首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry最新文献

英文 中文
Leibniz and Newton on Space, Time and the Trinity 莱布尼茨和牛顿的空间,时间和三位一体论
Pub Date : 2011-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171614
P. Redding
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, who was born in 1646 just before the end of the Thirty Years War and who died 1716, is surely one of the most bizarre and interesting of the early modern philosophers. He was an astonishing polymath, and responsible for some of the most advanced work in the sciences of his day--he was, for instance, the co-inventor along with Newton, of differential calculus, and is generally recognized as the greatest logician of the early modern period, responsible for advances in logic not rivaled until the mid-nineteenth century. But this progressive aspect of Leibniz's thought is paired by one that was more backward looking, deeply engaged with pre-modern forms of thinking that referred back through Medieval culture to the philosophy of ancient times. And alongside of his scientific advances, he is known for having created one of the most baroque and puzzling metaphysical systems in the history of philosophy--the so-called "Monadology". For much of his life he was also absorbed in theological disputes that have now been long been forgotten, and generally thought of as alien to modern scientific modes of thought. But it is easy to fall into anachronistic assumptions here. First, historians of the early modern period point to the degree that scientific and theological issues were virtually inseparable during much of this period. Even in the case of Newton, it would seem, he was forced to trade in ideas of very questionable provenance in order to come up with his revolutionary achievements in natural science. But if we further concentrate not on the development within formal or empirical sciences but on questions of a distinctly philosophical nature, Leibniz seems to further complicate assumptions about the unidirectional nature of intellectual progress. While many of his contemporaries saw progress as involving a break with the past, and especially the Aristotelianism that came from the scholastic period, Leibniz did not see the task as one of breaking with ancient philosophical thought, but as integrating it with modern scientific advances. Today I would like to attempt to bring some of the ways in which Leibniz's scientific, philosophical and theological views were bound up with each other by briefly examining his roles within two apparently different disputes in the late 17th and early 18th centuries: first his dispute with Newton over the nature of space and time; and next his dispute with the "Socinian" followers of Faustus Socinus (1539-1604), (a religious movement that later came to be called "Unitarianism"), over the doctrine of the trinity. (1) These may seem to be unrelated, but they might be connected in interesting ways. First, Leibniz's dispute with Newton over space and time had, as we will see, overtly theological aspects. Furthermore, as we now know, Newton had himself been a secret critic of the doctrine of the Trinity. (2) We might then wonder if there is a relation between Leibniz's attitude to Newton on the issue
戈特弗里德·威廉·莱布尼茨(Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz)出生于1646年,就在三十年战争结束前,于1716年去世。他无疑是早期现代哲学家中最离奇、最有趣的人之一。他是一个惊人的博学家,在他那个时代的科学中,他做出了一些最先进的工作——例如,他与牛顿共同发明了微分学,被普遍认为是近代早期最伟大的逻辑学家,他在逻辑学方面取得的进步直到19世纪中叶才被人匹敌。但是莱布尼茨思想中进步的一面与另一方面相辅相成的是更向后看的一面,与前现代的思想形式密切相关,这些思想形式可以追溯到中世纪文化和古代哲学。除了科学上的进步,他还创造了哲学史上最巴洛克、最令人费解的形而上学体系之一——所谓的“一元论”。在他一生的大部分时间里,他还专注于神学争论,这些争论现在早已被人遗忘,而且通常被认为与现代科学思维模式格格不入。但在这里很容易陷入时代错误的假设。首先,早期现代历史学家指出,在这一时期的大部分时间里,科学问题和神学问题实际上是不可分割的。即使是牛顿,为了在自然科学领域取得革命性的成就,他似乎也被迫放弃了一些来源非常可疑的想法。但是,如果我们不再关注形式科学或经验科学内部的发展,而是关注具有明显哲学性质的问题,莱布尼茨似乎将有关智力进步单向性的假设进一步复杂化。莱布尼茨同时代的许多人认为进步是与过去的决裂,尤其是与来自经院时期的亚里士多德主义决裂,但莱布尼茨并不认为这是与古代哲学思想决裂的任务之一,而是将其与现代科学进步相结合。今天,我想通过简要考察莱布尼茨在17世纪末和18世纪初两场明显不同的争论中所扮演的角色,来介绍莱布尼茨的科学、哲学和神学观点是如何相互联系在一起的:首先,他与牛顿关于空间和时间本质的争论;其次是他与浮士德·索西纳斯(1539-1604)的“索西尼派”追随者(一种后来被称为“一神论”的宗教运动)在三位一体教义上的争论。这些可能看起来毫无关联,但它们可能以有趣的方式联系在一起。首先,莱布尼茨与牛顿关于空间和时间的争论,我们将会看到,带有明显的神学色彩。此外,正如我们现在所知,牛顿自己也曾秘密地批评过三位一体学说。(2)那么,我们也许会想,莱布尼茨在空间和时间问题上对牛顿的态度,与他在三位一体问题上对社会主义者的态度,两者之间是否有某种关系。我认为这两者之间确实存在联系,这种联系与心智的对立概念及其在两种争论中隐含的运作有关。莱布尼茨对牛顿和社会主义者共同的上帝观的批判标志着对主流的神性观念的挑战,毕竟,人类是按照上帝的形象被创造出来的,神性观念的变化将会反映在人类的观念中。但这是一个面向过去的挑战,吸引了更老的观念。尽管如此,我相信,在莱布尼茨的思想中,我们可以看到一些后来的,更进步的思想描述,就像在费希特和黑格尔等后康德唯心主义者中发现的那样。这些描述是为了超越现代早期标准的“非唯物主义”和“唯物主义”替代方案,采取人类思想的方法。…
{"title":"Leibniz and Newton on Space, Time and the Trinity","authors":"P. Redding","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171614","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171614","url":null,"abstract":"Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, who was born in 1646 just before the end of the Thirty Years War and who died 1716, is surely one of the most bizarre and interesting of the early modern philosophers. He was an astonishing polymath, and responsible for some of the most advanced work in the sciences of his day--he was, for instance, the co-inventor along with Newton, of differential calculus, and is generally recognized as the greatest logician of the early modern period, responsible for advances in logic not rivaled until the mid-nineteenth century. But this progressive aspect of Leibniz's thought is paired by one that was more backward looking, deeply engaged with pre-modern forms of thinking that referred back through Medieval culture to the philosophy of ancient times. And alongside of his scientific advances, he is known for having created one of the most baroque and puzzling metaphysical systems in the history of philosophy--the so-called \"Monadology\". For much of his life he was also absorbed in theological disputes that have now been long been forgotten, and generally thought of as alien to modern scientific modes of thought. But it is easy to fall into anachronistic assumptions here. First, historians of the early modern period point to the degree that scientific and theological issues were virtually inseparable during much of this period. Even in the case of Newton, it would seem, he was forced to trade in ideas of very questionable provenance in order to come up with his revolutionary achievements in natural science. But if we further concentrate not on the development within formal or empirical sciences but on questions of a distinctly philosophical nature, Leibniz seems to further complicate assumptions about the unidirectional nature of intellectual progress. While many of his contemporaries saw progress as involving a break with the past, and especially the Aristotelianism that came from the scholastic period, Leibniz did not see the task as one of breaking with ancient philosophical thought, but as integrating it with modern scientific advances. Today I would like to attempt to bring some of the ways in which Leibniz's scientific, philosophical and theological views were bound up with each other by briefly examining his roles within two apparently different disputes in the late 17th and early 18th centuries: first his dispute with Newton over the nature of space and time; and next his dispute with the \"Socinian\" followers of Faustus Socinus (1539-1604), (a religious movement that later came to be called \"Unitarianism\"), over the doctrine of the trinity. (1) These may seem to be unrelated, but they might be connected in interesting ways. First, Leibniz's dispute with Newton over space and time had, as we will see, overtly theological aspects. Furthermore, as we now know, Newton had himself been a secret critic of the doctrine of the Trinity. (2) We might then wonder if there is a relation between Leibniz's attitude to Newton on the issue ","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"22 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122961375","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Stephane Mallarme's Un Coup De Des and the Poem And/as Book as Diagram Stephane Mallarme的《一场政变》和《诗与书如图》
Pub Date : 2011-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171612
J. Drucker
Few works of poetry have made a more dramatic case for the poem and/as book as a diagrammatic expression than Stephane Mallarme's renowned Un Coup de Des. (1) Initially issued in the May 1897 issue of the British publication, Cosmopolis, the work was produced in a second edition by the Nouvelle Revue Francaise in 1914. That later edition is considered by most Mallarme scholars to more closely resemble the manuscript and instructions conceived by the poet in advance of his death in 1898. Paul Valery saw those manuscripts, lying on a window sill at the house in which he visited the aging poet. (2) Valery left a suggestive, rather than detailed, description of those papers covered with calligraphic glyphs anticipating the typographic treatment Mallarme envisioned for the work. Photocopies have been published of the marked up manuscript, itself in the collection of the Bibliotheque Nationale in Paris, but even that is still an unreliable testimonial for editorial events that might have followed had the poet lived to see the project finished. An edition created by Michael Pierson and published in 2004 by Ptyx attempts a most faithful rendering of the edition originally planned by Ambrose Vollard. Discussions of the poem are always subject to qualification, therefore, since the work does not exist in any form authorized by Mallarme or produced under his final supervision. Further and final changes or alterations to either the textual composition or its graphical expression could have entered in the process, and so we have to qualify all critical discussion by an understanding that the "poem" in question is only tentatively the work Mallarme imagined. Such reservations are more appropriate to this poem than to many others, however, since its fundamental tensions are dynamic ones that circle around questions of being and nothing, chance and constellationary order, and the human "master" who struggles to mediate sense within the ongoing conflicts of these conditions. Because the poem is so completely about this process, as well as embodying and expressing it, the character of self-referentiality implodes in a state of dynamic incompleteness that is only further sustained by the fact that we are engaging in a state of the poem that is neither final nor definitive. The Cosmopolis and N.R.F. editions of 1897 and 1914 offer points of departure. The spatial drama of the work is evident in all its iterations, and the intention on the part of the author to articulate the poem within and across the spaces of a book is clear. And it is that specific attention to spatial and graphical articulation that makes Un Coup de Des the unique example that proves a significant point: that poems are, by their nature, structure, and expression, diagrammatic works par excellence. They are literary works whose meaning depends upon the spatialized relations of embodied in their texts and whose spatial relations are rendered meaningful by their graphical expression. Rather than co
很少有诗歌作品比斯蒂芬·马拉美著名的《一场政变》(Un Coup de Des)更具戏剧性地将这首诗和/或一本书作为一种生动的表达方式。(1)这部作品最初发表在1897年5月的英国出版物《大都会》(cosmopolitan)上,1914年由法国新评论社(Nouvelle Revue Francaise)再版。大多数马拉美学者认为,后来的版本更接近于这位诗人在1898年去世前构思的手稿和指示。保罗·瓦莱里(Paul Valery)在他拜访这位年迈诗人的房子里看到了这些手稿,它们躺在窗台上。(2)瓦莱里留下了一个暗示性的,而不是详细的描述,这些纸上覆盖着书法字形,预示着马拉美为这部作品设想的排版处理。已经出版了带有标记的手稿的影印本,它本身在巴黎国家图书馆的收藏中,但即使如此,对于编辑事件来说,如果诗人活着看到这个项目完成,这仍然是一个不可靠的证据。由迈克尔·皮尔森(Michael Pierson)创作并于2004年由Ptyx出版的版本试图最忠实地呈现安布罗斯·沃拉德(Ambrose Vollard)最初计划的版本。因此,对这首诗的讨论总是受到限制的,因为这部作品不是以马拉梅授权的任何形式存在的,也不是在他的最终监督下创作的。在这个过程中,对文本构成或图形表达的进一步和最终的改变或改变可能已经进入,因此,我们必须通过这样一种理解来限定所有的批判性讨论,即所讨论的“诗”只是马拉美想象的作品。然而,这种保留更适合这首诗,因为它的基本张力是动态的,围绕着存在与虚无、机会和星座秩序的问题,以及在这些条件下持续冲突中努力调解感觉的人类“主人”。因为这首诗完全是关于这个过程的,同时也体现和表达了这个过程,自我指涉的特征在一种动态的不完整状态中内爆了,这种不完整状态只有在我们参与到一种既不是最终的也不是决定性的诗歌状态中这一事实才会进一步得到维持。1897年版的《大都会》和1914年版的《自然科学基金会》提供了出发点。作品的空间戏剧性在其所有的迭代中都是显而易见的,作者想要在书的空间内或跨空间表达这首诗的意图是明确的。正是这种对空间和图形表达的特别关注,使《一场政变》成为一个独特的例子,证明了一个重要的观点:诗歌,就其性质、结构和表达而言,都是卓越的图解作品。它们是文学作品,其意义取决于其文本中体现的空间关系,其空间关系通过其图形表达而变得有意义。我不认为《政变》是诗歌作品历史上的一个反常现象,而是认为它的图解特征证明了它的典范性,明确地展示了通常在诗歌作品讨论中隐含的东西——一首诗是一部空间作品,其操作是图解的。《妙手一击》中的短语分布并不遵循严格的线性规则。诗歌的特点是强调语言元素在空间上的衔接,即使是一条接一条地排列,诗歌作品的特点也是如此。押韵、格律和文本在内容、意义、联想价值或诗歌创作功能的任何一种方式上的呼应,将诗歌的元素置于相互关联的多种构型中。这是散文和诗歌之间的基本区别之一,即使散文话语管理这种空间联系的方式与交响乐作品一样——通过主题和变化、短语、叙事、情绪等. ...
{"title":"Stephane Mallarme's Un Coup De Des and the Poem And/as Book as Diagram","authors":"J. Drucker","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171612","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171612","url":null,"abstract":"Few works of poetry have made a more dramatic case for the poem and/as book as a diagrammatic expression than Stephane Mallarme's renowned Un Coup de Des. (1) Initially issued in the May 1897 issue of the British publication, Cosmopolis, the work was produced in a second edition by the Nouvelle Revue Francaise in 1914. That later edition is considered by most Mallarme scholars to more closely resemble the manuscript and instructions conceived by the poet in advance of his death in 1898. Paul Valery saw those manuscripts, lying on a window sill at the house in which he visited the aging poet. (2) Valery left a suggestive, rather than detailed, description of those papers covered with calligraphic glyphs anticipating the typographic treatment Mallarme envisioned for the work. Photocopies have been published of the marked up manuscript, itself in the collection of the Bibliotheque Nationale in Paris, but even that is still an unreliable testimonial for editorial events that might have followed had the poet lived to see the project finished. An edition created by Michael Pierson and published in 2004 by Ptyx attempts a most faithful rendering of the edition originally planned by Ambrose Vollard. Discussions of the poem are always subject to qualification, therefore, since the work does not exist in any form authorized by Mallarme or produced under his final supervision. Further and final changes or alterations to either the textual composition or its graphical expression could have entered in the process, and so we have to qualify all critical discussion by an understanding that the \"poem\" in question is only tentatively the work Mallarme imagined. Such reservations are more appropriate to this poem than to many others, however, since its fundamental tensions are dynamic ones that circle around questions of being and nothing, chance and constellationary order, and the human \"master\" who struggles to mediate sense within the ongoing conflicts of these conditions. Because the poem is so completely about this process, as well as embodying and expressing it, the character of self-referentiality implodes in a state of dynamic incompleteness that is only further sustained by the fact that we are engaging in a state of the poem that is neither final nor definitive. The Cosmopolis and N.R.F. editions of 1897 and 1914 offer points of departure. The spatial drama of the work is evident in all its iterations, and the intention on the part of the author to articulate the poem within and across the spaces of a book is clear. And it is that specific attention to spatial and graphical articulation that makes Un Coup de Des the unique example that proves a significant point: that poems are, by their nature, structure, and expression, diagrammatic works par excellence. They are literary works whose meaning depends upon the spatialized relations of embodied in their texts and whose spatial relations are rendered meaningful by their graphical expression. Rather than co","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"143 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115811131","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Toward a Deleuzian Ethics: Value without Transcendence 走向德勒兹伦理学:没有超越的价值
Pub Date : 2011-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171620
Vernon W. Cisney
Nathan Jun and Daniel W. Smith, Deleuze and Ethics (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2011), Page229, ISBN: 978-0748641161. [ILLUSTRATION OMITTED] What, one might ask, has Gilles Deleuze to contribute to ethical discourse, given its current infatuation with rule-based problem-posing? Deleuze's critics on this score are found, not only in so-called mainstream contemporary ethics, but also among thinkers who claim explicitly to be working in Deleuze's shadow. He who found an affinity with and precursor in those very ethicists-Spinoza and Nietzsche-ostracized and marginalized by mainstream ethics today; he who praised Nietzsche's amor fati, and found exuberance in the Stoics, claiming that one must "make chance into an object of affirmation;" (Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 60) he who defined ethics, as "not to be unworthy of what happens to us"(149)--what has he to offer in the way of an ethics? This is the question taken up in Deleuze and Ethics (2011)--the most recent addition to Edinburgh's "Deleuze Connections" series. Edited by Nathan Jun and Daniel W. Smith, the contents of this important work, in the spirit of Deleuze himself pursue various lines of flight, stemming from the questions surrounding a Deleuzian ethics, which faces two specific fundamental challenges: (1) It rejects the comfortable transcendent principles of evaluation of post-Enlightenment theories of ethics, comfortable because they reassure us that at the end of the day, there is a fact of the matter about right and wrong, and justice will prevail; (2) Correlatively, Deleuze's ontology forbids the absolute freedom of the subject. Constituted within a field of differential relations, a subject can never be an autonomous or purely rational agent who dispassionately chooses from among its various options. Freedom in contemporary ethics allows us to render judgments about how agents choose, and thus allows us to declare these choices as right or wrong, and their agents as good or evil. Moreover, without freedom, what possibility is there for action at all? Lacking freedom in the absolute sense, are we to resign ourselves to passive acceptance? In his chapter, Smith outlines a critique of transcendent values, centered precisely around their inhibitive nature: "What an ethics of immanence will criticize, then, is anything that separates a mode of existence from its power of acting--and what separates us from our power of acting is, ultimately, the illusions of transcendence"(125). The transcendencies of God, Self, and Moral Law prescribe ideals to which a world of becoming can never attain, thus casting a pallor of deficiency over all of life. Dictating to the body how it ought to be, but can never be, they serve a limiting and inhibitive role to desire. Explicating Nietzsche's theory of the drives, in parallel with Leibniz's discussion of freedom in The New Essays Concerning Human Understanding (odd bedfellows, at least on the surface), Smith points the way to a Deleuzian th
Nathan Jun, Daniel W. Smith,《德勒兹与伦理学》(爱丁堡:爱丁堡大学出版社,2011),第229页,ISBN: 978-0748641161。有人可能会问,鉴于目前对基于规则的问题提出的迷恋,吉尔·德勒兹(Gilles Deleuze)对伦理话语有什么贡献?德勒兹在这方面的批评者,不仅存在于所谓的主流当代伦理学中,也存在于那些明确宣称在德勒兹的阴影下工作的思想家中。他在伦理学家斯宾诺莎和尼采身上找到了亲缘关系,并成为他们的先驱,他们被今天的主流伦理学所排斥和边缘化;他赞扬尼采的命运之爱,并在斯多葛派中发现了旺盛的生命力,声称人必须“把机会变成肯定的对象”;(德勒兹,《理性的逻辑》,第60页)他把伦理学定义为“不要对发生在我们身上的事情毫无价值”(149页)——他在伦理学的道路上提供了什么?这是《德勒兹与伦理学》(2011)中提出的问题——爱丁堡“德勒兹联系”系列的最新新作。由内森·君和丹尼尔·w·史密斯编辑,这本重要著作的内容,本着德勒兹本人的精神,追求各种各样的飞行路线,源于围绕德勒兹伦理的问题,它面临着两个具体的基本挑战:(1)它拒绝了后启蒙时代伦理学理论的舒适的超越原则,舒适是因为它们向我们保证,在一天结束的时候,有一个关于对与错的事实,正义将占上风;(2)相对而言,德勒兹的本体论禁止主体的绝对自由。主体在不同关系的领域中构成,永远不可能是一个自主的或纯粹理性的主体,在各种选择中冷静地做出选择。当代伦理学中的自由允许我们对行为人如何选择做出判断,从而允许我们宣布这些选择是对还是错,以及他们的行为人是善还是恶。此外,没有自由,行动又有什么可能呢?缺乏绝对意义上的自由,我们是否要让自己被动地接受?在这一章中,史密斯概述了对超越性价值的批判,其核心正是超越性价值的抑制性质:“那么,内在性伦理将批判的是任何将存在模式与其行动能力分开的东西——而将我们与我们的行动能力分开的东西,最终是超越性的幻觉”(125)。上帝、自我和道德法则的超越性规定了理想,而这些理想是一个正在形成的世界永远无法达到的,因此在整个生命中蒙上了一层缺陷的苍白。它们规定身体应该如何,但永远不能如何,它们对欲望起着限制和抑制的作用。解释尼采的驱力理论,与莱布尼茨在《关于人类理解的新论文》中对自由的讨论(至少在表面上是奇怪的同床异语)相平行,史密斯指出了德勒兹的欲望理论的道路,它提供了人类如何渴望超越道德的局限性的解释,同时也向一种方式移动,在这种方式中,欲望可能创造“生产新事物的条件”。(139)由此开启了自由的问题,真正的内在起源。...
{"title":"Toward a Deleuzian Ethics: Value without Transcendence","authors":"Vernon W. Cisney","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171620","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171620","url":null,"abstract":"Nathan Jun and Daniel W. Smith, Deleuze and Ethics (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2011), Page229, ISBN: 978-0748641161. [ILLUSTRATION OMITTED] What, one might ask, has Gilles Deleuze to contribute to ethical discourse, given its current infatuation with rule-based problem-posing? Deleuze's critics on this score are found, not only in so-called mainstream contemporary ethics, but also among thinkers who claim explicitly to be working in Deleuze's shadow. He who found an affinity with and precursor in those very ethicists-Spinoza and Nietzsche-ostracized and marginalized by mainstream ethics today; he who praised Nietzsche's amor fati, and found exuberance in the Stoics, claiming that one must \"make chance into an object of affirmation;\" (Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 60) he who defined ethics, as \"not to be unworthy of what happens to us\"(149)--what has he to offer in the way of an ethics? This is the question taken up in Deleuze and Ethics (2011)--the most recent addition to Edinburgh's \"Deleuze Connections\" series. Edited by Nathan Jun and Daniel W. Smith, the contents of this important work, in the spirit of Deleuze himself pursue various lines of flight, stemming from the questions surrounding a Deleuzian ethics, which faces two specific fundamental challenges: (1) It rejects the comfortable transcendent principles of evaluation of post-Enlightenment theories of ethics, comfortable because they reassure us that at the end of the day, there is a fact of the matter about right and wrong, and justice will prevail; (2) Correlatively, Deleuze's ontology forbids the absolute freedom of the subject. Constituted within a field of differential relations, a subject can never be an autonomous or purely rational agent who dispassionately chooses from among its various options. Freedom in contemporary ethics allows us to render judgments about how agents choose, and thus allows us to declare these choices as right or wrong, and their agents as good or evil. Moreover, without freedom, what possibility is there for action at all? Lacking freedom in the absolute sense, are we to resign ourselves to passive acceptance? In his chapter, Smith outlines a critique of transcendent values, centered precisely around their inhibitive nature: \"What an ethics of immanence will criticize, then, is anything that separates a mode of existence from its power of acting--and what separates us from our power of acting is, ultimately, the illusions of transcendence\"(125). The transcendencies of God, Self, and Moral Law prescribe ideals to which a world of becoming can never attain, thus casting a pallor of deficiency over all of life. Dictating to the body how it ought to be, but can never be, they serve a limiting and inhibitive role to desire. Explicating Nietzsche's theory of the drives, in parallel with Leibniz's discussion of freedom in The New Essays Concerning Human Understanding (odd bedfellows, at least on the surface), Smith points the way to a Deleuzian th","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"37 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126198423","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Deconstructing “Grown versus Made”: A Derridean Perspective on Cloning 解构“成长与制造”:克隆的德里安视角
Pub Date : 2011-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171615
Kelly Oliver
Most philosophers discussing genetic engineering, including cloning, assume the "grown versus made" opposition. Therefore, their stance on the ethics of both revolves around whether they privilege one side of this binary over the other. Part and parcel of the "grown versus made" opposition is the liberal notion of freedom of choice also assumed in these discussions. Most philosophers engaged in debates over genetic engineering and cloning begin with some version of a liberal sovereign individual who has freedom of choice that must be protected, whether we are talking about the parents' freedom (or lack thereof) in considering genetic engineering and embryo selection, or the future persons' freedom (or lack thereof) resulting from such a process. The central question in these debates is whose freedom is most important and thus who gets to exercise their free choice, and why. Although they have different answers to this question--John Harris opts for protecting parents' rights to choose, Jurgen Habermas for protecting the rights of future persons, and some feminists for guaranteeing women's rights to reproductive choice, all of them assume a sovereign individual operating either within a social situation that also makes them interdependent, or on an abstract level preferred by some philosophers to avoid the mess of the real world in favor of moral purity. (1) In this essay, I consider what happens to debates over genetic enhancement when we "deconstruct" the opposition between "grown and made" and the notion of freedom of choice that comes with it. Along with the binary grown and made comes other such oppositions at the center of these debates: chance and choice, accident and deliberation, nature and culture. By deconstructing the oppositions between grown versus made (chance versus choice, or accident versus deliberate), and free versus determined, alternative routes through these bioethical thickets start to emerge. On both sides of debates over genetic engineering and cloning, we see that philosophers assume a sovereign liberal notion of the individual who is free to choose, who can make decisions, and control the future. For philosophers like John Harris this is a good thing while for Jurgen Habermas and others it is not. Habermas imagines that genetic enhancement would make us masters of our destiny in such a way as to undermine the contingencies that make us free. (2) Yet, for Habermas, it is the authorship of one's own life and the ownership of one's own body that results in human agency, an authorship and ownership already at odds with the contigency he privileges. If we refuse the sovereign author/owner as our starting point, then the contingency of life (and of morality) is not merely the result of an autonomous agent stuck in a contingent world. Rather, the subject itself cannot, contra Habermas, escape the Other and others to which and to whom it is beholden; its existence is a contingency all the way down to the kernel of its subjectiv
大多数讨论基因工程的哲学家,包括克隆,都假设“生长vs制造”的对立。因此,他们对两者伦理的立场围绕着他们是否给予这二元对立的一方特权而不是另一方。“成长与制造”对立的重要组成部分是自由选择的自由概念,也在这些讨论中被假设。大多数参与基因工程和克隆辩论的哲学家,都是从某种形式的自由主权个人开始的,他有选择的自由,必须得到保护,无论我们是在谈论父母在考虑基因工程和胚胎选择方面的自由(或缺乏自由),还是在这个过程中产生的未来人的自由(或缺乏自由)。这些争论的核心问题是谁的自由最重要,因此谁可以行使他们的自由选择,以及为什么。尽管他们对这个问题有不同的答案——约翰·哈里斯选择保护父母的选择权,尤尔根·哈贝马斯选择保护未来人的权利,一些女权主义者则选择保障妇女的生育选择权,但他们都假设一个至高无上的个人,要么在一个也使他们相互依存的社会环境中运作,要么在一些哲学家喜欢的抽象层面上运作,以避免现实世界的混乱,支持道德纯洁。(1)在这篇文章中,我考虑了当我们“解构”“生长和制造”之间的对立以及随之而来的选择自由的概念时,关于基因增强的争论会发生什么。伴随着生长和制造的二元对立,这些辩论的中心还出现了其他这样的对立:机会和选择,偶然和深思熟虑,自然和文化。通过解构成长与创造之间的对立(机会与选择,或意外与故意),自由与决定之间的对立,通过这些生物伦理丛林的替代路线开始出现。在关于基因工程和克隆的争论中,我们看到哲学家们都假设了一个至高无上的自由主义概念,即个人可以自由选择,可以做出决定,可以控制未来。对于像约翰·哈里斯这样的哲学家来说,这是一件好事,而对于于尔根·哈贝马斯和其他人来说则不是。哈贝马斯设想,基因增强将使我们成为自己命运的主人,从而削弱使我们自由的偶然性。(2)然而,对哈贝马斯来说,正是对自己生命的所有权和对自己身体的所有权导致了人的能动性,这种所有权和所有权已经与他所享有的偶然性相冲突。如果我们拒绝把至高无上的作者/所有者作为我们的出发点,那么生命(和道德)的偶然性就不仅仅是一个被困在偶然性世界中的自主主体的结果。相反,与哈贝马斯相反,主体本身无法逃避他者和他者,它对他者和他者负有义务;它的存在是一种偶然性,一直到它的主观性和能动性的核心。这并不是说主体(也许像萨特一样)在与一个随时威胁其本质和真实个性的敌对或偶然的世界作斗争。相反,这场战斗发生在主体内部——或者更好地说,构成主体——主体无法统一或重新整合,因为它的经验从根本上是碎片化的。因此,伦理责任既不是掌握的结果,也不是作者的结果,而是对他者/他者召唤的回应。另一方面,哈里斯认为掌握未来是一种道德上的要求,也就是说,我们有道德上的责任通过包括克隆在内的基因技术创造更好的人。他认为我们可以利用科学知识来控制人类的未来,而这正是哈贝马斯所憎恶的。但是,只有从人类能动性作为主宰,作为主宰自然的概念出发,我们才能得出上述结论中的任何一个。...
{"title":"Deconstructing “Grown versus Made”: A Derridean Perspective on Cloning","authors":"Kelly Oliver","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171615","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171615","url":null,"abstract":"Most philosophers discussing genetic engineering, including cloning, assume the \"grown versus made\" opposition. Therefore, their stance on the ethics of both revolves around whether they privilege one side of this binary over the other. Part and parcel of the \"grown versus made\" opposition is the liberal notion of freedom of choice also assumed in these discussions. Most philosophers engaged in debates over genetic engineering and cloning begin with some version of a liberal sovereign individual who has freedom of choice that must be protected, whether we are talking about the parents' freedom (or lack thereof) in considering genetic engineering and embryo selection, or the future persons' freedom (or lack thereof) resulting from such a process. The central question in these debates is whose freedom is most important and thus who gets to exercise their free choice, and why. Although they have different answers to this question--John Harris opts for protecting parents' rights to choose, Jurgen Habermas for protecting the rights of future persons, and some feminists for guaranteeing women's rights to reproductive choice, all of them assume a sovereign individual operating either within a social situation that also makes them interdependent, or on an abstract level preferred by some philosophers to avoid the mess of the real world in favor of moral purity. (1) In this essay, I consider what happens to debates over genetic enhancement when we \"deconstruct\" the opposition between \"grown and made\" and the notion of freedom of choice that comes with it. Along with the binary grown and made comes other such oppositions at the center of these debates: chance and choice, accident and deliberation, nature and culture. By deconstructing the oppositions between grown versus made (chance versus choice, or accident versus deliberate), and free versus determined, alternative routes through these bioethical thickets start to emerge. On both sides of debates over genetic engineering and cloning, we see that philosophers assume a sovereign liberal notion of the individual who is free to choose, who can make decisions, and control the future. For philosophers like John Harris this is a good thing while for Jurgen Habermas and others it is not. Habermas imagines that genetic enhancement would make us masters of our destiny in such a way as to undermine the contingencies that make us free. (2) Yet, for Habermas, it is the authorship of one's own life and the ownership of one's own body that results in human agency, an authorship and ownership already at odds with the contigency he privileges. If we refuse the sovereign author/owner as our starting point, then the contingency of life (and of morality) is not merely the result of an autonomous agent stuck in a contingent world. Rather, the subject itself cannot, contra Habermas, escape the Other and others to which and to whom it is beholden; its existence is a contingency all the way down to the kernel of its subjectiv","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"64 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128062067","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
“The Self and Other People: Reading Conflict Resolution and Reconciliation with René Girard and Emmanuel Levinas” 《自我与他人:与雷诺·吉拉德、伊曼纽尔·列维纳斯解读冲突解决与和解》
Pub Date : 2011-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171613
Sandor Goodhart
Emmanuel Levinas ... talks of the defenseless face of the other which shows itself to us in a way we can't avoid. When we recognize this face, it makes us a captive. This face is the face of the scapegoat, the victim, helpless and without possibility of escape. (1) Part One: Conflict Resolution, Girard, and Levinas One of the hot topics in conflict resolution studies over the past thirty years or so has been the introduction of the idea of reconciliation. (2) The idea behind it is that the resolution of conflict remains temporary as long as we focus exclusively upon the symptomatic issues at hand and that only if we step back and look more broadly at the people involved and the larger contexts in which they live and work can it be made permanent--and thus something like reconciliation becomes possible. In this expanding contextual understanding, the work of Rene Girard has assumed special importance. Why? Girard posits that all culture operates in effect as a management system for mimetic desire, a system sustained by what he calls the scapegoat mechanism, a system in which a victim arbitrarily chosen and sacrificially removed from the community in a veritable lynching is understood to be at the origin of all social distinction, founded as such distinction is upon the difference between the sacred and violence. The sacred and violence for Girard are one and the same. The sacred is violence effectively removed from the community, and violence is the sacred deviated from its segregated transcendent status and come down into the city to wreak havoc among its citizenry. If the system is effectively maintained, the originating violence is reenacted each year in the form of commemorative ritual, and the result is the regeneration of the sacred. If the system is not maintained, the result is violence, which is to say, difference gone wrong, distinction gone awry, asserted in the extreme in its inefficacy. Untouched by the outside world, archaic communities, as Girard tells the story, sustained their existence for thousands of years within this cycle of difference, difference gone wrong (or sacrificial crisis), paroxysmal exclusionary behavior (or surrogate victimage), and new differentiation (and commemorative reenactment). With the advent of the "modern" world some twenty five hundred years ago (and for whatever reason), these sacrificial systems were threatened and the ones that survived were the ones that effectively developed a means of living more or less without sacrificial victims in the traditional sense. It is not hard to imagine how or why conflict resolution theorists would be interested in these ideas and identify in this account of sacrificial violence and its mechanism a useful model. Here for example is how Roel Kaptein explains Girard: Our culture increasingly gives us the impression that we are atomized individuals, responsible for and to ourselves and free to do what we want. Inevitably in this situation, everybody and everything else
伊曼纽尔·列维纳斯……他者毫无防备的面孔以一种我们无法回避的方式展现在我们面前。当我们认出这张脸时,我们就成了俘虏。这张脸是替罪羊的脸,受害者的脸,无助,没有逃脱的可能。(1)第一部分:冲突解决、吉拉德和列维纳斯在过去30年左右的冲突解决研究中,和解概念的引入是一个热门话题。(2)它背后的思想是,只要我们只关注手头的症状性问题,冲突的解决就仍然是暂时的,只有当我们退后一步,更广泛地看待所涉及的人以及他们生活和工作的更大背景时,冲突才能成为永久性的——因此,和解之类的东西才有可能实现。在这种不断扩大的语境理解中,勒内·吉拉德的工作具有特殊的重要性。为什么?吉拉德认为,所有文化实际上都是一种模仿欲望的管理系统,一种由他所谓的替罪羊机制维持的系统,在这种系统中,一个受害者被任意选择,并在一场真正的私刑中被牺牲地从社区中移除,被理解为所有社会区别的起源,这种区别建立在神圣和暴力之间的区别之上。对吉拉德来说,神圣和暴力是一回事。神圣是指暴力有效地从社区中移除,而暴力是指神圣脱离了其隔离的超然地位,进入城市,在市民中造成严重破坏。如果有效地维持这一制度,每年都会以纪念仪式的形式再现最初的暴力,其结果是神圣的再生。如果制度得不到维护,结果就是暴力,也就是说,差别错了,区别错了,在其无效的情况下被极端地断言。正如吉拉德讲述的那样,古老的社区不受外部世界的影响,在这种差异、差异出错(或牺牲危机)、突发性排斥行为(或替代受害者)和新的差异(和纪念重演)的循环中维持了数千年的存在。大约2500年前,随着“现代”世界的到来(无论出于什么原因),这些祭祀制度受到了威胁,幸存下来的是那些有效地发展了一种或多或少没有传统意义上的祭祀受害者的生活方式。不难想象,冲突解决理论家会如何或为什么对这些观点感兴趣,并在这种关于牺牲暴力及其机制的描述中找到一个有用的模型。举个例子,罗尔·卡普泰因是这样解释吉拉德的:我们的文化越来越给我们一种印象,即我们是原子化的个体,对自己负责,对自己负责,可以自由地做我们想做的事。在这种情况下,每个人和每件事都不可避免地成为我们用来实现自己目标的工具。其他人挡在我们和我们的目标之间。当我们看到别人找替罪羊和指责别人时,我们鄙视它。然而,在蔑视和厌恶它的过程中,我们实际上证明了我们自己并没有摆脱它。相反,我们表现出我们对它了如指掌。然而,我们继续找替罪羊,指责别人,一次又一次,从来没有承认我们在做什么。即使在我们这样做的时候,我们仍然绝对确信我们自己不是替罪羊。我们确信我们是完全正确的!在这种情况下,这段经文中的一切,甚至我们从福音中学到的一切都可以用来玩替罪羊的游戏,文化的游戏,更好。我们可以成为更聪明的伪君子,认为自己高人一等。要摆脱这种循环,只有一种可能;认识到通过我们运作的替罪羊机制。…
{"title":"“The Self and Other People: Reading Conflict Resolution and Reconciliation with René Girard and Emmanuel Levinas”","authors":"Sandor Goodhart","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171613","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171613","url":null,"abstract":"Emmanuel Levinas ... talks of the defenseless face of the other which shows itself to us in a way we can't avoid. When we recognize this face, it makes us a captive. This face is the face of the scapegoat, the victim, helpless and without possibility of escape. (1) Part One: Conflict Resolution, Girard, and Levinas One of the hot topics in conflict resolution studies over the past thirty years or so has been the introduction of the idea of reconciliation. (2) The idea behind it is that the resolution of conflict remains temporary as long as we focus exclusively upon the symptomatic issues at hand and that only if we step back and look more broadly at the people involved and the larger contexts in which they live and work can it be made permanent--and thus something like reconciliation becomes possible. In this expanding contextual understanding, the work of Rene Girard has assumed special importance. Why? Girard posits that all culture operates in effect as a management system for mimetic desire, a system sustained by what he calls the scapegoat mechanism, a system in which a victim arbitrarily chosen and sacrificially removed from the community in a veritable lynching is understood to be at the origin of all social distinction, founded as such distinction is upon the difference between the sacred and violence. The sacred and violence for Girard are one and the same. The sacred is violence effectively removed from the community, and violence is the sacred deviated from its segregated transcendent status and come down into the city to wreak havoc among its citizenry. If the system is effectively maintained, the originating violence is reenacted each year in the form of commemorative ritual, and the result is the regeneration of the sacred. If the system is not maintained, the result is violence, which is to say, difference gone wrong, distinction gone awry, asserted in the extreme in its inefficacy. Untouched by the outside world, archaic communities, as Girard tells the story, sustained their existence for thousands of years within this cycle of difference, difference gone wrong (or sacrificial crisis), paroxysmal exclusionary behavior (or surrogate victimage), and new differentiation (and commemorative reenactment). With the advent of the \"modern\" world some twenty five hundred years ago (and for whatever reason), these sacrificial systems were threatened and the ones that survived were the ones that effectively developed a means of living more or less without sacrificial victims in the traditional sense. It is not hard to imagine how or why conflict resolution theorists would be interested in these ideas and identify in this account of sacrificial violence and its mechanism a useful model. Here for example is how Roel Kaptein explains Girard: Our culture increasingly gives us the impression that we are atomized individuals, responsible for and to ourselves and free to do what we want. Inevitably in this situation, everybody and everything else ","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"13 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126746279","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Interventions: Postcolonial, Agency and Resistance 干预:后殖民、代理和抵抗
Pub Date : 2011-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171617
R. J. Young
(Yubraj Aryal interviewed Robert Young on postcolonial studies. Mr. Aryal focused his questions on the issues of postcolonial agency, resistance and new models of political and cultural practices in postcolonial studies.) Y. A.: Since you are editing a leading journal, Interventions: International Journal of Postcolonial Studies, what "interventions" are you making in the postcolonial fields in terms of postcolonial agency, modes of resistance, and the emergence of new models of political and cultural practice of alternative communities? What forms of new knowledge have you been attempting to produce in the field since 1998? How can academic and non-academic experiences of alternative communities, like that of Nepali communities, for instance, be of interest to your journal? What has characterized the postcolonia in the past decade from the point of view of my first three questions? R.Y.: Because it is conditioned by history, the postcolonial is always in a situation of transformation. The political context is always changing, and the interventions that we make will always be shifting as a result from year to year. The global political scene has altered profoundly since the journal began in 1998, most notably of course 9/11 and its aftermath, but also in other arenas such as the high profile developments of indigenous struggles in Latin America, Australasia, South Asia and elsewhere. I don't think there is anything that we could call "postcolonial agency" as such: rather there are forms of agency which manifest themselves in specific situations, particularly those of resistance and, one might add, triumph. Agency itself is governed by the conditions of its production. So if we take the Arab Spring, for example, we can see that the agency there is at once individual and collective, and takes the form not only of protest but a general withdrawal of consent to power. Ultimately, in a revolutionary situation, this is the most formidable kind of agency, because it means that the revolution is coming from below, rather than from a vanguard elite (a situation which always poses trouble). With respect to new forms of knowledge, we have not ourselves been trying to produce them as such, though we do when we can, but rather to see the journal as a vehicle by which others can be enabled to produce and articulate new forms of knowledge, particularly those which go outside conventional academic protocols. We are particularly interested in knowledge that proceeds from everyday life, from people whose knowledge does not typically count as real or authorized knowledge, and from those who are struggling to articulate their own knowledges within frameworks that do not easily accommodate them. With respect to Nepali communities, we have been much less active than I should have liked, and this is of course related to the material which we receive and the contacts which we have. But we should have been more proactive in seeking out material from (rather than merely a
Yubraj Aryal就后殖民研究采访了Robert Young。阿亚尔的问题集中在后殖民机构、抵抗以及后殖民研究中政治和文化实践的新模式等问题上。)答:既然你是《干预:国际后殖民研究杂志》的主编,那么你在后殖民领域进行了哪些“干预”,包括后殖民机构、抵抗模式,以及另类社区的政治和文化实践新模式的出现?自1998年以来,您一直在尝试在该领域产生哪些形式的新知识?另类社群的学术与非学术经验,例如尼泊尔社群的经验,如何会成为你的期刊感兴趣的内容?从我的前三个问题来看,过去十年的后殖民主义有什么特点?r.y.:由于受历史的制约,后殖民总是处于一种转型的状态。政治环境总是在变化,我们所做的干预也会因此每年都在变化。自1998年创刊以来,全球政治舞台发生了深刻的变化,最显著的当然是9/11事件及其后果,但也在其他领域,如拉丁美洲、澳大拉西亚、南亚和其他地方的土著斗争的高调发展。我不认为有什么我们可以称之为“后殖民能动性”的东西:相反,有一些形式的能动性在特定的情况下表现出来,特别是在抵抗和胜利的情况下。代理本身受其生产条件的支配。因此,如果我们以阿拉伯之春为例,我们可以看到,那里的机构既是个人的,也是集体的,其形式不仅是抗议,而且是对权力的普遍撤回。最终,在革命形势下,这是最令人生畏的一种机构,因为这意味着革命来自下层,而不是来自先锋精英(这种形势总是会带来麻烦)。关于新形式的知识,我们自己并没有试图去创造它们,尽管我们在可能的时候会这样做,而是把期刊看作一个工具,通过它,其他人可以创造和阐明新形式的知识,特别是那些超越传统学术协议的知识。我们特别感兴趣的是来自日常生活的知识,来自那些通常不被视为真实或授权知识的人的知识,以及那些在不容易适应他们的框架中努力表达自己知识的人的知识。关于尼泊尔社区,我们的活跃程度远远低于我的期望,这当然与我们收到的材料和我们的联系有关。但我们本应更积极主动地从尼泊尔(而不仅仅是关于尼泊尔)寻找材料。雅:谁是后殖民主体(如果有的话)?有一种普遍的观点认为,这门学科是由殖民残余构成的。我看到了这种观点的道德问题,因为它假设了一种贫乏的代理形式。我相信,对后殖民主体的动态理解,包括一个存在于后殖民或任何一套政治范畴之外的自我概念。这不是殖民主义的影响,而是主体从殖民主义中产生的差异。你同意吗?r.y.:我不确定是否有这样的“后殖民主题”——在我看来,在后殖民在日常生活的锻炼和体验中显得过于重要。当然,也有一些主体以不同的方式受到后殖民影响的影响,直接的,或者,如你所说,更多的是与殖民残余有关。例如,后殖民社会中的许多主体都受到法治的约束,法律体系作为一种规则,与殖民统治下建立的法律体系无缝地运作。…
{"title":"Interventions: Postcolonial, Agency and Resistance","authors":"R. J. Young","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171617","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171617","url":null,"abstract":"(Yubraj Aryal interviewed Robert Young on postcolonial studies. Mr. Aryal focused his questions on the issues of postcolonial agency, resistance and new models of political and cultural practices in postcolonial studies.) Y. A.: Since you are editing a leading journal, Interventions: International Journal of Postcolonial Studies, what \"interventions\" are you making in the postcolonial fields in terms of postcolonial agency, modes of resistance, and the emergence of new models of political and cultural practice of alternative communities? What forms of new knowledge have you been attempting to produce in the field since 1998? How can academic and non-academic experiences of alternative communities, like that of Nepali communities, for instance, be of interest to your journal? What has characterized the postcolonia in the past decade from the point of view of my first three questions? R.Y.: Because it is conditioned by history, the postcolonial is always in a situation of transformation. The political context is always changing, and the interventions that we make will always be shifting as a result from year to year. The global political scene has altered profoundly since the journal began in 1998, most notably of course 9/11 and its aftermath, but also in other arenas such as the high profile developments of indigenous struggles in Latin America, Australasia, South Asia and elsewhere. I don't think there is anything that we could call \"postcolonial agency\" as such: rather there are forms of agency which manifest themselves in specific situations, particularly those of resistance and, one might add, triumph. Agency itself is governed by the conditions of its production. So if we take the Arab Spring, for example, we can see that the agency there is at once individual and collective, and takes the form not only of protest but a general withdrawal of consent to power. Ultimately, in a revolutionary situation, this is the most formidable kind of agency, because it means that the revolution is coming from below, rather than from a vanguard elite (a situation which always poses trouble). With respect to new forms of knowledge, we have not ourselves been trying to produce them as such, though we do when we can, but rather to see the journal as a vehicle by which others can be enabled to produce and articulate new forms of knowledge, particularly those which go outside conventional academic protocols. We are particularly interested in knowledge that proceeds from everyday life, from people whose knowledge does not typically count as real or authorized knowledge, and from those who are struggling to articulate their own knowledges within frameworks that do not easily accommodate them. With respect to Nepali communities, we have been much less active than I should have liked, and this is of course related to the material which we receive and the contacts which we have. But we should have been more proactive in seeking out material from (rather than merely a","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"68 6","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"113961570","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Anthropocentric Vision: Aesthetics of Effect and Terror in Poe’s “Hop-Frog” 人类中心视野:坡《跳蛙》的效果美学与恐怖美学
Pub Date : 2011-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201161527
Satwik Dasgupta
In 1996, Gabriele Rippl wrote a seminal essay on the connection between Edgar Allan Poe and anthropology, formulating an unusual approach to Poe's fiction. Re-examining Poe's aesthetics, specifically through tales dealing with the body or the essential physicality of the characters, Rippl argues, would demonstrate that it is the readers who are indirectly the author of these tales. In other words, one can generate meaning from these texts provided one is able to discern Poe's vision as directed towards a reader-centric anthropology, whereby the author's aesthetics of terror are but a measure of his readers' responsiveness. As Rippl puts it, "[a] discussion of the anthropological impact of Poe's literary texts shows that his real interest is not so much in representing current conceptions of man, but rather the anthropology of the reader," and "it is not the examination of the body as such that interests Poe but the aesthetic effects to be achieved by this detailed presentation." (1) In addition, Rippl observes that just as Poe's protagonists become victims of their self-generated terrors, the readers are "victims" of Poe's aesthetics of the unity of effect, something that has been termed "aesthetics" of terror. Herbert Grabes points out that "[t]he growing interest in culture, or rather cultures, speaks for ... cultural anthropology," and "in this case, literature will be considered mainly as a cultural product providing evidence of the particular features of the culture within which it is produced." (2) What Grabes observes about "cultural anthropology" is traceable in Poe's fiction because it generally projects narrators into extreme conditions/states of being in the context of their immediate socio-cultural surroundings. Poe engaged in probing the essentials of mind-body dichotomy pointing to larger concerns affecting the human psyche. Whether satires, hoaxes, "arabesques," or "grotesques," Poe envisioned and revealed the minds of men possessing various degrees of sanity, intelligence, physical characteristics, and the like to highlight Man's existential crisis. As readers, we can understand and appreciate Poe's anthropocentrism by re-evaluating his fiction with respect to his essential ideas of the human being, both as a social animal and a cultural trope. Gabriele Rippl uses four tales from Poe's oeuvre--"Ligeia" (1838), "The Fall of the House of Usher" (1839), "The Pit and the Pendulum" (1842), and "The Facts in the Case of M. Valdemar" (1845)--to demonstrate how Poe exploited his readers' anthropology to generate meaning and achieve his aesthetic of unity and terror. Graves' concept of the reader-centric anthropology is particularly suitable for Poe's fiction. "The anthropology of the reader" in Poe's fiction would mean that the readers' reactions and attitudes towards specific tropes of horror or cruelty are directly proportional to and built upon their inherent tolerance or repugnance towards such visions of atrocity. This concept is sim
1996年,加布里埃尔·里普尔(Gabriele Rippl)写了一篇关于埃德加·爱伦·坡与人类学之间联系的开创性文章,对爱伦·坡的小说提出了一种不同寻常的研究方法。里普尔认为,重新审视坡的美学,特别是通过与身体或人物的基本身体有关的故事,将证明读者是这些故事的间接作者。换句话说,我们可以从这些文本中获得意义,只要我们能够看出坡的视角是指向以读者为中心的人类学,而作者的恐怖美学只是衡量读者反应的一种方式。正如Rippl所说,“对坡的文学文本的人类学影响的讨论表明,他真正的兴趣并不是表现当前的人类观念,而是读者的人类学,”而且“坡感兴趣的不是对身体的检查,而是通过这种详细的呈现所达到的美学效果。”(1)此外,Rippl观察到,正如坡的主人公成为他们自己产生的恐惧的受害者一样,读者也是坡的效果统一美学的“受害者”,这被称为恐怖的“美学”。赫伯特·格雷布斯指出:“人们对文化,或者更确切地说,对文化日益增长的兴趣,说明了……以及“在这种情况下,文学将主要被视为一种文化产品,为其产生的文化的特定特征提供证据。”(2)格雷布斯对“文化人类学”的观察可以追溯到坡的小说中,因为它通常将叙述者置于他们所处的社会文化环境的极端条件/状态中。坡致力于探索身心二分法的本质,指出影响人类心理的更大问题。无论是讽刺、恶作剧、“阿拉伯风格”还是“怪诞”,坡都设想并揭示了具有不同程度的理智、智慧、身体特征等的人的思想,以突出人类的生存危机。作为读者,我们可以通过重新评价坡的小说来理解和欣赏他的人类中心主义,他将人类作为一种社会动物和一种文化比喻。加布里埃尔·里普尔用爱伦·坡作品中的四个故事——《丽吉娅》(1838)、《厄谢尔家的倒塌》(1839)、《坑与钟摆》(1842)和《瓦尔德马先生的真相》(1845)——来展示爱伦·坡如何利用读者的人类学来产生意义,并实现他的统一与恐怖美学。格雷夫斯的以读者为中心的人类学概念特别适用于爱伦坡的小说。坡小说中的“读者的人类学”意味着读者对恐怖或残忍的特定比喻的反应和态度与他们对这种暴行的固有容忍或厌恶成正比并建立在此基础上。这一概念类似于批评的读者反应理论,但更强调读者的情感构成;他们对恐怖和暴力的先入为主和根深蒂固的反应赋予了特定故事中发生的事情以意义,从而使其变得恐怖/怪诞。在这些故事中,Rippl看到了各种各样的二分法(理想-真实,心灵-身体,自然-超自然),这些二分法通过各自的叙述来揭示,在每一个转折点,潜在的暴力,恐怖和怪诞的令人不安的图像,旨在震惊和惊讶读者。这篇文章展示了坡的《跳蛙》(1849)不仅对作者小说的上述方面进行了富有成效的人类学研究,而且通过对一个半类人猿形象的心理社会进化的视觉化,恰如其分地产生了一种恐怖、暴力和恐怖美学的强化质感,这种形象本身就包含了身体畸形和精神敏锐的极端,这种组合在19世纪的美国既受欢迎又令人恐惧。…
{"title":"The Anthropocentric Vision: Aesthetics of Effect and Terror in Poe’s “Hop-Frog”","authors":"Satwik Dasgupta","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201161527","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201161527","url":null,"abstract":"In 1996, Gabriele Rippl wrote a seminal essay on the connection between Edgar Allan Poe and anthropology, formulating an unusual approach to Poe's fiction. Re-examining Poe's aesthetics, specifically through tales dealing with the body or the essential physicality of the characters, Rippl argues, would demonstrate that it is the readers who are indirectly the author of these tales. In other words, one can generate meaning from these texts provided one is able to discern Poe's vision as directed towards a reader-centric anthropology, whereby the author's aesthetics of terror are but a measure of his readers' responsiveness. As Rippl puts it, \"[a] discussion of the anthropological impact of Poe's literary texts shows that his real interest is not so much in representing current conceptions of man, but rather the anthropology of the reader,\" and \"it is not the examination of the body as such that interests Poe but the aesthetic effects to be achieved by this detailed presentation.\" (1) In addition, Rippl observes that just as Poe's protagonists become victims of their self-generated terrors, the readers are \"victims\" of Poe's aesthetics of the unity of effect, something that has been termed \"aesthetics\" of terror. Herbert Grabes points out that \"[t]he growing interest in culture, or rather cultures, speaks for ... cultural anthropology,\" and \"in this case, literature will be considered mainly as a cultural product providing evidence of the particular features of the culture within which it is produced.\" (2) What Grabes observes about \"cultural anthropology\" is traceable in Poe's fiction because it generally projects narrators into extreme conditions/states of being in the context of their immediate socio-cultural surroundings. Poe engaged in probing the essentials of mind-body dichotomy pointing to larger concerns affecting the human psyche. Whether satires, hoaxes, \"arabesques,\" or \"grotesques,\" Poe envisioned and revealed the minds of men possessing various degrees of sanity, intelligence, physical characteristics, and the like to highlight Man's existential crisis. As readers, we can understand and appreciate Poe's anthropocentrism by re-evaluating his fiction with respect to his essential ideas of the human being, both as a social animal and a cultural trope. Gabriele Rippl uses four tales from Poe's oeuvre--\"Ligeia\" (1838), \"The Fall of the House of Usher\" (1839), \"The Pit and the Pendulum\" (1842), and \"The Facts in the Case of M. Valdemar\" (1845)--to demonstrate how Poe exploited his readers' anthropology to generate meaning and achieve his aesthetic of unity and terror. Graves' concept of the reader-centric anthropology is particularly suitable for Poe's fiction. \"The anthropology of the reader\" in Poe's fiction would mean that the readers' reactions and attitudes towards specific tropes of horror or cruelty are directly proportional to and built upon their inherent tolerance or repugnance towards such visions of atrocity. This concept is sim","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133387246","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Kali, Clodia, and the Problem of Representation 卡利,克洛迪亚和代表性问题
Pub Date : 2011-11-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201161526
Iswari P. Pandey
Introduction The study of woman in ancient literature is the study of men's views of women and cannot become anything else. --Phyllis Culham (1) Growing up in Nepal in the 70s, I witnessed my grandma worshipping Goddess Kali, a Hindu goddess of supreme power. A devotee of Kali, my grandma used to tell me stories about the many superhuman deeds attributed to the Goddess, one of which was to kill the demons and liberate the gods. Not only did I like the stories, I also identified the Goddess with my own grandmother because like the Goddess of the legends, she had also scored some extraordinary achievements by the standard of her times. She had taken my grandpa to court for his second marriage and extracted a fair share of property for her family. She had raised her only son alone in a much small property while her husband lived with his second wife in a relatively luxurious estate. Although unable to read or write, my grandma knew how to manage the household independently. If the Goddess was mother to the entire civilization, my grandma was the creator and protector of our family. But at about ten, my image of this Goddess came under what I then considered a mortal attack. I was attending a special nine-day, Goddess-worshipping, Fall ritual in which a pundit (literally) reciting and interpreting Devi Mahatmya (In Praise of Goddess) posited that the Goddess had emerged out of the combined energies of the three male gods: Brahma (the Creator), Bishnu (the Protector), and Mahadev (the Destroyer). To my young mind, it was hard to reconcile whether the Goddess was forged by the trinity of gods or she was a cosmic power operating independent of any other sources. According to the stories my grandmother told me, Kali was the cosmic power that started the motion of the wheel of universal time, as well as the primal impulse in the phenomenal existence and becoming. According to this tantric (ritualistic) version of the Goddess cult, while time (or kala, in Sanskrit) "devours" the worlds of all the three planes of Creation (the physical universe, the astral/ subtle universe, and the causal universe), at the end it is the Kali that "devours" even time (kala). Kali would, therefore, be the primordial cause of creation and destruction and in that could represent both consciousness and absolute existence. But according to this male pundit, the Goddess' existence was predicated on the will and energy of the male gods. Her role was tangential to the purpose set forth by these gods. I kept wondering which version was correct, and how one could reconcile the conflicting images of the same Goddess. To a young mind back then, it was more a problem of reconciliation than of representation. However, when I started pondering the silenced subjects in legends and other classical texts as a student of rhetoric, there was no such confusion. As I read about women in ancient rhetorical texts by men, for example, I knew these were the images of women at men's mercy, as Culham (
古代文学中对女性的研究,是对男性对女性的看法的研究,不能成为别的东西。——菲利斯身为Culham(1)在尼泊尔在70年代长大,我目睹了我奶奶崇拜女神卡莉,印度教女神的最高权力。作为卡莉的信徒,我的祖母过去常常给我讲关于女神的许多超人事迹的故事,其中之一是杀死恶魔,解放众神。我不仅喜欢这些故事,我还把女神和我自己的祖母联系在一起,因为就像传说中的女神一样,她也取得了一些以她那个时代的标准衡量的非凡成就。她为了爷爷的第二次婚姻把他告上了法庭,并为她的家庭争取到了相当一部分财产。她独自一人在一个小房子里养大了她唯一的儿子,而她的丈夫和他的第二任妻子住在一个相对豪华的房子里。奶奶虽然不会读书写字,但她知道如何独立管理家务。如果说女神是整个文明的母亲,那么我奶奶就是我们家的创造者和保护者。但在大约十岁的时候,我对这位女神的形象受到了我当时认为是致命的攻击。我参加了一个特殊的为期九天的秋季女神崇拜仪式,在这个仪式上,一位权威(字面上)背诵和解释了《神颂》(赞美女神),认为女神是从三位男神——梵天(创造者)、毗瑟奴(保护者)和马哈德夫(毁灭者)——的联合能量中出现的。在我年轻的头脑中,很难调和女神是由三位一体的神铸造的,还是她是一种独立于任何其他来源的宇宙力量。根据我祖母给我讲的故事,卡莉是宇宙的力量,它启动了宇宙时间之轮的运动,也是现象存在和形成的原始冲动。根据这个密宗(仪式)版本的女神崇拜,而时间(或梵语中的kala)“吞噬”创造的所有三个层面的世界(物质宇宙、星体/微妙宇宙和因果宇宙),最后是卡利“吞噬”甚至时间(卡拉)。因此,卡利将是创造和毁灭的原始原因,在这一点上,它可以代表意识和绝对存在。但根据这位男性权威人士的说法,女神的存在是建立在男神的意志和能量之上的。她的角色与这些神所设定的目的相去甚远。我一直想知道哪个版本是正确的,一个人如何才能调和同一位女神的相互矛盾的形象。对当时的年轻人来说,这更多的是和解问题,而不是代表问题。然而,当我作为修辞学的学生开始思考传说和其他古典文本中沉默的主题时,就没有这样的困惑了。例如,当我在古代男性的修辞文本中读到女性时,我知道这些都是女性受男性摆布的形象,正如Culham(在上面的铭文中)所暗示的那样,而不是女性真实的声音。毕竟,几乎没有任何古代女性的作品流传至今。那么问题来了,我们如何看待这些通过别人来到我们面前的人物呢?当我们知道一个给定的描述是由一个明确的动机所驱动的,这个动机是为了战术上的利益而消极地描绘这个主题时,这个问题就变得更加重要了,就像在法庭上一样。西塞罗的《开谕》中克洛迪亚的形象就是一个很好的例子。关于西塞罗的演讲和它的文化政治已经写了很多,我不打算在这篇文章中重复。相反,我想利用这个机会来探讨在恢复和修订工作中的代表性问题。学者们经常想知道恢复历史上沉默的主题的挑战和可能性,通常从伦理角度提出这些问题。然后,挑战不仅仅是关于研究对象的历史准确性或其他方面,而且更重要的是,在随后的文本中(重新)书写它们的行为。...
{"title":"Kali, Clodia, and the Problem of Representation","authors":"Iswari P. Pandey","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201161526","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201161526","url":null,"abstract":"Introduction The study of woman in ancient literature is the study of men's views of women and cannot become anything else. --Phyllis Culham (1) Growing up in Nepal in the 70s, I witnessed my grandma worshipping Goddess Kali, a Hindu goddess of supreme power. A devotee of Kali, my grandma used to tell me stories about the many superhuman deeds attributed to the Goddess, one of which was to kill the demons and liberate the gods. Not only did I like the stories, I also identified the Goddess with my own grandmother because like the Goddess of the legends, she had also scored some extraordinary achievements by the standard of her times. She had taken my grandpa to court for his second marriage and extracted a fair share of property for her family. She had raised her only son alone in a much small property while her husband lived with his second wife in a relatively luxurious estate. Although unable to read or write, my grandma knew how to manage the household independently. If the Goddess was mother to the entire civilization, my grandma was the creator and protector of our family. But at about ten, my image of this Goddess came under what I then considered a mortal attack. I was attending a special nine-day, Goddess-worshipping, Fall ritual in which a pundit (literally) reciting and interpreting Devi Mahatmya (In Praise of Goddess) posited that the Goddess had emerged out of the combined energies of the three male gods: Brahma (the Creator), Bishnu (the Protector), and Mahadev (the Destroyer). To my young mind, it was hard to reconcile whether the Goddess was forged by the trinity of gods or she was a cosmic power operating independent of any other sources. According to the stories my grandmother told me, Kali was the cosmic power that started the motion of the wheel of universal time, as well as the primal impulse in the phenomenal existence and becoming. According to this tantric (ritualistic) version of the Goddess cult, while time (or kala, in Sanskrit) \"devours\" the worlds of all the three planes of Creation (the physical universe, the astral/ subtle universe, and the causal universe), at the end it is the Kali that \"devours\" even time (kala). Kali would, therefore, be the primordial cause of creation and destruction and in that could represent both consciousness and absolute existence. But according to this male pundit, the Goddess' existence was predicated on the will and energy of the male gods. Her role was tangential to the purpose set forth by these gods. I kept wondering which version was correct, and how one could reconcile the conflicting images of the same Goddess. To a young mind back then, it was more a problem of reconciliation than of representation. However, when I started pondering the silenced subjects in legends and other classical texts as a student of rhetoric, there was no such confusion. As I read about women in ancient rhetorical texts by men, for example, I knew these were the images of women at men's mercy, as Culham (","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"56 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123333176","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Radical Atheism and “The Arche-Materiality of Time” 激进无神论与“时间的原始物质性”
Pub Date : 2011-04-04 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20116147
Martin Hägglund
(Robert King interviewed Martin Hagglund. Dr. King focused his questions on the impact of Radical Atheism and the "arche-materiality" of time). R.K.: Did the reception of Radical Atheism push your research in any surprising directions? M.H.: The most surprising thing, at least for me, is first of all how much response the book has generated. The reception of Radical Atheism has gone far beyond anything I expected and I am deeply grateful for the ways in which it has challenged me to refine my thinking and develop my arguments. Thanks to careful and demanding respondents, I have not only been given the chance to press home the stakes of my intervention; I have also been pushed to pursue issues that were either underdeveloped or inadequately addressed in my previous work. Beginning with The Challenge of Radical Atheism conference at Cornell and continuing with the colloquium on Ethics, Hospitality and Radical Atheism at Oxford as well as the Derrida and Religion conference at Harvard, I have had the good fortune to engage in direct debate with central interlocutors of the book. These debates have in turn informed the written exchanges about the book, which continue to inspire my current work. [ILLUSTRATION OMITTED] Leaving aside the specific polemics about Derrida scholarship, I would emphasize two strands of questioning that have been both the most difficult and the most productive to address. The first strand concerns the status of the structure of the trace in my argument, while the second concerns the conception of desire that informs what I call radical atheism. R.K.: Could you say more about these two strands of questioning? And how do you see them intersecting with other developments in Continental Philosophy? M.H.: The first strand of questioning can be situated in relation to a trend that is increasingly visible in Continental Philosophy, namely, a turn away from the focus on questions of language and discourse in favor of a renewed interest in questions of the real, the material, and the biological. If Saussure and linguistics once were an obligatory reference point, Darwin and evolutionary theory have increasingly come to occupy a similar position. In the wake of this development, Derrida's work is largely seen as mired in the linguistic turn or as mortgaged to an ethical and religious piety that leaves it without resources to engage the sciences and the question of material being. As I argue in Radical Atheism, however, such an assessment of deconstruction is deeply misleading. Already in Of Grammatology Derrida articulates his key notion of "the trace" in terms of not only linguistics and phenomenology but also natural science. My crucial point here is that Derrida defines the trace in terms of a general co-implication of time and space: it designates the becoming-space of time and the becoming-time of space, which Derrida abbreviates as spacing (espacement). Spacing is according to Derrida the condition for both the animate and the in
(罗伯特·金采访了马丁·赫格伦。金博士把他的问题集中在激进无神论的影响和时间的“原始物质性”上。r.k.:激进无神论的接受有没有把你的研究推向任何令人惊讶的方向?h.h.:最令人惊讶的事情,至少对我来说,首先是这本书产生了如此多的反响。对激进无神论的接受远远超出了我的预期,我深深感激它挑战我的方式来完善我的思想和发展我的论点。感谢那些谨慎而苛刻的受访者,我不仅有机会强调我的干预的利害关系;我还被迫去追求那些在我以前的工作中没有得到充分解决或没有得到充分解决的问题。从康奈尔大学的“激进无神论的挑战”会议开始,到牛津大学的“道德、好客和激进无神论”研讨会,再到哈佛大学的“德里达与宗教”会议,我有幸与书中的核心对话者进行了直接辩论。这些辩论反过来又促进了关于这本书的书面交流,这继续激励着我目前的工作。撇开关于德里达学术的具体争论不谈,我想强调两种问题,这两种问题是最难解决的,也是最有成效的。第一条线索是关于我的论证中轨迹结构的地位,第二条线索是关于欲望的概念,我称之为激进无神论。r.k.:你能多谈谈这两种问题吗?你如何看待它们与大陆哲学的其他发展的交集?马赫:第一个问题与大陆哲学中越来越明显的一个趋势有关,即从对语言和话语问题的关注转向对真实、物质和生物问题的重新关注。如果说索绪尔和语言学曾经是一个强制性的参考点,那么达尔文和进化论越来越占据了类似的位置。随着这种发展,德里达的作品在很大程度上被视为陷入了语言转向的泥潭,或者被抵押给了一种伦理和宗教虔诚,这使得它没有资源来参与科学和物质存在的问题。然而,正如我在《激进无神论》中所说的那样,这种对解构主义的评估是严重误导的。在《论语法》中,德里达不仅从语言学和现象学的角度,而且从自然科学的角度阐述了他的关键概念“痕迹”。我在这里的关键观点是,德里达根据时间和空间的一般共同含义来定义轨迹:它指定了时间的形成空间和空间的形成时间,德里达将其缩写为间隔(空间)。在德里达看来,间隔是有生命和无生命的条件,是理想和物质的条件。那么,问题是如何使这种对轨迹结构的概括合法化。说痕迹不仅是语言和经验的条件,而且是超越人类甚至生命的过程的条件,在方法论上的理由是什么?在“激进无神论的挑战”会议上,亨利·斯塔顿以其特有的敏锐,第一个对这个问题提出了压力,我在过去两年的大部分时间里都在寻求一个准确的答案。r.k.:那么在你的工作中,你是如何回应方法论论证这个问题的?马赫:我认为,需要的区别是逻辑和本体论之间的区别(在这里,我也受到了罗西奥·桑布拉纳关于黑格尔的著作的影响)。轨迹不是一种本体论的规定,而是一种逻辑结构,它明确了继承概念中隐含的东西。...
{"title":"Radical Atheism and “The Arche-Materiality of Time”","authors":"Martin Hägglund","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20116147","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20116147","url":null,"abstract":"(Robert King interviewed Martin Hagglund. Dr. King focused his questions on the impact of Radical Atheism and the \"arche-materiality\" of time). R.K.: Did the reception of Radical Atheism push your research in any surprising directions? M.H.: The most surprising thing, at least for me, is first of all how much response the book has generated. The reception of Radical Atheism has gone far beyond anything I expected and I am deeply grateful for the ways in which it has challenged me to refine my thinking and develop my arguments. Thanks to careful and demanding respondents, I have not only been given the chance to press home the stakes of my intervention; I have also been pushed to pursue issues that were either underdeveloped or inadequately addressed in my previous work. Beginning with The Challenge of Radical Atheism conference at Cornell and continuing with the colloquium on Ethics, Hospitality and Radical Atheism at Oxford as well as the Derrida and Religion conference at Harvard, I have had the good fortune to engage in direct debate with central interlocutors of the book. These debates have in turn informed the written exchanges about the book, which continue to inspire my current work. [ILLUSTRATION OMITTED] Leaving aside the specific polemics about Derrida scholarship, I would emphasize two strands of questioning that have been both the most difficult and the most productive to address. The first strand concerns the status of the structure of the trace in my argument, while the second concerns the conception of desire that informs what I call radical atheism. R.K.: Could you say more about these two strands of questioning? And how do you see them intersecting with other developments in Continental Philosophy? M.H.: The first strand of questioning can be situated in relation to a trend that is increasingly visible in Continental Philosophy, namely, a turn away from the focus on questions of language and discourse in favor of a renewed interest in questions of the real, the material, and the biological. If Saussure and linguistics once were an obligatory reference point, Darwin and evolutionary theory have increasingly come to occupy a similar position. In the wake of this development, Derrida's work is largely seen as mired in the linguistic turn or as mortgaged to an ethical and religious piety that leaves it without resources to engage the sciences and the question of material being. As I argue in Radical Atheism, however, such an assessment of deconstruction is deeply misleading. Already in Of Grammatology Derrida articulates his key notion of \"the trace\" in terms of not only linguistics and phenomenology but also natural science. My crucial point here is that Derrida defines the trace in terms of a general co-implication of time and space: it designates the becoming-space of time and the becoming-time of space, which Derrida abbreviates as spacing (espacement). Spacing is according to Derrida the condition for both the animate and the in","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"46 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-04-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125625843","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Mother and Son: The Dynamics of Hamlet’s Cartesian Madness 母亲与儿子哈姆雷特笛卡尔式疯狂的动力
Pub Date : 2011-04-04 DOI: 10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20116146
John DeCarlo
Introduction In his Hamlet essay: "Hamlet and His Problems," T.S. Eliot conceived Hamlet as an artistic failure, pointing at the inexplicable manner in which Hamlet is obsessed with his mother's behavior; and how in terms of an objective correlative, Gertrude is not only an inadequate object for the emotions generated in the play, but also unable to support them. In other words, the problem of the play lies not in the character of Hamlet, but in the author's treatment of "the effect of a mother's guilt upon her son." (1) But might there be an image that distills Hamlet's emotional connection to his mother? Picture Hamlet standing in the graveyard contemplating the universal and fleeting nature of life, while also holding the skull of Yorick, the symbol of all that is wild, silly and ridiculous. Might such a juxtaposition of consciousness correspond to the conceptual form of Descartes' Cogito, whereby a determined reason and a determined madness stand both together, and yet separate? By the same token, while Elliot's superego considered Shakespeare, the artist, incapable of controlling his disordered subjectivity and to transform it to the literary tradition that preceded him or surrounded him, might the philosophical form of the Cogito, which Shakespeare implicitly pre-figures in the play, be the form which helps to understand Hamlet's intense feelings towards his mother's sexual behavior? (2) In keeping with the assertion that the play as a whole is problematic, Eliot also suggests that Stoll is correct in steering away from a psychological reading of the leading character, in terms of staying "nearer in spirit to Shakespeare's art." (3) In this respect, it seems that Eliot is correct in asserting that some other factor must be responsible for Hamlet's emotions. However, in asserting that the dominating emotion is "inexpressible, because it is in excess of the facts as they appear" (4) seems to be misleading in terms of Eliot's underestimation of the play's philosophical dimensions, and the degree that Hamlet's psychological response to his philosophical concerns spills over to his perception and judgment of his mother's behavior. In contrast, it will be developed how Hamlet's judgment of his mother's sexual behavior and her shameless attitude toward it, is intensified by his own restless sense of shame related to his unguarded philosophical doubts. A) Hamlet's Pre-Cartesian Doubt In keeping with Eliot's assertion that "there was an older play by Thomas Kyd," (5) most critics agree that Kyd probably wrote the UR-Hamlet, performed during the late 1580's and early 1590's. Considering that Kyd's version already contained the elements of the Ghost, the play within the play, etc, as well as the conditions of the Elizabethan stage and conventions of the revenge tragedy, it would give great insight into Shakespeare's innovations and underlying intentions. Since the primary source has been irrevocably lost, Shakespeare's intentions are not clear and rem
引言 T.S. 艾略特在他的《哈姆雷特》一文中"T.S.艾略特在《哈姆雷特和他的问题》一文中,将《哈姆雷特》视为艺术上的失败,指出哈姆雷特对母亲行为的痴迷令人费解;从客观相关性的角度来看,格特鲁德不仅不是剧中情感产生的适当对象,而且也无法支撑这种情感。换言之,该剧的问题不在于哈姆雷特的性格,而在于作者对 "母亲的愧疚对儿子的影响 "的处理。(1)但是否有一个形象可以提炼出哈姆雷特与母亲的情感联系呢?想象一下,哈姆雷特站在墓地里思考生命的普遍性和短暂性,同时还拿着象征一切狂野、愚蠢和可笑的约里克的头骨。这样的意识并置是否符合笛卡尔《Cogito》的概念形式,即坚定的理性和坚定的疯狂既站在一起,又相互分离?同样,当埃利奥特的超我认为作为艺术家的莎士比亚无法控制自己混乱的主观性并将其转化为先于他或围绕着他的文学传统时,莎士比亚在剧中暗含预设的 "Cogito "的哲学形式是否有助于理解哈姆雷特对母亲性行为的强烈感受?(2)为了与 "全剧存在问题 "的论断保持一致,艾略特还认为,斯托尔从 "精神上更接近莎士比亚的艺术 "的角度出发,避免对剧中主角进行心理解读是正确的。(3)就此而言,艾略特主张哈姆雷特的情感必须由其他因素造成,似乎是正确的。然而,艾略特断言主导情感的是 "无法表达的,因为它超出了事实的表象"(4),这似乎有误导之嫌,因为艾略特低估了该剧的哲学维度,低估了哈姆雷特对其哲学关切的心理反应波及他对母亲行为的感知和判断的程度。相比之下,哈姆雷特对母亲性行为的判断以及她对性行为的无耻态度,是如何被他自己因毫无戒备的哲学疑虑而产生的躁动不安的羞耻感所强化的。A) 哈姆雷特的前笛卡尔式怀疑 艾略特曾断言 "托马斯-凯德有一个更古老的剧本",(5) 大多数评论家都认为凯德很可能创作了《哈姆雷特》(UR-Hamlet),并在 15 世纪 80 年代末和 90 年代初上演。考虑到基德的版本已经包含了《鬼魂》、戏中戏等元素,以及伊丽莎白时代的舞台条件和复仇悲剧的惯例,它可以让人对莎士比亚的创新和深层意图有更深入的了解。由于原始资料已经无可挽回地遗失,莎士比亚的意图并不明确,仍然笼罩在神秘的阴影之下。然而,与艾略特断言的 "在早先的戏剧中,动机仅仅是复仇;"(6)麦克卡里断言,尽管对复仇者角色的质疑是复仇剧体裁中的 "吱吱作响的惯例",正如《西班牙悲剧》中所展示的那样,而《哈姆雷特》与《西班牙悲剧》有着密切的相似之处,但在《哈姆雷特》中,这种质疑无疑被提升到了深刻的哲学推测的高度。(7)换句话说,尽管两剧之间存在 "言语上的相似之处",但莎士比亚并不像艾略特所说的那样,"只是修改了凯德的文本"。(8)事实上,当观众开始体验眼前展开的戏剧时,很明显,习惯上的权威被改变了,甚至被颠倒了。弗朗西斯科正在值班,而贝尔纳多显然对 "篡夺""夜晚"(I. ...
{"title":"Mother and Son: The Dynamics of Hamlet’s Cartesian Madness","authors":"John DeCarlo","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20116146","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL20116146","url":null,"abstract":"Introduction In his Hamlet essay: \"Hamlet and His Problems,\" T.S. Eliot conceived Hamlet as an artistic failure, pointing at the inexplicable manner in which Hamlet is obsessed with his mother's behavior; and how in terms of an objective correlative, Gertrude is not only an inadequate object for the emotions generated in the play, but also unable to support them. In other words, the problem of the play lies not in the character of Hamlet, but in the author's treatment of \"the effect of a mother's guilt upon her son.\" (1) But might there be an image that distills Hamlet's emotional connection to his mother? Picture Hamlet standing in the graveyard contemplating the universal and fleeting nature of life, while also holding the skull of Yorick, the symbol of all that is wild, silly and ridiculous. Might such a juxtaposition of consciousness correspond to the conceptual form of Descartes' Cogito, whereby a determined reason and a determined madness stand both together, and yet separate? By the same token, while Elliot's superego considered Shakespeare, the artist, incapable of controlling his disordered subjectivity and to transform it to the literary tradition that preceded him or surrounded him, might the philosophical form of the Cogito, which Shakespeare implicitly pre-figures in the play, be the form which helps to understand Hamlet's intense feelings towards his mother's sexual behavior? (2) In keeping with the assertion that the play as a whole is problematic, Eliot also suggests that Stoll is correct in steering away from a psychological reading of the leading character, in terms of staying \"nearer in spirit to Shakespeare's art.\" (3) In this respect, it seems that Eliot is correct in asserting that some other factor must be responsible for Hamlet's emotions. However, in asserting that the dominating emotion is \"inexpressible, because it is in excess of the facts as they appear\" (4) seems to be misleading in terms of Eliot's underestimation of the play's philosophical dimensions, and the degree that Hamlet's psychological response to his philosophical concerns spills over to his perception and judgment of his mother's behavior. In contrast, it will be developed how Hamlet's judgment of his mother's sexual behavior and her shameless attitude toward it, is intensified by his own restless sense of shame related to his unguarded philosophical doubts. A) Hamlet's Pre-Cartesian Doubt In keeping with Eliot's assertion that \"there was an older play by Thomas Kyd,\" (5) most critics agree that Kyd probably wrote the UR-Hamlet, performed during the late 1580's and early 1590's. Considering that Kyd's version already contained the elements of the Ghost, the play within the play, etc, as well as the conditions of the Elizabethan stage and conventions of the revenge tragedy, it would give great insight into Shakespeare's innovations and underlying intentions. Since the primary source has been irrevocably lost, Shakespeare's intentions are not clear and rem","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2011-04-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125742197","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1