首页 > 最新文献

Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science最新文献

英文 中文
Platonic Astronomy and the Development of Ancient Sphairopoiia 柏拉图天文学与古代球球学的发展
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2016-01-15 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2016-0010
Paul Kalligas
Abstract Plato’s views on astronomy are still somehow debated, however various scholars have associated his name with the project of “saving the appearances”, which is thought to have aimed at offering a precise geometrical account of celestial motions. A passage from Theon of Smyrna’s treatise on Platonic mathematics relates this project with the construction of mechanical models of the cosmos. New information deriving from the study of the so-called Antikythera mechanism, found nearly 100 years ago in an ancient shipwreck in the Aegean, seems to provide important technical evidence illustrating the evolution of this endeavour during the Hellenistic period.
柏拉图对天文学的看法至今仍有争议,但许多学者将他的名字与“拯救现象”的计划联系在一起,该计划被认为旨在提供天体运动的精确几何描述。士麦拿的席恩(Theon of Smyrna)关于柏拉图数学的论文中的一段话,将这个项目与宇宙力学模型的构建联系起来。近100年前,在爱琴海的一艘古沉船上发现了所谓的安提基西拉机械装置,研究得出的新信息似乎提供了重要的技术证据,说明了这种努力在希腊化时期的演变。
{"title":"Platonic Astronomy and the Development of Ancient Sphairopoiia","authors":"Paul Kalligas","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2016-0010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2016-0010","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Plato’s views on astronomy are still somehow debated, however various scholars have associated his name with the project of “saving the appearances”, which is thought to have aimed at offering a precise geometrical account of celestial motions. A passage from Theon of Smyrna’s treatise on Platonic mathematics relates this project with the construction of mechanical models of the cosmos. New information deriving from the study of the so-called Antikythera mechanism, found nearly 100 years ago in an ancient shipwreck in the Aegean, seems to provide important technical evidence illustrating the evolution of this endeavour during the Hellenistic period.","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"62 1","pages":"176 - 200"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81072385","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 19
Elemental Change in Empedocles 恩培多克勒斯的元素变化
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2016-01-15 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2016-0003
J. Palmer
Abstract This essay argues that Empedocles envisaged the elemental “roots” fire, water, earth, and air as having their own life cycles and undergoing their own transformations like virtually everything else in his system except Love and Strife. Empedocles conceives of the elements’ destruction and generation in terms of their losing and recovering their distinctive qualitative identities as they intermingle through Love’s agency and grow apart through Strife’s. This result makes it possible to understand the crucial verses Physika I.234–36 as Empedocles’ general description of the dual processes involved in the generation and destruction of all specimen compounds.
摘要本文认为,恩培多克勒斯设想的元素“根”火、水、土和空气都有自己的生命周期,并经历着自己的转变,就像他的体系中除了爱和斗争之外的几乎所有其他事物一样。恩培多克勒斯设想了元素的毁灭和生成,从它们失去和恢复其独特的定性身份的角度来看,它们通过爱的力量混合在一起,通过斗争的力量分开。这一结果使我们有可能理解关键的诗句Physika I.234-36是恩培多克勒斯对所有样品化合物的产生和破坏所涉及的双重过程的一般描述。
{"title":"Elemental Change in Empedocles","authors":"J. Palmer","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2016-0003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2016-0003","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This essay argues that Empedocles envisaged the elemental “roots” fire, water, earth, and air as having their own life cycles and undergoing their own transformations like virtually everything else in his system except Love and Strife. Empedocles conceives of the elements’ destruction and generation in terms of their losing and recovering their distinctive qualitative identities as they intermingle through Love’s agency and grow apart through Strife’s. This result makes it possible to understand the crucial verses Physika I.234–36 as Empedocles’ general description of the dual processes involved in the generation and destruction of all specimen compounds.","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"9 1","pages":"30 - 54"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73984531","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
David Sider and Dirk Obbink (eds.), Doctrine and Doxography: Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras 大卫·赛德和德克·奥宾克(编),学说和文献:赫拉克利特和毕达哥拉斯的研究
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2016-01-15 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2016-0015
P. Curd
This splendid book has been worth the wait. The papers collected here (four on Pythagoras and eight on Heraclitus) were presented in 2005 at “a bicontinental conference” (as the editors call it) on Samos and in Kuşadaı, organized by Apostolos Pierris of the Institute for Philosophical Research.1 This rich mixture of essays by established international scholars nicely complements the collection from the 2012 Symposium Praesocraticum on Heraclitus published in this journal’s volume 3 issue 1 in 2015, and other recent books on Heraclitus or Pythagoras.2 In the opening essay, “Philosophy’s Numerical Turn: Why the Pythagoreans’ Interest in Numbers is Truly Awesome”, Catherine Rowett fearlessly takes on the problems of just what it was about numbers that interested early Pythagoreans (including the elusive Pythagoras himself) and why. Rowett argues that the pre-Platonic Pythagoreans, in exploring harmony theory and its ratios (which she sees also in pre-Philolaus Pythagoreanism), deserve as much philosophical credit for commitments to reason and to order as Anaximander (who posits a mysterious apeiron) and Heraclitus (who argues that everything happens in accordance with the logos, the fundamental principle(s) of order and rationality).3 That none of these theories turn out to be correct is irrelevant, for all share the fundamental Presocratic philosophical commitment to order and explanation, and to the beauty of the cosmos. What Rowett finds particularly important and worth admiration and celebration in the “Pythagorean turn” as it develops through early Pythagoreanism, Philolaus and Archytas, is its reliance on mathematical knowledge as a prerequisite to any other knowledge and its emerging view of number as incorporeal. Rowett argues that Pythagoreanism begins with a commitment to “the explanatory power of beauty, structure, form, and indeed teleology, in the universe”; thinking of it this way shows how the “idea of appealing
这本精彩的书值得等待。这里收集的论文(四篇关于毕达哥拉斯,八篇关于赫拉克利特)于2005年在萨莫斯和ku adaii上的“双大陆会议”(编辑们这样称呼它)上发表,由哲学研究所的Apostolos Pierris组织。这一丰富的国际学者论文的混合物很好地补充了2012年发表在该杂志第3卷第1期上的关于赫拉克利特的研讨会。在开篇文章《哲学的数字转向:为什么毕达哥拉斯学派对数字的兴趣是真正令人敬畏的》中,凯瑟琳·罗威特大胆地探讨了早期毕达哥拉斯学派(包括难以捉摸的毕达哥拉斯本人)对数字感兴趣的原因及其原因。Rowett认为,柏拉图之前的毕达哥拉斯学派,在探索和谐理论及其比率(她也在菲洛劳斯之前的毕达哥拉斯主义中看到)中,与阿那克西曼德(他假设了一个神秘的apeiron)和赫拉克利特(他认为一切都是按照逻各斯,秩序和理性的基本原则发生的)一样,应该得到同样多的理性和秩序的哲学荣誉这些理论都没有被证明是正确的,这是无关紧要的,因为它们都有着前苏格拉底哲学对秩序和解释的基本承诺,以及对宇宙之美的承诺。在早期毕达哥拉斯主义(Philolaus和Archytas)发展起来的“毕达哥拉斯转向”中,Rowett发现特别重要和值得钦佩和庆祝的是,它对数学知识的依赖,将其作为任何其他知识的先决条件,以及它新兴的非物质数观。罗威特认为,毕达哥拉斯主义始于对“宇宙中美、结构、形式以及目的论的解释力”的承诺;从这个角度思考,可以看出“吸引人的想法”是怎样的
{"title":"David Sider and Dirk Obbink (eds.), Doctrine and Doxography: Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras","authors":"P. Curd","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2016-0015","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2016-0015","url":null,"abstract":"This splendid book has been worth the wait. The papers collected here (four on Pythagoras and eight on Heraclitus) were presented in 2005 at “a bicontinental conference” (as the editors call it) on Samos and in Kuşadaı, organized by Apostolos Pierris of the Institute for Philosophical Research.1 This rich mixture of essays by established international scholars nicely complements the collection from the 2012 Symposium Praesocraticum on Heraclitus published in this journal’s volume 3 issue 1 in 2015, and other recent books on Heraclitus or Pythagoras.2 In the opening essay, “Philosophy’s Numerical Turn: Why the Pythagoreans’ Interest in Numbers is Truly Awesome”, Catherine Rowett fearlessly takes on the problems of just what it was about numbers that interested early Pythagoreans (including the elusive Pythagoras himself) and why. Rowett argues that the pre-Platonic Pythagoreans, in exploring harmony theory and its ratios (which she sees also in pre-Philolaus Pythagoreanism), deserve as much philosophical credit for commitments to reason and to order as Anaximander (who posits a mysterious apeiron) and Heraclitus (who argues that everything happens in accordance with the logos, the fundamental principle(s) of order and rationality).3 That none of these theories turn out to be correct is irrelevant, for all share the fundamental Presocratic philosophical commitment to order and explanation, and to the beauty of the cosmos. What Rowett finds particularly important and worth admiration and celebration in the “Pythagorean turn” as it develops through early Pythagoreanism, Philolaus and Archytas, is its reliance on mathematical knowledge as a prerequisite to any other knowledge and its emerging view of number as incorporeal. Rowett argues that Pythagoreanism begins with a commitment to “the explanatory power of beauty, structure, form, and indeed teleology, in the universe”; thinking of it this way shows how the “idea of appealing","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"104 1","pages":"1 - 276 - 287 - 349"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74997763","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Actuality of the Movable (by the Mover): a Relational Interpretation of Aristotle’s Definition of Motion 可动物的现实性(由动者):亚里士多德运动定义的关系解释
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2016-01-15 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2016-0012
Monica Ugaglia
Abstract The paper discusses Aristotle’s conception of motion and proposes a new perspective for a reading. Of course, motion can be located between two states of a movable, between potentiality and actuality, but it can also be located between (the state of) a movable and (that of) its mover. It is also argued that this relational perspective is the correct way to understand Aristotle’s definition of motion. When Aristotle defines motion as “the actuality of what potentially is, qua such” he does not simply mean that motion is “the actuality of the movable”: by being the actuality of the movable “qua movable”, motion is also the actuality of the mover. Indeed, in its proper meaning, ‘movable’ does not refer to a per se entity. Instead it is a relative term, always standing for “movable by the mover”; the qua-clause is intended to stress this relational aspect.
本文讨论了亚里士多德的运动概念,并提出了一个新的阅读视角。当然,运动可以位于可动物体的两种状态之间,即潜在状态和现实性之间,但它也可以位于可动物体和被动物体之间。本文还认为,这种关系视角是理解亚里士多德运动定义的正确方式。当亚里士多德将运动定义为“潜在存在的现实性”时,他并不仅仅意味着运动是“可动之物的现实性”:作为可动之物的现实性,运动也是动者的现实性。事实上,“可移动的”在其适当的意义上并不是指一个实体本身。相反,它是一个相对术语,总是代表“由移动者移动”;限定从句旨在强调这种关系方面。
{"title":"The Actuality of the Movable (by the Mover): a Relational Interpretation of Aristotle’s Definition of Motion","authors":"Monica Ugaglia","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2016-0012","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2016-0012","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The paper discusses Aristotle’s conception of motion and proposes a new perspective for a reading. Of course, motion can be located between two states of a movable, between potentiality and actuality, but it can also be located between (the state of) a movable and (that of) its mover. It is also argued that this relational perspective is the correct way to understand Aristotle’s definition of motion. When Aristotle defines motion as “the actuality of what potentially is, qua such” he does not simply mean that motion is “the actuality of the movable”: by being the actuality of the movable “qua movable”, motion is also the actuality of the mover. Indeed, in its proper meaning, ‘movable’ does not refer to a per se entity. Instead it is a relative term, always standing for “movable by the mover”; the qua-clause is intended to stress this relational aspect.","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"14 1","pages":"225 - 256"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81499281","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Gabriele Cornelli, Richard McKirahan, and Constantinos Macris (eds.), On Pythagoreanism
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2016-01-15 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2016-0014
P. Horky
{"title":"Gabriele Cornelli, Richard McKirahan, and Constantinos Macris (eds.), On Pythagoreanism","authors":"P. Horky","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2016-0014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2016-0014","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"10 1","pages":"1 - 269 - 275 - 532"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78556125","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Francesco Verde, Epicuro 弗朗西斯科·佛得角,伊壁鸠鲁
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2016-01-15 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2016-0016
M. Monti
{"title":"Francesco Verde, Epicuro","authors":"M. Monti","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2016-0016","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2016-0016","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"19 1","pages":"1 - 276 - 287 - 292"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79850927","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Empedocles’ Cosmic Cycle and the Pythagorean Tetractys 恩培多克勒的宇宙循环和毕达哥拉斯的四元学说
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2016-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2016-0002
Oliver Primavesi
Abstract Empedocles posits six fundamental principles of the world: Love, Strife and the four elements (rhizōmata). On the cosmic level, he describes the interaction of the principles as an eternal recurrence of the same, i.e. as a cosmic cycle. The cycle is subject to a time-table the evidence for which was discovered by Marwan Rashed and has been edited by him in 2001 and 2014. The purpose of the present paper is to show that this timetable is based on the numerical ratios of the Pythagorean tetractys.
恩培多克勒斯提出了世界的六大基本原则:爱、斗争和四要素(rhizōmata)。在宇宙层面上,他把这些原理的相互作用描述为同一事物的永恒循环,即宇宙循环。这个周期有一个时间表,证据是由马尔万·拉希德(Marwan Rashed)发现的,并在2001年和2014年进行了编辑。本文的目的是要说明,这个时间表是建立在毕达哥拉斯四律的数值比率的基础上的。
{"title":"Empedocles’ Cosmic Cycle and the Pythagorean Tetractys","authors":"Oliver Primavesi","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2016-0002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2016-0002","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Empedocles posits six fundamental principles of the world: Love, Strife and the four elements (rhizōmata). On the cosmic level, he describes the interaction of the principles as an eternal recurrence of the same, i.e. as a cosmic cycle. The cycle is subject to a time-table the evidence for which was discovered by Marwan Rashed and has been edited by him in 2001 and 2014. The purpose of the present paper is to show that this timetable is based on the numerical ratios of the Pythagorean tetractys.","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"41 1","pages":"29 - 5"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"76374252","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
Empedoclean Superorganisms Empedoclean超级有机体
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2016-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2016-0006
D. Sedley
In Empedocles’ zoogony, an original set of single-specialism organisms – solitary hands, eyes, etc. – combined into complex organisms, of which the fittest survived. A less recognized anticipation of (one strand of) the Darwinian tradition relates to the superorganism theory: what is naturally selected for is not the individual and/or its kin, but, as most manifestly in insect colonies, the cooperative group. Empedocles’ Love likewise works by promoting co-operation, whose emergence in complex organisms reflects her growing power, and the periodic world-organism, Sphairos, her ultimate triumph. This latter divinity is not a homogeneous blend of the elements, but a single self-sufficient superorganism.
在恩培多克勒斯的动物学中,最初的一组单一的生物——孤独的手、眼睛等——结合成复杂的生物,其中最适合的存活了下来。达尔文传统的(一条)不太为人所知的预期与超有机体理论有关:自然选择的不是个体和/或其亲属,而是合作群体,这一点在昆虫群体中最为明显。恩培多克勒斯的《爱》同样通过促进合作而起作用,这种合作在复杂生物体中的出现反映了她不断增长的力量,而周期性的世界生物体斯海罗斯则是她的最终胜利。后一种神性不是元素的同质混合,而是单一的自给自足的超有机体。
{"title":"Empedoclean Superorganisms","authors":"D. Sedley","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2016-0006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2016-0006","url":null,"abstract":"In Empedocles’ zoogony, an original set of single-specialism organisms – solitary hands, eyes, etc. – combined into complex organisms, of which the fittest survived. A less recognized anticipation of (one strand of) the Darwinian tradition relates to the superorganism theory: what is naturally selected for is not the individual and/or its kin, but, as most manifestly in insect colonies, the cooperative group. Empedocles’ Love likewise works by promoting co-operation, whose emergence in complex organisms reflects her growing power, and the periodic world-organism, Sphairos, her ultimate triumph. This latter divinity is not a homogeneous blend of the elements, but a single self-sufficient superorganism.","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"39 1","pages":"111 - 125"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77823412","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 25
Mimesis, Friendship, and Moral Development in Aristotle’s Ethics 亚里士多德伦理学中的拟态、友谊与道德发展
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2015-12-01 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2015-0007
Andreas Vakirtzis
Abstract The significance of imitation for moral development during childhood, in Aristotle’s ethics, has been recognized and studied. However, what role does imitation play in the morally mature agent’s character development? In this paper, I argue that moral development is possible for the advanced moral agent, when she imitates her character-friend. But the mature agent’s imitation is of a thoroughly different type than the imitation of the young moral agent; the mature imitation mechanism is selective and interpretative. The agent selects from the goodness in her friend, depending on the agent’s own sensitivities, and adopts this goodness as a pattern that allows for personalized implementations, depending on her own dispositions and skills. In this way, the morally mature agent develops her moral character by enriching her epistemic tools and experience within the spectrum of the good.
在亚里士多德的伦理学中,模仿对儿童时期道德发展的重要性得到了认可和研究。然而,模仿在道德成熟行为人的性格发展中起着怎样的作用?在本文中,我认为当高级道德行为人模仿她的角色朋友时,道德发展是可能的。但成熟行为人的模仿与年轻道德行为人的模仿是完全不同的类型;成熟的模仿机制具有选择性和解释性。代理根据自己的敏感性,从朋友的优点中进行选择,并根据自己的性格和技能,采用这种优点作为允许个性化实现的模式。通过这种方式,道德成熟的行动者通过在善的范围内丰富她的认知工具和经验来发展她的道德品质。
{"title":"Mimesis, Friendship, and Moral Development in Aristotle’s Ethics","authors":"Andreas Vakirtzis","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2015-0007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2015-0007","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The significance of imitation for moral development during childhood, in Aristotle’s ethics, has been recognized and studied. However, what role does imitation play in the morally mature agent’s character development? In this paper, I argue that moral development is possible for the advanced moral agent, when she imitates her character-friend. But the mature agent’s imitation is of a thoroughly different type than the imitation of the young moral agent; the mature imitation mechanism is selective and interpretative. The agent selects from the goodness in her friend, depending on the agent’s own sensitivities, and adopts this goodness as a pattern that allows for personalized implementations, depending on her own dispositions and skills. In this way, the morally mature agent develops her moral character by enriching her epistemic tools and experience within the spectrum of the good.","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"28 1","pages":"125 - 142"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2015-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82840868","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Melissus’s So-called Refutation of Mixture 梅利苏斯所谓的“混合驳斥”
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2015-12-01 DOI: 10.1515/rhiz-2015-0008
Mathilde Brémond
Abstract There is discussion among critics about the authenticity of Pseudo-Aristotle’s account on Melissus in the De Melisso, Xenophane, Gorgia, and especially about the refutation of mixture that he attributes to the latter. For there is no clue in the other testimonies and in the fragments that the Eleatic made such a refutation. In this article, I aim to show that the argument as it is presented is not genuinely Melissean, but inspired by some of Aristotle’s considerations on colour-mixture in the De sensu. I then claim that taking this source into account solves many of the difficulties inherent to this demonstration against mixture, and reveals something on Pseudo-Aristotle’s doxographical approach.
摘要在《论梅利索、色诺芬、高尔吉亚》中,伪亚里士多德对梅利索斯的描述的真实性存在争议,特别是他认为后者对混合的反驳。因为在其他的证词和碎片中,没有线索表明埃利亚提亚作了这样的反驳。在这篇文章中,我的目的是表明,这一论点并不是真正的梅利森式的,而是受到亚里士多德在《论感性》中关于颜色混合的一些考虑的启发。然后,我声称,考虑到这个来源,解决了许多固有的困难,以证明反对混合,并揭示了一些伪亚里士多德的文献方法。
{"title":"Melissus’s So-called Refutation of Mixture","authors":"Mathilde Brémond","doi":"10.1515/rhiz-2015-0008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2015-0008","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract There is discussion among critics about the authenticity of Pseudo-Aristotle’s account on Melissus in the De Melisso, Xenophane, Gorgia, and especially about the refutation of mixture that he attributes to the latter. For there is no clue in the other testimonies and in the fragments that the Eleatic made such a refutation. In this article, I aim to show that the argument as it is presented is not genuinely Melissean, but inspired by some of Aristotle’s considerations on colour-mixture in the De sensu. I then claim that taking this source into account solves many of the difficulties inherent to this demonstration against mixture, and reveals something on Pseudo-Aristotle’s doxographical approach.","PeriodicalId":40571,"journal":{"name":"Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science","volume":"9 1","pages":"143 - 158"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2015-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85655901","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
期刊
Rhizomata-A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1