract":"Truer words were never spoken than when Deleuze said of Difference and Repetition in his 1973 \"Letter to a Harsh Critic,\" \"it's still full of academic elements, it's heavy going.\" (1) I'll say! (Part of that academicism comes from Deleuze having submitted Difference and Repetition to his jury as the primary thesis for the doctorat d'Etat; the secondary thesis was the big Spinoza book). The context of these remarks is useful: Deleuze has just been noting that \"the history of philosophy plays a patently repressive role in philosophy, it's philosophy's own version of the Oedipus complex.\" (2) Deleuze continues that he tried to subvert this repressive force by various means: (3) (1) by writing on authors such as Lucretius, Hume, Spinoza and Nietzsche who contested the rationalist tradition by the \"critique of negativity, the cultivation of joy, the hatred of interiority, the externality of forces and relations, the denunciation of power [pouvoir]\"; (2) by enculage / immaculate conception: making the author say something in their own words that would be monstrous. These are famous lines, and the last is certainly fun in an epater les bourgeois sort of way. But what is really important in my view comes next, when Deleuze explains what it means to finally write \"in your own name,\" as he claims he first did in Difference and Repetition: Individuals find a real name for themselves ... only through the harshest exercises in depersonalization, by opening themselves up to the multiplicities everywhere w/in them, to the intensities running through them. [This is] a depersonalization through love rather than through subjection. (4) So that's our challenge in introducing Difference and Repetition: can we help our students avoid subjecting themselves to it as a monument in the history of philosophy, as is the case with an Oedipal relation to the history of philosophy in which you give yourself up to be a mere repetiteur: an old occupational title in the French academic system? Rather, can we help them turn their reading of it into a \"harsh exercise in depersonalization,\" that is, an opening up of themselves to the multiplicities and intensities within them, indeed, within all of us, student and teacher alike? Can our encounter with it be a depersonalization through love? Can we learn from it, rather than gain knowledge from it? Luckily, Difference and Repetition contains a discussion of learning; it thematizes the challenge it poses to us. The discussion of learning occurs at a key point in Difference and Repetition, at the turning point of the book, the end of the middle chapter, \"The Image of Thought.\" Let's look at the architecture of the book, which after the Preface, has a pleasing and significant asymmetry: Introduction: Repetition and Difference Chapter One: Difference in Itself Chapter Two: Repetition for Itself Chapter Three: The Image of Thought Chapter Four: Ideal Synthesis of Difference Chapter Five: Asymmetrical Synthesis of Sensibility Conclusion: ","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"63 3","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2010-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"113958444","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
Representations of Time and Memory in Holocaust Literature: A Comparison of Charlotte Delbo’s Days and Memory and Ida Fink’s Selected Stories 大屠杀文学中时间与记忆的表现:夏洛特·德尔博的《日子与记忆》与艾达·芬克的《故事选集》比较
Pub Date : 2009-12-15 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL2009484
A. Pokhrel
The recent Holocaust testimonies are often disruptive narration of personal histories. In the form of memory, these testimonies capture survivors' experience of the Nazi Holocaust. As the survivor recalls his or her past experience in the present, "'[c]otemporality' becomes the controlling principle of these testimonies, as witnesses struggle with the impossible task of making their recollections of the camp experience coalesce with the rest of their lives." (1) The sense of time is deeply embedded in the survivor's consciousness. Caught between the transitions of past and present, the survivor becomes traumatized by his or her own anguish and the anguish of others. Hence, in these testimonies, the psychological association of events becomes more important than the chronological order of events. Original in its narrative technique and use of memory and time, Charlotte Delbo's posthumous memoir La memoire et les jours (translated as Days and Memory, 1985), is a complex reflection of the atrocious past. Auschwitz is fresh in Delbo's memory, and its horrifying images permeate her being in the present. So the present moment is not a simple point, but it has a certain extension and inner structure of its own. German philosopher Martin Heidegger has said that the reality of time is constructed not as something which we encounter only when we attempt to reckon it but as something which becomes operational within human existence. Similarly, Ida Fink, in her short stories "A Scrap of Time," "A Second Scrap of Time," and "Traces" (published in her anthologies Traces and A Scrap of Time and Other Stories), excavates the "ruins of memory" that invoke the devastating experiences of the Nazi Holocaust, which cannot be "measured in months and years" but can only be measured psychologically. (2) Interestingly enough, both Delbo and Fink focus on the intricate relations of past and present. In this respect, the principal question pertaining to this study would be: How are memory and time used in Delbo's memoir and Fink's stories in representing the Holocaust? Although Delbo and Fink both make use of memory and time in narrating the inhuman conditions of ghettoization, deportation, forced labor, roundups, and mass execution, their ways of representation vary significantly. Memory and time are used in Delbo to show the timelessness in complex layers of memory and to recreate a reality through inventive narrative style while in Fink they are used to delineate the scraps of time in the ruins of memory and to create a tragic domestic reality through conventional narrativity. Charlotte Delbo and Ida Fink both write in the present looking back at the past moments. Delbo writes from the cafe in France after many years of camp life, whereas Fink writes from Israel after many years of ghetto life. Both find their present self inextricably linked to the past self. Despite their recognition of the importance of remembering, Delbo and Fink both encounter a problem in conveyin
最近的大屠杀证词往往是对个人历史的破坏性叙述。这些证词以记忆的形式记录了幸存者对纳粹大屠杀的经历。当幸存者回忆起他或她现在的过去经历时,“‘暂时性’成为这些证词的控制原则,因为证人努力完成不可能完成的任务,使他们对集中营经历的回忆与他们生活的其余部分结合起来。”时间观念深深植根于幸存者的意识中。在过去和现在的过渡之间,幸存者因自己和他人的痛苦而受到创伤。因此,在这些证词中,事件的心理联系变得比事件的时间顺序更重要。夏洛特·德尔博的遗作《La memoire et les jours》(翻译为《日子与记忆》,1985年)在叙事技巧和对记忆和时间的运用上具有独创性,是对残暴过去的复杂反映。奥斯维辛在德尔博的记忆中是鲜活的,它的恐怖形象渗透在她现在的生活中。所以当下时刻不是一个简单的点,而是有一定的外延和自身的内在结构。德国哲学家马丁·海德格尔曾说过,时间的实在性不是我们在试图计算它时才遇到的东西,而是在人类存在中成为可操作的东西。同样,艾达·芬克(Ida Fink)在她的短篇小说《一小段时间》(A fragment of Time)、《第二段时间》(A Second fragment of Time)和《痕迹》(Traces)(发表在她的选集《痕迹》、《一小段时间》和《其他故事》中)中,挖掘了“记忆的废墟”,唤起了纳粹大屠杀的毁灭性经历,这些经历不能“用月和年来衡量”,只能从心理上衡量。(2)有趣的是,Delbo和Fink都关注过去和现在的复杂关系。在这方面,与这项研究有关的主要问题是:德尔博的回忆录和芬克的故事如何利用记忆和时间来代表大屠杀?尽管德尔博和芬克都利用记忆和时间来叙述种族隔离、驱逐、强迫劳动、围捕和大规模处决等不人道的条件,但他们的表现方式却大相径庭。在Delbo中,记忆和时间被用来在复杂的记忆层中表现出永恒,并通过创造性的叙事风格重新创造现实,而在Fink中,它们被用来描绘记忆废墟中的时间碎片,并通过传统叙事创造出悲惨的国内现实。夏洛特·德尔博和艾达·芬克都写在现在,回顾过去的时刻。德尔博在法国的咖啡馆里写了多年的集中营生活,而芬克在以色列写了多年的贫民窟生活。他们都发现现在的自己与过去的自己有着千丝万缕的联系。尽管德尔博和芬克认识到记忆的重要性,但他们都遇到了一个问题,即如何将他们的经验和知识作为连贯的历史真相传达给他人。然而,最重要的是,德尔博在奥斯维辛集中营的短暂经历与芬克在犹太人区的经历有很大不同。奥斯威辛根本没有时钟。德尔博在集中营里经历的唯一时间就是人类的时间。不像德尔博,芬克在贫民区可能对时间有更好的感觉。暴行的性质和其他情况也可能有所不同。在这里,人们不禁会想,集中营和隔都的不同情况可能是他们对时间和记忆的感知也不同的主要原因之一。在研究德尔博的《日子与记忆》和芬克精选的故事之前,我将简要地研究记忆和时间的一些重要理论立场,特别是它们与大屠杀文学的关系。著名学者劳伦斯·兰格在他的《大屠杀证词:记忆的废墟》中强调了证词中记忆的重要性,他说:“证词是一种记忆的形式。…
{"title":"Representations of Time and Memory in Holocaust Literature: A Comparison of Charlotte Delbo’s Days and Memory and Ida Fink’s Selected Stories","authors":"A. Pokhrel","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL2009484","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL2009484","url":null,"abstract":"The recent Holocaust testimonies are often disruptive narration of personal histories. In the form of memory, these testimonies capture survivors' experience of the Nazi Holocaust. As the survivor recalls his or her past experience in the present, \"'[c]otemporality' becomes the controlling principle of these testimonies, as witnesses struggle with the impossible task of making their recollections of the camp experience coalesce with the rest of their lives.\" (1) The sense of time is deeply embedded in the survivor's consciousness. Caught between the transitions of past and present, the survivor becomes traumatized by his or her own anguish and the anguish of others. Hence, in these testimonies, the psychological association of events becomes more important than the chronological order of events. Original in its narrative technique and use of memory and time, Charlotte Delbo's posthumous memoir La memoire et les jours (translated as Days and Memory, 1985), is a complex reflection of the atrocious past. Auschwitz is fresh in Delbo's memory, and its horrifying images permeate her being in the present. So the present moment is not a simple point, but it has a certain extension and inner structure of its own. German philosopher Martin Heidegger has said that the reality of time is constructed not as something which we encounter only when we attempt to reckon it but as something which becomes operational within human existence. Similarly, Ida Fink, in her short stories \"A Scrap of Time,\" \"A Second Scrap of Time,\" and \"Traces\" (published in her anthologies Traces and A Scrap of Time and Other Stories), excavates the \"ruins of memory\" that invoke the devastating experiences of the Nazi Holocaust, which cannot be \"measured in months and years\" but can only be measured psychologically. (2) Interestingly enough, both Delbo and Fink focus on the intricate relations of past and present. In this respect, the principal question pertaining to this study would be: How are memory and time used in Delbo's memoir and Fink's stories in representing the Holocaust? Although Delbo and Fink both make use of memory and time in narrating the inhuman conditions of ghettoization, deportation, forced labor, roundups, and mass execution, their ways of representation vary significantly. Memory and time are used in Delbo to show the timelessness in complex layers of memory and to recreate a reality through inventive narrative style while in Fink they are used to delineate the scraps of time in the ruins of memory and to create a tragic domestic reality through conventional narrativity. Charlotte Delbo and Ida Fink both write in the present looking back at the past moments. Delbo writes from the cafe in France after many years of camp life, whereas Fink writes from Israel after many years of ghetto life. Both find their present self inextricably linked to the past self. Despite their recognition of the importance of remembering, Delbo and Fink both encounter a problem in conveyin","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-12-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115676207","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Deleuze’s Concept of the Virtual and the Critique of the Possible 德勒兹的虚的概念与可能的批判
Pub Date : 2009-12-15 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094913
Daniel W. Smith
In this paper, I would simply like to sketch out what I take to be the component elements of Deleuze's concept of the virtual. (1) My thesis is this: Deleuze's philosophy can accurately be described as a transcendental philosophy--a transcendental empiricism, as he himself puts it--although Deleuze defines the transcendental field in a completely different manner than does Kant, who invented the term. Kant's genius, according to Deleuze, was to have conceived of a purely immanent critique of reason, a critique that did not seek, within reason, "errors" produced by external causes, but rather "illusions" that arise internally and inevitably from within reason itself by the illegitimate (that is, transcendent) uses of the syntheses. (2) Insofar as Deleuze conceives of philosophy as the construction of a plane of immanence, he aligns himself squarely with Kant's critical philosophy. (3) But he also criticizes Kant for having failed to fulfill the immanent ambitions of his critique, for reasons that we shall see in a moment. The difference does not lie simply in the fact that Deleuze purges the transcendental of any reference to consciousness or to a transcendental subject. The more important difference lies precisely in the distinction he makes between the possible and the virtual. For Deleuze, the transcendental does not serve to define the "conditions of possible experience" for a subject; on the contrary, it is a virtual field that serves as the genetic or productive condition of real experience, and that exists prior to the constitution of the subject. In what follows, I would like to draw out this difference between the possible and the virtual (as two conceptions of the transcendental) from the point of view of the history of philosophy: first, by examining two figures who seem to have influenced Deleuze most in this regard--Henri Bergson and Salomon Maimon; second, by examining the reading of Kant that Deleuze provides in Difference and Repetition; and finally, by briefly examining, as examples, Deleuze's analysis of three virtual structures, namely those of language, society, and the body. 1. Bergson's Problematization of the Possible. I turn first to Bergson. Deleuze derives the concept of the virtual directly from Bergson, and in a number of early articles (1956) he argues that Bergson forged the concept of the virtual by problematizing the notion of the possible. More precisely, the virtual is by nature problematizing; it expresses a problematic. What does he mean by this? The activity of thought is frequently conceived of as the search for solutions to problems, a prejudice whose roots, Deleuze suggests, are both social and pedagogical. In the classroom, it is the school teacher who poses ready-made problems, the pupil's task being to discover the correct solution, and what the notions of "true" and "false" serve to qualify are precisely these responses or solutions. Yet everyone recognizes that problems are never given ready-made but mu
在本文中,我想简单地勾勒出德勒兹虚拟概念的组成要素。(1)我的论点是这样的:德勒兹的哲学可以被准确地描述为一种先验哲学——一种先验的经验主义,正如他自己所说的那样——尽管德勒兹对先验领域的定义与发明了这个术语的康德完全不同。根据德勒兹的说法,康德的天才在于他构想了一种纯粹内在的理性批判,这种批判并不在理性内部寻找由外因产生的“错误”,而是在理性内部不可避免地通过非法(即超越)的综合使用而产生的“幻觉”。(2)就德勒兹认为哲学是一种内在层面的建构而言,他与康德的批判哲学是完全一致的。(3)但他也批评康德未能实现其批判的内在目标,其原因我们稍后将会看到。二者的区别并不仅仅在于德勒兹清除了对意识或先验主体的任何涉及。更重要的区别恰恰在于他对可能与虚拟的区分。对于德勒兹来说,先验并不用于定义主体的“可能经验条件”;相反,它是一个虚拟的领域,作为真实经验的遗传或生产条件,它先于主体的构成而存在。接下来,我想从哲学史的角度,画出可能与虚拟(作为先验的两个概念)之间的区别:首先,考察两个似乎在这方面对德勒兹影响最大的人物——亨利·柏格森和所罗门·迈蒙;第二,考察德勒兹在《差异与重复》中对康德的解读;最后,以德勒兹对语言、社会和身体三种虚拟结构的分析为例,进行简要的考察。1. 柏格森的《可能性的问题化》我首先转向柏格森。德勒兹直接从柏格森那里衍生出虚拟的概念,在1956年的一些早期文章中,他认为柏格森通过将可能的概念问题化来锻造虚拟的概念。更准确地说,虚拟本质上是有问题的;它表达了一个问题。他这话是什么意思?思想活动经常被认为是寻找问题的解决方案,德勒兹认为,这种偏见的根源是社会的和教育的。在课堂上,是学校老师提出现成的问题,学生的任务是找出正确的解决办法,而“真”和“假”的概念所限定的正是这些回答或解决办法。然而,每个人都认识到,问题从来不是现成的,而是必须自己构造或构成——因此,当考试中出现“错误”或表述不佳的问题时,就会出现丑闻。这并不是说解决方案不重要;反之,问题的解决才是最重要的,但正如德勒兹在他的著作中好几处所说的那样,一个问题的解决总是取决于它的表述方式,取决于我们用来表述它的手段和条件,也就是说,取决于它被确定为问题的条件。因此,“问题化”一个概念不仅意味着人们将其置于问题之中;它的意思是,一个人试图确定问题的本质,并以此作为解决方案。这就是问题化的过程如此复杂的原因。德勒兹写道:“对于问题已经陈述的解决方案,定义真假相对容易,但当它们直接应用于问题本身时,就很难说真假是由什么组成的了。”...
{"title":"Deleuze’s Concept of the Virtual and the Critique of the Possible","authors":"Daniel W. Smith","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094913","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094913","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, I would simply like to sketch out what I take to be the component elements of Deleuze's concept of the virtual. (1) My thesis is this: Deleuze's philosophy can accurately be described as a transcendental philosophy--a transcendental empiricism, as he himself puts it--although Deleuze defines the transcendental field in a completely different manner than does Kant, who invented the term. Kant's genius, according to Deleuze, was to have conceived of a purely immanent critique of reason, a critique that did not seek, within reason, \"errors\" produced by external causes, but rather \"illusions\" that arise internally and inevitably from within reason itself by the illegitimate (that is, transcendent) uses of the syntheses. (2) Insofar as Deleuze conceives of philosophy as the construction of a plane of immanence, he aligns himself squarely with Kant's critical philosophy. (3) But he also criticizes Kant for having failed to fulfill the immanent ambitions of his critique, for reasons that we shall see in a moment. The difference does not lie simply in the fact that Deleuze purges the transcendental of any reference to consciousness or to a transcendental subject. The more important difference lies precisely in the distinction he makes between the possible and the virtual. For Deleuze, the transcendental does not serve to define the \"conditions of possible experience\" for a subject; on the contrary, it is a virtual field that serves as the genetic or productive condition of real experience, and that exists prior to the constitution of the subject. In what follows, I would like to draw out this difference between the possible and the virtual (as two conceptions of the transcendental) from the point of view of the history of philosophy: first, by examining two figures who seem to have influenced Deleuze most in this regard--Henri Bergson and Salomon Maimon; second, by examining the reading of Kant that Deleuze provides in Difference and Repetition; and finally, by briefly examining, as examples, Deleuze's analysis of three virtual structures, namely those of language, society, and the body. 1. Bergson's Problematization of the Possible. I turn first to Bergson. Deleuze derives the concept of the virtual directly from Bergson, and in a number of early articles (1956) he argues that Bergson forged the concept of the virtual by problematizing the notion of the possible. More precisely, the virtual is by nature problematizing; it expresses a problematic. What does he mean by this? The activity of thought is frequently conceived of as the search for solutions to problems, a prejudice whose roots, Deleuze suggests, are both social and pedagogical. In the classroom, it is the school teacher who poses ready-made problems, the pupil's task being to discover the correct solution, and what the notions of \"true\" and \"false\" serve to qualify are precisely these responses or solutions. Yet everyone recognizes that problems are never given ready-made but mu","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"108 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-12-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121774845","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 13
African Philosophy as the Practice of Resistance 作为抵抗实践的非洲哲学
Pub Date : 2009-12-15 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094914
T. Serequeberhan
In what follows I will present my views regarding the questions, and areas of concern, that are of fundamental importance to the contemporary discourse/practice of African philosophy. I will present a programmatic statement of what I take to be a form of resistance in the realm of theory. And so, in keeping with the above, I will explore and concretely engage three interconnected and nodal points: 1. the indigenous re-orientation of philosophic work 2. the critique of Eurocentrism 3. and the question of our "generic human identity" The concerns expressed in the above three points are, in my view, crucial issues that warrant on-going discussion and debate. In examining them my hope is to further develop their articulation in view of making their importance more palpable and pressing. (2) For, it is out of such efforts that we can better grasp, and possibly participate in changing, our dismal contemporary neo-colonial situation located in-between (3) our former status of colonial subjects and our present wretched condition of being dependent formerly colonized peoples. It is this dismal and barren in-between, which constitutes our lived present. Our postcolonial situation, to properly be such, has to put in question this colonial residue-the in-between-ness of our present. 1. We are today, at the end first decade of the 21st century, at a point in time when the concrete dominance of the universe of Euro-American singularity is being encompassed, or engulfed, by the multi-verse of our shared humanity. In this context, the central concern for the practice of philosophy focused on the formerly colonized world should be directed at helping to create a situation in which the enduring residue of the colonial past is systematically put in question. For, even if, at the end of the first decade of the 21st century, we are beyond the "Age of Europe" (4) yet, every aspect of our existence in the formerly colonized world is still-in essential and fundamental ways-determined and controlled by our former colonizers. I say this not in order to shift blame but to locate specifically the source of our present predicament, not only as regards our economic and political dependence on the West, but also as regards the basic dependent orientation of our theoretic efforts. Indeed, as Paulin J. Hountondji has correctly noted: "Historically, science and technology, in their present form on the African continent, can be traced back to the colonial period." (5) In today's Africa, the practice of science, technology, and theoretic work in general--as conducted in African universities and research centers, such as they are--continues, in the same vein, as during colonial times. How this practice might be changed, in view of present needs, is a question that is seldom, if ever, asked! As Hountondji points out, this deplorable situation is taken "for granted" (6) and as "normal" by those engaged in scientific work. Now, this "subjective" acceptance and internalization of coloni
在接下来的内容中,我将阐述我对当代非洲哲学话语/实践中具有根本重要性的问题和关注领域的看法。我将提出一个纲领性的陈述,我认为这是理论领域中的一种抵抗形式。因此,为了与上述观点保持一致,我将探讨并具体涉及三个相互关联的节点:哲学工作的本土再定位2。对欧洲中心主义的批判;在我看来,上述三点所表达的关切是值得持续讨论和辩论的关键问题。在研究它们时,我希望进一步发展它们的清晰度,使它们的重要性更加明显和紧迫。(2)因为,正是通过这样的努力,我们才能更好地把握,并有可能参与改变我们处于(3)我们以前作为殖民地臣民的地位和我们现在作为前殖民地人民的依附性的悲惨状况之间的凄惨的当代新殖民主义局面。正是这种凄凉而贫瘠的中间地带,构成了我们活生生的现在。我们的后殖民时期的情况,恰当地说,必须对殖民时期的残余——我们现在的中间状态——提出质疑。1. 今天,在21世纪第一个十年的末尾,我们正处在这样一个时间点上,欧美奇点宇宙的具体主导地位正在被我们共同的人类的多元宇宙所包围或吞没。在这方面,以前殖民地世界为中心的哲学实践的中心关注应该是帮助创造一种局面,在这种局面中,殖民地历史的持久残余受到系统的质疑。因为,即使在21世纪的第一个十年结束时,我们已经超越了“欧洲时代”,但我们在前殖民地世界生存的每一个方面——在本质上和根本上——仍然由我们的前殖民者决定和控制。我说这些不是为了推卸责任,而是为了明确地找到我们目前困境的根源,不仅是关于我们对西方的经济和政治依赖,而且还有关于我们理论努力的基本依赖取向。事实上,正如Paulin J. Hountondji正确地指出的那样:“从历史上看,科学和技术,在非洲大陆上的目前形式,可以追溯到殖民时期。”(5)在今天的非洲,科学、技术和理论工作的实践——就像在非洲大学和研究中心所进行的那样——以同样的方式继续着,就像在殖民时期一样。鉴于目前的需要,如何改变这种做法,是一个很少被问到的问题!正如Hountondji所指出的那样,这种令人遗憾的情况被从事科学工作的人视为“理所当然”和“正常”。现在,在“新”条件下,这种对殖民霸权的“主观”接受和内化——我们当前的新殖民主义的中间性——有其具体的“客观”关联(7):[T]历史整合和隶属于……(我们的知识体系)……对于知识和“技术诀窍”的世界体系来说,作为一个整体,同样不发达的结果,主要不是由于任何原始的落后,而是由于我们的自给经济融入了世界资本主义市场。(8)在主观方面,在能动性方面,这个等式——我们社会的具体的、物质的从属关系,它使我们成为“世界知识体系”的多余附属物——在未来被一种“意识形态……(9)它是西化非洲的主体性、有意识的自我意识(即思维)的活矩阵。正如伊曼纽尔·沃勒斯坦所指出的;普遍主义是一种信仰,也是一种认识论。…
{"title":"African Philosophy as the Practice of Resistance","authors":"T. Serequeberhan","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094914","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094914","url":null,"abstract":"In what follows I will present my views regarding the questions, and areas of concern, that are of fundamental importance to the contemporary discourse/practice of African philosophy. I will present a programmatic statement of what I take to be a form of resistance in the realm of theory. And so, in keeping with the above, I will explore and concretely engage three interconnected and nodal points: 1. the indigenous re-orientation of philosophic work 2. the critique of Eurocentrism 3. and the question of our \"generic human identity\" The concerns expressed in the above three points are, in my view, crucial issues that warrant on-going discussion and debate. In examining them my hope is to further develop their articulation in view of making their importance more palpable and pressing. (2) For, it is out of such efforts that we can better grasp, and possibly participate in changing, our dismal contemporary neo-colonial situation located in-between (3) our former status of colonial subjects and our present wretched condition of being dependent formerly colonized peoples. It is this dismal and barren in-between, which constitutes our lived present. Our postcolonial situation, to properly be such, has to put in question this colonial residue-the in-between-ness of our present. 1. We are today, at the end first decade of the 21st century, at a point in time when the concrete dominance of the universe of Euro-American singularity is being encompassed, or engulfed, by the multi-verse of our shared humanity. In this context, the central concern for the practice of philosophy focused on the formerly colonized world should be directed at helping to create a situation in which the enduring residue of the colonial past is systematically put in question. For, even if, at the end of the first decade of the 21st century, we are beyond the \"Age of Europe\" (4) yet, every aspect of our existence in the formerly colonized world is still-in essential and fundamental ways-determined and controlled by our former colonizers. I say this not in order to shift blame but to locate specifically the source of our present predicament, not only as regards our economic and political dependence on the West, but also as regards the basic dependent orientation of our theoretic efforts. Indeed, as Paulin J. Hountondji has correctly noted: \"Historically, science and technology, in their present form on the African continent, can be traced back to the colonial period.\" (5) In today's Africa, the practice of science, technology, and theoretic work in general--as conducted in African universities and research centers, such as they are--continues, in the same vein, as during colonial times. How this practice might be changed, in view of present needs, is a question that is seldom, if ever, asked! As Hountondji points out, this deplorable situation is taken \"for granted\" (6) and as \"normal\" by those engaged in scientific work. Now, this \"subjective\" acceptance and internalization of coloni","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"130 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-12-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131741723","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Mimesis in Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory 阿多诺美学理论中的模仿
Pub Date : 2009-12-15 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL2009481
Bed P. Paudyal
Theodor W. Adorno's reflections on literature and the arts are spread over several of his works, but his "systematic" and comprehensive theorization of art (including literature) was to wait until Aesthetic Theory, which Adorno did not live to complete. However, as the editors of the original German edition, Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedeman, quote Adorno (from a letter he wrote "several days before his death"), "the final version 'still needed a desperate effort' but ... 'basically it is now a matter of organization and hardly that of the substance of the book'"; (1) it is not inappropriate to rely on Aesthetic Theory as repository of Adorno's thought on the subject of art and literature. Supplementing its "reading" with relevant chapters from Adorno's other works -Dialectic of Enlightenment (which he coauthored with Max Horkheimer), Prisms, and Notes to Literature)-this essay concentrates on the concept of mimesis in Adorno's theory of arts and literature in order to examine the various meanings Adorno assigns to that concept as well as the "constellations" in which this concept articulates with other concepts. Since Adorno's aesthetic theory forms a coherent part of his overall philosophical enterprise, the strategy used here is to discuss briefly some key concepts constitutive of Adorno's critique of philosophy and of Capitalist society, and then zero in on the concept of mimesis. Adorno was a leading member of the Frankfurt School-an institute that championed "critical theory," which attempted to "grasp contemporary society and culture as a totality," espoused "unity of theory and praxis," and critiqued instrumental rationality. (2) Key to Adorno's thinking, as to the Frankfurt School's, were Marx's concept of commodity fetishism and Georg Lukacs's concept of reification. Commodity fetishism names the enigma in Capitalist society, where the value of the commodity as the product of social labor appears as the value of the commodity itself just as the relation between human beings essential to the production and exchange of commodities appears as the relation between commodities themselves. In other words, commodities become fetishes because they seem to acquire a life of their own. (3) Lukacs's theory of reification extends Marx's concept of commodity fetishism, via Max Weber's theory of rationalization, to argue that not only the economic sphere (in Marxist base-superstructure model, the socio-economic base comprising of the forces and relations of production) but "social institutions such as law, administration, and journalism" and "academic disciplines such as economics, jurisprudence, and philosophy" also become permeated by the commodity form or the logic of exchange. Indeed, according to Lukacs, commodity fetishism governs not only the objects in the world but equally the subjects, who are reduced to exchangeable commodities, "like mere things obeying the inexorable laws of the marketplace." (4) Adorno's favorite word for the total reific
阿多诺对文学和艺术的思考贯穿在他的几部作品中,但他对艺术(包括文学)的“系统”和全面的理论化是等到《美学理论》之后才出现的,而阿多诺并没有活着完成《美学理论》。然而,正如德文版的编辑格莱特·阿多诺(Gretel Adorno)和罗尔夫·蒂德曼(Rolf Tiedeman)引用阿多诺的话(摘自他“死前几天”写的一封信),“最终版本‘仍然需要绝望的努力’,但是……'现在基本上是组织问题,而不是书的内容问题'";(1)将《美学理论》作为阿多诺关于艺术与文学主题的思想宝库,并非不恰当。补充了阿多诺其他作品的相关章节——《启蒙辩证法》(他与马克斯·霍克海默合著)、《棱镜》和《文学笔记》——这篇文章集中在阿多诺艺术和文学理论中的模仿概念上,以检验阿多诺赋予这个概念的各种含义,以及这个概念与其他概念相结合的“星座”。由于阿多诺的美学理论构成了他整个哲学事业的一个连贯部分,这里使用的策略是简要讨论构成阿多诺对哲学和资本主义社会批判的一些关键概念,然后将重点放在模仿的概念上。阿多诺是法兰克福学派的主要成员,该学派倡导“批判理论”,试图“将当代社会和文化作为一个整体来把握”,支持“理论与实践的统一”,并批评工具理性。(2)与法兰克福学派一样,阿多诺思想的关键是马克思的商品拜物教概念和卢卡奇的物化概念。商品拜物教指出了资本主义社会中的一个谜,在这个谜中,作为社会劳动产物的商品价值表现为商品本身的价值,正如对商品生产和交换至关重要的人与人之间的关系表现为商品本身之间的关系一样。换句话说,商品之所以成为恋物,是因为它们似乎获得了自己的生命。(3)卢卡奇的物化理论通过马克斯·韦伯的理性化理论扩展了马克思的商品拜物教概念,认为不仅经济领域(在马克思主义的基础-上层建筑模型中,由生产力和生产关系组成的社会经济基础),而且“法律、行政和新闻等社会机构”和“经济学、法学等学术学科”哲学也被商品形式或交换逻辑所渗透。事实上,根据卢卡奇的观点,商品拜物教不仅支配着世界上的客体,也同样支配着主体,这些主体被简化为可交换的商品,“就像服从无情的市场法则的纯粹事物”。(4)阿多诺最喜欢用“被管理的世界”来形容资本主义下社会的整体物化,这个词在《美学理论》和他的其他作品中反复出现。因此,在《文化批判与社会》中,阿多诺描述了物化的总体化和极权主义的影响:这种管制,是所有人类关系的进步社会化的结果,并不是简单地从外部面对心灵;它迁移到其内在的一致性....以交换行为为模型,整体的网络变得越来越紧密。它使个体意识逃避的余地越来越小,使个体意识表现得越来越彻底,先验地切断了个体意识与自身差别的可能性,因为一切差别都在供给的单调中退化为细微差别。(5)因此,笛卡尔关于思维的自我与扩展的实在的区分,即使曾经成立,也不再成立了;主体不是从一个超越客体的位置来面对客体,而是被卷入“整体的网络”中,没有给真正的差异和自主性留下空间。...
{"title":"Mimesis in Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory","authors":"Bed P. Paudyal","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL2009481","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL2009481","url":null,"abstract":"Theodor W. Adorno's reflections on literature and the arts are spread over several of his works, but his \"systematic\" and comprehensive theorization of art (including literature) was to wait until Aesthetic Theory, which Adorno did not live to complete. However, as the editors of the original German edition, Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedeman, quote Adorno (from a letter he wrote \"several days before his death\"), \"the final version 'still needed a desperate effort' but ... 'basically it is now a matter of organization and hardly that of the substance of the book'\"; (1) it is not inappropriate to rely on Aesthetic Theory as repository of Adorno's thought on the subject of art and literature. Supplementing its \"reading\" with relevant chapters from Adorno's other works -Dialectic of Enlightenment (which he coauthored with Max Horkheimer), Prisms, and Notes to Literature)-this essay concentrates on the concept of mimesis in Adorno's theory of arts and literature in order to examine the various meanings Adorno assigns to that concept as well as the \"constellations\" in which this concept articulates with other concepts. Since Adorno's aesthetic theory forms a coherent part of his overall philosophical enterprise, the strategy used here is to discuss briefly some key concepts constitutive of Adorno's critique of philosophy and of Capitalist society, and then zero in on the concept of mimesis. Adorno was a leading member of the Frankfurt School-an institute that championed \"critical theory,\" which attempted to \"grasp contemporary society and culture as a totality,\" espoused \"unity of theory and praxis,\" and critiqued instrumental rationality. (2) Key to Adorno's thinking, as to the Frankfurt School's, were Marx's concept of commodity fetishism and Georg Lukacs's concept of reification. Commodity fetishism names the enigma in Capitalist society, where the value of the commodity as the product of social labor appears as the value of the commodity itself just as the relation between human beings essential to the production and exchange of commodities appears as the relation between commodities themselves. In other words, commodities become fetishes because they seem to acquire a life of their own. (3) Lukacs's theory of reification extends Marx's concept of commodity fetishism, via Max Weber's theory of rationalization, to argue that not only the economic sphere (in Marxist base-superstructure model, the socio-economic base comprising of the forces and relations of production) but \"social institutions such as law, administration, and journalism\" and \"academic disciplines such as economics, jurisprudence, and philosophy\" also become permeated by the commodity form or the logic of exchange. Indeed, according to Lukacs, commodity fetishism governs not only the objects in the world but equally the subjects, who are reduced to exchangeable commodities, \"like mere things obeying the inexorable laws of the marketplace.\" (4) Adorno's favorite word for the total reific","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-12-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130600921","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
XXII World Congress of Philosophy and Nepali Representation 第二十二届世界哲学大会和尼泊尔代表大会
Pub Date : 2009-12-15 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094833
Yubraj Aryal
This year's XXII World Congress of Philosophy met on July 30-August 05 in Korea under the Congress's theme " Rethinking Philosophy Today." This is a congress which meets every five years. Last time it met in 2003 in Turkey and the next time will be in Greece, the homeland of philosophy indeed, in 2013. Philosophers and philosophy teachers from more than eighty-two countries participated in this quintessential philosophy congress. Most of them including myself presented papers at a series of different sessions. Almost all of the rest of the countries except my own country had more than one delegate. I was the single delegate from Nepal. This speaks much about ourselves besides the fact of our economic hardship, because participation from 'poor' countries like Ethiopia, Sudan, and Nigeria included more than a single delegate. Despite some bitter feelings about our backwardness, I represented my country with a high feeling. The XXII Congress was important for us Asians, because it is the first ever of these congresses to have met on Asian soil in the long history of its one hundred and eight years. It was an opportunity to display the beauty and strength of our philosophical systems and traditions to the global communities. The heavy presence of philosophers from China, India, Japan and Korea definitively asserted what was Asian in the congress. Nepali representation at such a historic congress was very crucial for the promotion of the Nepali image in the global intellectual community, and I was very conscious of this fact. Who we are matters in how far we engage in dialogue with the global community. Our long isolationism can no longer help us to define who we are. For the first time in the history of the Nepali philosophical tradition, I stood high in front of a colorful gathering of very distinguished philosophers and spoke in a Nepali voice about our interest in the establishment of a cooperative society for philosophy and humanistic studies in South Asia. I was quite aware that we alone could do nothing unless intellectual colleagues of our neighboring countries extended their helping hands. But I was proud when Professor Bhuvan Chandel, current Secretary of the Centre for Studies in Civilizations in New Delhi, embraced me saying "Nepal is our identity!" after the gathering. At least we could make our presence and influences known and felt to our own Indian counterparts. Finally, I realized that the global community (although we can question the validity of such a community) is welcoming us to come up with our own voice. They are sympathetic to listening to our voice. How much we want to come out of our 'exotic' hibernation depends on us. Whether we want to maintain same past isolationism in a kind of illusory prelapsarian bliss, or whether we want to come up to the global front is up to us. Keeping the local sovereignty intact and letting it interact with the global is a need of every society today. To initiate a dialogue with the global does
今年的第22届世界哲学大会于7月30日至8月5日在韩国举行,大会的主题是“重新思考今天的哲学”。这是每五年召开一次的代表大会。上一次会议于2003年在土耳其举行,下一次将于2013年在哲学之乡希腊举行。来自超过82个国家的哲学家和哲学教师参加了这次典型的哲学大会。他们中的大多数人,包括我自己,在一系列不同的会议上发表了论文。除了我国以外,几乎所有其他国家都有不止一名代表。我是唯一来自尼泊尔的代表。这不仅说明了我们的经济困难,还说明了我们自己的情况,因为来自埃塞俄比亚、苏丹和尼日利亚等“贫穷”国家的与会代表不止一人。尽管对我们的落后有一些怨恨,但我以一种崇高的感情代表我的国家。第二十二届代表大会对我们亚洲人来说很重要,因为这是在其108年的漫长历史中第一次在亚洲土地上召开的代表大会。这是一个向全球社区展示我们哲学体系和传统的美丽和力量的机会。来自中国、印度、日本和韩国的哲学家的大量出席,明确地表明了大会的亚洲特色。在这样一个具有历史意义的大会上,尼泊尔的代表对于提升尼泊尔在全球知识界的形象至关重要,我非常清楚这一点。我们是谁关系到我们在多大程度上参与与全球社会的对话。我们长期的孤立主义再也不能帮助我们定义我们是谁。在尼泊尔哲学传统的历史上,我第一次高高站在一群色彩缤纷的杰出哲学家面前,用尼泊尔人的声音讲述了我们对在南亚建立一个哲学和人文主义研究合作协会的兴趣。我很清楚,如果邻国的知识分子不伸出援助之手,我们自己是无能为力的。但当新德里文明研究中心现任秘书布万·昌德尔教授在聚会结束后拥抱我说“尼泊尔是我们的身份”时,我感到自豪。至少我们可以让我们的印度同行知道和感受到我们的存在和影响。最后,我意识到全球社区(尽管我们可以质疑这样一个社区的有效性)欢迎我们发出自己的声音。他们愿意倾听我们的声音。我们有多想摆脱“异国情调”的冬眠取决于我们自己。我们是想在一种虚幻的堕落前的幸福中保持过去的孤立主义,还是想站到全球的前沿,这取决于我们自己。保持地方主权完整,使其与全球互动,是当今每个社会的需要。发起与全球的对话并不一定意味着西方化。不幸的是,我们的一些人仍然受到这种普遍误解的困扰。在我看来,事实是我们必须适当地与全球互动,不仅要抵制我们不是的东西,还要在文化和社会上坚持我们是什么。...
{"title":"XXII World Congress of Philosophy and Nepali Representation","authors":"Yubraj Aryal","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094833","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20094833","url":null,"abstract":"This year's XXII World Congress of Philosophy met on July 30-August 05 in Korea under the Congress's theme \" Rethinking Philosophy Today.\" This is a congress which meets every five years. Last time it met in 2003 in Turkey and the next time will be in Greece, the homeland of philosophy indeed, in 2013. Philosophers and philosophy teachers from more than eighty-two countries participated in this quintessential philosophy congress. Most of them including myself presented papers at a series of different sessions. Almost all of the rest of the countries except my own country had more than one delegate. I was the single delegate from Nepal. This speaks much about ourselves besides the fact of our economic hardship, because participation from 'poor' countries like Ethiopia, Sudan, and Nigeria included more than a single delegate. Despite some bitter feelings about our backwardness, I represented my country with a high feeling. The XXII Congress was important for us Asians, because it is the first ever of these congresses to have met on Asian soil in the long history of its one hundred and eight years. It was an opportunity to display the beauty and strength of our philosophical systems and traditions to the global communities. The heavy presence of philosophers from China, India, Japan and Korea definitively asserted what was Asian in the congress. Nepali representation at such a historic congress was very crucial for the promotion of the Nepali image in the global intellectual community, and I was very conscious of this fact. Who we are matters in how far we engage in dialogue with the global community. Our long isolationism can no longer help us to define who we are. For the first time in the history of the Nepali philosophical tradition, I stood high in front of a colorful gathering of very distinguished philosophers and spoke in a Nepali voice about our interest in the establishment of a cooperative society for philosophy and humanistic studies in South Asia. I was quite aware that we alone could do nothing unless intellectual colleagues of our neighboring countries extended their helping hands. But I was proud when Professor Bhuvan Chandel, current Secretary of the Centre for Studies in Civilizations in New Delhi, embraced me saying \"Nepal is our identity!\" after the gathering. At least we could make our presence and influences known and felt to our own Indian counterparts. Finally, I realized that the global community (although we can question the validity of such a community) is welcoming us to come up with our own voice. They are sympathetic to listening to our voice. How much we want to come out of our 'exotic' hibernation depends on us. Whether we want to maintain same past isolationism in a kind of illusory prelapsarian bliss, or whether we want to come up to the global front is up to us. Keeping the local sovereignty intact and letting it interact with the global is a need of every society today. To initiate a dialogue with the global does ","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-12-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127331289","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1