首页 > 最新文献

International Journal of Philosophy and Theology最新文献

英文 中文
Freud’s Moses and Fromm’s Freud: Erich Fromm’s silence on Freud’s Moses – a silence of negation or a silence of consent? 弗洛伊德的摩西和弗洛姆的弗洛伊德:弗洛姆对弗洛伊德的摩西的沉默——否定的沉默还是同意的沉默?
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-08-08 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2140184
Ronen Pinkas
ABSTRACT In 1939 Sigmund Freud published his latest book, Moses and Monotheism, which is his most unusual and problematic work. In Moses Freud offers four groundbreaking claims in regard to the biblical story: [a] Moses was an Egyptian [b] The origin of monotheism is not Judaism [c] Moses was murdered by the Jews [d] The murder sparked a constant sense of unconscious guilt, which eventually contributed to the rational and ethical development of Jewish monotheism. As is well known, Freud’s Moses received extremely negative reviews from Jewish thinkers. The social psychoanalyst, Erich Fromm, who wrote extensively on Freud as well as on Judaism and the biblical narrative, did not explicitly express his position on Freud’s latest work. This paper offers explanations for Fromm’s roaring silence on Freud’s Moses.
摘要1939年,弗洛伊德出版了他的最新著作《摩西与一神论》,这是他最不寻常和最有问题的作品。在《摩西》一书中,弗洛伊德就圣经故事提出了四个开创性的主张:【a】摩西是埃及人【b】一神教的起源不是犹太教【c】摩西是被犹太人谋杀的【d】谋杀引发了一种持续的无意识的负罪感,最终促成了犹太一神教在理性和伦理方面的发展。众所周知,弗洛伊德的《摩西》受到了犹太思想家极其负面的评价。社会精神分析学家Erich Fromm撰写了大量关于弗洛伊德、犹太教和圣经叙事的文章,但他没有明确表达他对弗洛伊德最新作品的立场。本文对弗洛姆对弗洛伊德《摩西》的咆哮式沉默作了解释。
{"title":"Freud’s Moses and Fromm’s Freud: Erich Fromm’s silence on Freud’s Moses – a silence of negation or a silence of consent?","authors":"Ronen Pinkas","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2140184","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2140184","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT In 1939 Sigmund Freud published his latest book, Moses and Monotheism, which is his most unusual and problematic work. In Moses Freud offers four groundbreaking claims in regard to the biblical story: [a] Moses was an Egyptian [b] The origin of monotheism is not Judaism [c] Moses was murdered by the Jews [d] The murder sparked a constant sense of unconscious guilt, which eventually contributed to the rational and ethical development of Jewish monotheism. As is well known, Freud’s Moses received extremely negative reviews from Jewish thinkers. The social psychoanalyst, Erich Fromm, who wrote extensively on Freud as well as on Judaism and the biblical narrative, did not explicitly express his position on Freud’s latest work. This paper offers explanations for Fromm’s roaring silence on Freud’s Moses.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-08-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45887767","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Depth of Reason: Kant, Marx, and Heidegger in the Deconstruction of Christianity 理性的深度:康德、马克思和海德格尔对基督教的解构
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-05-27 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2093776
Nikolaas Cassidy‐Deketelaere
ABSTRACT Jean-Luc Nancy’s so-called ‘deconstruction of Christianity’ is usually understood as both a philosophy of culture (in line with various other exercises in ‘post-secular’ thought) and a critique of metaphysics (in line with Jacques Derrida’s deconstruction of the metaphysics of presence). This article, however, argues that its primary concern is neither the Christian religion as a cultural formation, nor the exhaustion of the metaphysical enterprise. Instead, by looking at some of the philosophical sources on which Nancy’s project is built – namely, Immanuel Kant, Karl Marx, and Martin Heidegger –, the article suggests that its true aim is to develop a new understanding of reason, or to renew the experience of reason. Though these authors have largely been neglected by the growing discussion of Nancy’s deconstruction of Christianity, the article shows how it is only by developing his occasional references to them that we can come to appreciate an important but neglected dimension of this project: namely, the fact that it is an exercise in philosophical anthropology, i.e. an inquiry into the exact nature of the reason that supposedly characterises the rational animal.
文摘jean - luc南希的所谓的“解构主义的基督教”通常被理解为一个文化哲学(与其他各种演习“post-secular”思想)和批判形而上学(符合雅克·德里达的解构主义的形而上学的存在)。然而,本文认为,它的主要关注点既不是基督教作为一种文化形态,也不是形而上学事业的枯竭。相反,通过观察南希的项目所依据的一些哲学来源——即伊曼努尔·康德、卡尔·马克思和马丁·海德格尔——文章表明,它的真正目的是发展对理性的新理解,或者更新理性的经验。尽管这些作者在很大程度上被南希解构基督教的讨论所忽视,但这篇文章表明,只有通过发展他偶尔提到的他们,我们才能欣赏到这个项目的一个重要但被忽视的方面:即,这是一个哲学人类学的实践,即对理性动物特征的理性的确切本质的探究。
{"title":"The Depth of Reason: Kant, Marx, and Heidegger in the Deconstruction of Christianity","authors":"Nikolaas Cassidy‐Deketelaere","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2093776","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2093776","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Jean-Luc Nancy’s so-called ‘deconstruction of Christianity’ is usually understood as both a philosophy of culture (in line with various other exercises in ‘post-secular’ thought) and a critique of metaphysics (in line with Jacques Derrida’s deconstruction of the metaphysics of presence). This article, however, argues that its primary concern is neither the Christian religion as a cultural formation, nor the exhaustion of the metaphysical enterprise. Instead, by looking at some of the philosophical sources on which Nancy’s project is built – namely, Immanuel Kant, Karl Marx, and Martin Heidegger –, the article suggests that its true aim is to develop a new understanding of reason, or to renew the experience of reason. Though these authors have largely been neglected by the growing discussion of Nancy’s deconstruction of Christianity, the article shows how it is only by developing his occasional references to them that we can come to appreciate an important but neglected dimension of this project: namely, the fact that it is an exercise in philosophical anthropology, i.e. an inquiry into the exact nature of the reason that supposedly characterises the rational animal.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44824341","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The concepts of the sublime and the saturated phenomenon in Immanuel Kant and Jean-Luc Marion: a systematic comparison based on their philosophical origins 康德与马里恩的崇高概念与饱和现象:基于哲学渊源的系统比较
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-05-27 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2127421
A. Karpiński
ABSTRACT This paper is a systematic comparison between two well–known and theologically relevant concepts – the sublime as developed in Kant’s third Critique, and Marion’s saturated phenomenon. Although it discusses the significant and apparent similarities between them, it also criticizes Marion’s identification of the sublime as a possible example of a saturated phenomenon. This is primarily because of the different origins and philosophical presuppositions guiding the elaboration of these two ideas. Kant’s aim is to confine the reception of the phenomenon to the conditions of experience, so that both in the case of judg-ments of beauty and judg-ments of the sublime, the subject achieves pleasure through self-centred appreciation of its rational capacities. Marion’s saturated phenomenon, on the other hand, aims at dispensing with the ‘metaphysical’ horizon of either the object, or the transcendental subject, in favour of passive appropriation of givenness. Although both are meant to describe what happens when the limits of understanding are breached, in the sublime this breach only serves to reinforce the capacity of the rational subject, whereas in the saturated phenomenon it points to the possibility of apprehension of the totally Other as purely given.
摘要本文系统地比较了康德第三次批判中提出的崇高和马里昂的饱和现象这两个著名的神学相关概念。尽管它讨论了它们之间显著而明显的相似之处,但它也批评了马里昂将崇高视为饱和现象的可能例子。这主要是因为指导这两种思想阐述的不同起源和哲学预设。康德的目的是将对现象的接受限制在经验的条件下,这样,无论是在对美的判断还是对崇高的判断中,主体都通过以自我为中心的对其理性能力的欣赏来获得快乐。另一方面,马里昂的饱和现象旨在摒弃对象或先验主体的“形而上学”视野,而倾向于被动挪用给予性。尽管两者都是为了描述当理解的极限被突破时会发生什么,但在崇高中,这种突破只会加强理性主体的能力,而在饱和现象中,它指向了对纯粹给定的完全他者的理解的可能性。
{"title":"The concepts of the sublime and the saturated phenomenon in Immanuel Kant and Jean-Luc Marion: a systematic comparison based on their philosophical origins","authors":"A. Karpiński","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2127421","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2127421","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT This paper is a systematic comparison between two well–known and theologically relevant concepts – the sublime as developed in Kant’s third Critique, and Marion’s saturated phenomenon. Although it discusses the significant and apparent similarities between them, it also criticizes Marion’s identification of the sublime as a possible example of a saturated phenomenon. This is primarily because of the different origins and philosophical presuppositions guiding the elaboration of these two ideas. Kant’s aim is to confine the reception of the phenomenon to the conditions of experience, so that both in the case of judg-ments of beauty and judg-ments of the sublime, the subject achieves pleasure through self-centred appreciation of its rational capacities. Marion’s saturated phenomenon, on the other hand, aims at dispensing with the ‘metaphysical’ horizon of either the object, or the transcendental subject, in favour of passive appropriation of givenness. Although both are meant to describe what happens when the limits of understanding are breached, in the sublime this breach only serves to reinforce the capacity of the rational subject, whereas in the saturated phenomenon it points to the possibility of apprehension of the totally Other as purely given.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47874955","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Does the sovereign exist? Robert Musil’s political theology 主权者存在吗?罗伯特·穆希尔的政治神学
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-05-27 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2127420
Z. Balázs
ABSTRACT The paper discusses a possible political theological interpretation of arguments developed in Robert Musil’s The Man Without Qualities. What emerges is that Musil (or his characters) pose a fundamental challenge to the possibility of any real analogy between God and the political sovereign, as suggested by Carl Schmitt. At stake is Austria as a yet-to-be-born modern sovereign. However, the novel shows why attempts to conceive it in an image of God all fail. After surveying four such attempts, the main focus will be the discussion of Anselm of Canterbury’s existential argument in this secular context. At Diotima’s inspiration it is General von Bordwehr, a largely neglected figure, who makes the most serious attempt to argue for the political sovereign as the greatest conceivable thing. The argument is that greatness entails containing every idea and its opposite, and this yields the concept of order. But order means the frozen end of everything. Hence, instead of a living God, we end up with a political sovereign marked by death.
本文讨论了对罗伯特·穆希尔《没有品质的人》中论点的一种可能的政治神学解释。正如卡尔·施密特(Carl Schmitt)所指出的那样,穆希尔(或他笔下的人物)对上帝与政治君主之间任何真正类比的可能性提出了根本性的挑战。这关系到奥地利作为一个尚未诞生的现代君主的地位。然而,这部小说展示了为什么试图把它想象成上帝的形象都失败了。在考察了四种这样的尝试之后,主要的焦点将是在这种世俗背景下讨论坎特伯雷的安瑟伦的存在主义论点。受到狄奥蒂玛启发的是冯·博尔德韦尔将军,一个几乎被忽视的人物,他做出了最严肃的尝试,认为政治主权是可以想象到的最伟大的东西。他们的论点是,伟大需要包含每一种思想及其对立面,这就产生了秩序的概念。但秩序意味着一切的终结。因此,我们面对的不是一个永生的上帝,而是一个以死亡为标志的政治主权。
{"title":"Does the sovereign exist? Robert Musil’s political theology","authors":"Z. Balázs","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2127420","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2127420","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT The paper discusses a possible political theological interpretation of arguments developed in Robert Musil’s The Man Without Qualities. What emerges is that Musil (or his characters) pose a fundamental challenge to the possibility of any real analogy between God and the political sovereign, as suggested by Carl Schmitt. At stake is Austria as a yet-to-be-born modern sovereign. However, the novel shows why attempts to conceive it in an image of God all fail. After surveying four such attempts, the main focus will be the discussion of Anselm of Canterbury’s existential argument in this secular context. At Diotima’s inspiration it is General von Bordwehr, a largely neglected figure, who makes the most serious attempt to argue for the political sovereign as the greatest conceivable thing. The argument is that greatness entails containing every idea and its opposite, and this yields the concept of order. But order means the frozen end of everything. Hence, instead of a living God, we end up with a political sovereign marked by death.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46677012","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Giving up on knowing and loving oneself: Anders Nygren, Hannah Arendt, and Augustine 放弃认识和爱自己:安德斯·尼格伦、汉娜·阿伦特和奥古斯丁
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-05-27 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2127419
Torbjörn Gustafsson Chorell
ABSTRACT Anders Nygren’s and Hannah Arendt’s critical reading of Augustine’s concept of love had its point of departure in a fundamental skepticism towards the possibility of knowing oneself. Nygren defended the need to give up the search for the ego in order to enter a fellowship with God, whereas Arendt’s turn toward the world necessitated a critical evaluation of self-love and the search for inner motivations for action in a unified self. Arendt’s solution in particular suggests that the fate of the tradition of gnothi seauton was to surrender to the new discourse on identity that effectively turned Augustine’s question of himself from a puzzle solved by inwardness into a question of performance and encounters with others.
安德斯·尼格伦和汉娜·阿伦特对奥古斯丁爱情观的批判性解读,其出发点是对认识自己的可能性的根本怀疑。尼格伦为放弃寻找自我以进入与上帝的关系辩护,而阿伦特转向世界需要对自爱进行批判性的评估,并在一个统一的自我中寻找行动的内在动机。阿伦特的解决方案特别表明,灵知传统的命运是屈服于关于身份的新话语,这种话语有效地将奥古斯丁关于自己的问题从一个由内在解决的谜题转变为一个表现和与他人相遇的问题。
{"title":"Giving up on knowing and loving oneself: Anders Nygren, Hannah Arendt, and Augustine","authors":"Torbjörn Gustafsson Chorell","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2127419","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2127419","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Anders Nygren’s and Hannah Arendt’s critical reading of Augustine’s concept of love had its point of departure in a fundamental skepticism towards the possibility of knowing oneself. Nygren defended the need to give up the search for the ego in order to enter a fellowship with God, whereas Arendt’s turn toward the world necessitated a critical evaluation of self-love and the search for inner motivations for action in a unified self. Arendt’s solution in particular suggests that the fate of the tradition of gnothi seauton was to surrender to the new discourse on identity that effectively turned Augustine’s question of himself from a puzzle solved by inwardness into a question of performance and encounters with others.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46649417","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The affinity between artistic creation in Heidegger and divine creation in Schelling 论海德格尔的艺术创作与谢林的神性创作的契合
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-05-27 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2128857
Yu Xia
ABSTRACT The majority of the contemporary literature on Schelling and Heidegger focuses on the direct connection between the two philosophers – Heidegger’s engagement with Schelling’s Freedom essay. This paper, however, explores an implicit link between them on the topic of creation by reading Schelling’s Ages of the World alongside Heidegger’s ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’. It brings God’s creation in Schelling together with artistic creation in Heidegger and argues that the two have similarities in their structures, sources, and aims: both creations are dependent on a two-fold struggle, the sources are either the absolute (in Schelling) or being (in Heidegger), and the aims are to reveal the divine principle (in Schelling) or the truth of being (in Heidegger) in the world. In making these comparisons, I argue that, in spite of Heidegger’s esoteric neologisms, his account of artistic creation is not as radically new as he himself claims. It can be read and better comprehended in the light of a Schellingian metaphysics of creation and, more broadly, in the light of the history of philosophy in general. Eventually, Heidegger’s philosophy remains committed to the tradition of philosophical theology, despite his own attempt to move beyond this tradition.
当代大多数关于谢林和海德格尔的文献都集中在这两位哲学家之间的直接联系上——海德格尔与谢林的《自由》论文的接触。然而,本文通过阅读谢林的《世界时代》和海德格尔的《艺术作品的起源》,探讨了他们之间在创作主题上的隐含联系。将谢林的上帝创造与海德格尔的艺术创造结合在一起,认为两者在结构、来源和目的上具有相似性:两者的创造都依赖于双重斗争,来源要么是绝对(谢林),要么是存在(海德格尔),目的是揭示世界上的神圣原则(谢林),要么是存在的真理(海德格尔)。在进行这些比较时,我认为,尽管海德格尔有深奥的新词,但他对艺术创造的描述并不像他自己声称的那样彻底新颖。根据谢林的创造形而上学,更广泛地说,根据一般哲学史,可以更好地阅读和理解它。最终,海德格尔的哲学仍然致力于哲学神学的传统,尽管他自己试图超越这一传统。
{"title":"The affinity between artistic creation in Heidegger and divine creation in Schelling","authors":"Yu Xia","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2128857","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2128857","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT The majority of the contemporary literature on Schelling and Heidegger focuses on the direct connection between the two philosophers – Heidegger’s engagement with Schelling’s Freedom essay. This paper, however, explores an implicit link between them on the topic of creation by reading Schelling’s Ages of the World alongside Heidegger’s ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’. It brings God’s creation in Schelling together with artistic creation in Heidegger and argues that the two have similarities in their structures, sources, and aims: both creations are dependent on a two-fold struggle, the sources are either the absolute (in Schelling) or being (in Heidegger), and the aims are to reveal the divine principle (in Schelling) or the truth of being (in Heidegger) in the world. In making these comparisons, I argue that, in spite of Heidegger’s esoteric neologisms, his account of artistic creation is not as radically new as he himself claims. It can be read and better comprehended in the light of a Schellingian metaphysics of creation and, more broadly, in the light of the history of philosophy in general. Eventually, Heidegger’s philosophy remains committed to the tradition of philosophical theology, despite his own attempt to move beyond this tradition.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41953939","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The symbolic order and the noosphere: Pierre Teilhard de Chardin and Jacques Lacan on technoscience and the future of the planet 象征秩序和人类圈:皮埃尔·德·德·夏尔丹和雅克·拉康论科技和地球的未来
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-05-27 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2093775
H. Zwart
ABSTRACT This paper presents a mutual confrontation of the oeuvres of Pierre Teilhard de Chardin (1881–1955) and Jacques Lacan (1901–1980), highlighting their relevance for the planetary challenges we are facing today. I will present their views on technoscience, environmental pollution and religious faith, focussing on human genomics as a case study. Both authors claim that technoscience reflects a tendency towards symbolisation: incorporating the biosphere (living nature) into the “symbolic order’ (Lacan) or ‘noosphere’ (Teilhard). On various occasions, Lacan refers to Teilhard’s concept of the hominization of the planet and their dialogue culminates in a ‘final conversation’ between Teilhard and Lacan in 1954, during a reception organised by the journal Psyché. I will conclude that the Teilhard-Lacan dialogue is highly relevant for current debates concerning the Anthropocene, as a moment of global awakening and global crisis. Processes of hominization allowed humans to become literate beings, littering the planet as well: humans as literate litterers. Whereas Teilhard argues that technoscience and self-directed evolution are about to culminate in what he refers to as point Omega, Lacan rather stresses the hazards involved in this optimistic desire towards all-encompassing synthesis, unification and fulfilment.
摘要本文介绍了Pierre Teilhard de Chardin(1881–1955)和Jacques Lacan(1901–1980)的作品的相互对抗,强调了它们与我们今天面临的行星挑战的相关性。我将介绍他们对技术科学、环境污染和宗教信仰的看法,重点是人类基因组学作为一个案例研究。两位作者都声称,技术科学反映了一种象征化的趋势:将生物圈(活的自然)纳入“象征秩序”(Lacan)或“noosphere”(Teilhard)在各种场合,拉康都提到了泰尔哈德关于地球人类化的概念,他们的对话在1954年泰尔哈德和拉康在《Psyché》杂志组织的招待会上的“最后对话”中达到了高潮。我的结论是,作为全球觉醒和全球危机的时刻,Teilhard-Lacan对话与当前关于人类世的辩论高度相关。人类化的过程使人类成为有文化的人,也在地球上乱扔垃圾:人类是有文化的乱扔垃圾者。Teilhard认为,技术科学和自我导向的进化即将达到他所说的欧米茄点,而Lacan则强调了这种对全面综合、统一和实现的乐观愿望所涉及的危险。
{"title":"The symbolic order and the noosphere: Pierre Teilhard de Chardin and Jacques Lacan on technoscience and the future of the planet","authors":"H. Zwart","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2093775","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2093775","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT This paper presents a mutual confrontation of the oeuvres of Pierre Teilhard de Chardin (1881–1955) and Jacques Lacan (1901–1980), highlighting their relevance for the planetary challenges we are facing today. I will present their views on technoscience, environmental pollution and religious faith, focussing on human genomics as a case study. Both authors claim that technoscience reflects a tendency towards symbolisation: incorporating the biosphere (living nature) into the “symbolic order’ (Lacan) or ‘noosphere’ (Teilhard). On various occasions, Lacan refers to Teilhard’s concept of the hominization of the planet and their dialogue culminates in a ‘final conversation’ between Teilhard and Lacan in 1954, during a reception organised by the journal Psyché. I will conclude that the Teilhard-Lacan dialogue is highly relevant for current debates concerning the Anthropocene, as a moment of global awakening and global crisis. Processes of hominization allowed humans to become literate beings, littering the planet as well: humans as literate litterers. Whereas Teilhard argues that technoscience and self-directed evolution are about to culminate in what he refers to as point Omega, Lacan rather stresses the hazards involved in this optimistic desire towards all-encompassing synthesis, unification and fulfilment.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43645749","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Iris Murdoch between buddhism and christianity: moral change, conceptual loss/recovery, unselfing 在佛教和基督教之间:道德的改变,观念的丧失/恢复,无私
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-05-27 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2129744
O. Beran, Kai Marchal
ABSTRACT The article discusses Iris Murdoch’s philosophical relationship to Buddhism. First, we argue that Murdoch was not, and did not identify herself as, a Buddhist. Then we suggest caution regarding Murdoch’s interpretations of Buddhism. On the one hand, she applies the limited viewpoint of her era. On the other hand, her approach is motivated by insights tracing affinities between Buddhism and Husserl’s and Sartre’s analyses of consciousness, as well as Platonic ideas of unselfing and self-purification. Murdoch’s reflections on Buddhism serve primarily a complex argument about the role of religion in our moral lives, as these reflect the rapidly changing Western cultural environment. She envisages the possibility for Christianity to learn from Buddhism and move closer towards demythologisation and a radical, loving commitment to the others here and now. While Murdoch’s observations may not be accurate as a ‘diagnosis of our times’, they serve as a valuable opening for reflecting on our lives in the suggested terms. They are also inspiring in their optimism that there is the possibility to learn from others (other cultures, other religions) for the better. The ‘muddled’ nature of our reality does not thwart this possibility of learning; it only makes its particular steps unpredictable.
摘要本文论述了默多克与佛教的哲学关系。首先,我们认为默多克不是,也没有表明自己是佛教徒。然后,我们建议对默多克对佛教的解读保持谨慎。一方面,她运用了她那个时代的有限观点。另一方面,她的方法是基于对佛教与胡塞尔和萨特对意识的分析之间的密切关系的见解,以及柏拉图关于无私和自我净化的思想。默多克对佛教的思考主要是关于宗教在我们道德生活中的作用的复杂争论,因为这些思考反映了快速变化的西方文化环境。她设想了基督教向佛教学习的可能性,并朝着去神话化和对此时此地其他人的激进、爱的承诺迈进。虽然默多克的观察作为“对我们时代的诊断”可能并不准确,但它们为用建议的术语反思我们的生活提供了一个宝贵的机会。他们乐观地认为,有可能向其他人(其他文化、其他宗教)学习,让自己变得更好。我们现实的“混乱”本质并没有阻碍这种学习的可能性;它只会使其特定的步骤变得不可预测。
{"title":"Iris Murdoch between buddhism and christianity: moral change, conceptual loss/recovery, unselfing","authors":"O. Beran, Kai Marchal","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2129744","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2129744","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT The article discusses Iris Murdoch’s philosophical relationship to Buddhism. First, we argue that Murdoch was not, and did not identify herself as, a Buddhist. Then we suggest caution regarding Murdoch’s interpretations of Buddhism. On the one hand, she applies the limited viewpoint of her era. On the other hand, her approach is motivated by insights tracing affinities between Buddhism and Husserl’s and Sartre’s analyses of consciousness, as well as Platonic ideas of unselfing and self-purification. Murdoch’s reflections on Buddhism serve primarily a complex argument about the role of religion in our moral lives, as these reflect the rapidly changing Western cultural environment. She envisages the possibility for Christianity to learn from Buddhism and move closer towards demythologisation and a radical, loving commitment to the others here and now. While Murdoch’s observations may not be accurate as a ‘diagnosis of our times’, they serve as a valuable opening for reflecting on our lives in the suggested terms. They are also inspiring in their optimism that there is the possibility to learn from others (other cultures, other religions) for the better. The ‘muddled’ nature of our reality does not thwart this possibility of learning; it only makes its particular steps unpredictable.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44936415","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Communal recognition and human flourishing: a Kierkegaardian account 社区认同与人类繁荣:克尔凯郭尔的叙述
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-04-29 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2022.2070862
Dylan S. Bailey
ABSTRACT Recent debates over the role of recognition by the community for one’s development and flourishing generally discuss community in a univocal sense: the way that recognition functions in particular communities is not fundamentally different from the way it functions in the larger community. They also tend to logically prioritize a fundamental human identity over particular religious, ethnic, or societal identities, which are understood to be secondary to, and derivative of, this basic identity. In his depiction of how communal recognition contributes to individual selfhood, Søren Kierkegaard challenges these accounts by (1) differentiating between how communal recognition occurs in society in general and in one particular community, the Christian church and (2) questioning the idea that the self created in the former is more fundamental than that created in the latter. For Kierkegaard, one’s identities as both a Christian and a fully-developed self depend essentially on recognition by the Other: initially and fundamentally on recognition by God alone, and secondarily and derivatively on recognition by the human Other.
摘要最近关于社区认可对一个人的发展和繁荣的作用的辩论通常从单一的意义上讨论社区:认可在特定社区中的作用与在更大社区中的功能没有根本区别。他们还倾向于从逻辑上优先考虑基本的人类身份,而不是特定的宗教、种族或社会身份,这些身份被理解为是这种基本身份的次要和衍生物。瑟伦·克尔凯郭尔(Søren Kierkegaard)在描述社区认可如何促进个人自我时,对这些说法提出了质疑,他(1)区分了社区认可在整个社会和一个特定的社区,即基督教会中是如何发生的,(2)质疑前者创造的自我比后者创造的自我更根本的观点。对克尔凯郭尔来说,一个人作为基督徒和完全发展的自我的身份本质上取决于他人的认可:最初和根本上取决于上帝的认可,其次和衍生地取决于人类他人的认可。
{"title":"Communal recognition and human flourishing: a Kierkegaardian account","authors":"Dylan S. Bailey","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2022.2070862","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2022.2070862","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Recent debates over the role of recognition by the community for one’s development and flourishing generally discuss community in a univocal sense: the way that recognition functions in particular communities is not fundamentally different from the way it functions in the larger community. They also tend to logically prioritize a fundamental human identity over particular religious, ethnic, or societal identities, which are understood to be secondary to, and derivative of, this basic identity. In his depiction of how communal recognition contributes to individual selfhood, Søren Kierkegaard challenges these accounts by (1) differentiating between how communal recognition occurs in society in general and in one particular community, the Christian church and (2) questioning the idea that the self created in the former is more fundamental than that created in the latter. For Kierkegaard, one’s identities as both a Christian and a fully-developed self depend essentially on recognition by the Other: initially and fundamentally on recognition by God alone, and secondarily and derivatively on recognition by the human Other.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-04-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48129556","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Why the divine purpose theory fails: a conversation with Thaddeus Metz 神圣目的论为什么失败——与撒迪厄斯·梅斯的对话
IF 0.2 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-10-20 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2021.2002713
A. D. Attoe
ABSTRACT Thaddeus Metz’s new book ‘God, Soul and the Meaning of Life’ presents a brief analysis of supernaturalist views about the meaning of life – my specific concern being the Divine purpose theory. While the view locates meaning in the fulfilment of some divine mandate, I show that this theory is, at best, unattractive. In this essay, I challenge the view that a belief in God is not necessary for the Divine purpose theory to be viable. I show that if we were to agree that a belief in God is inconceivable, then a theory built on such a belief is, at best, wishful thinking. Arguing from a subjectivist perspective, I make clear the fact that any recourse to a godly mandate as what makes life meaningful inadvertently assumes an extrinsic and instrumental character, which makes such a pursuit an unattractive form of meaningfulness. Finally, I show that the God purpose theory is much too narrow as it fails to capture other paths to meaningfulness that do not involve a recourse to God, and also that any assigned purpose is unnecessary (and, therefore, unattractive), if God is all-knowing, all-powerful, etc.
摘要:撒迪厄斯·梅斯的新书《上帝、灵魂与生命的意义》简要分析了超自然主义者对生命意义的看法——我特别关注的是神圣目的论。虽然这种观点将意义定位于某种神圣使命的实现,但我表明,这种理论充其量是没有吸引力的。在这篇文章中,我挑战了这样一种观点,即对上帝的信仰并不是神圣目的理论可行的必要条件。我表明,如果我们同意对上帝的信仰是不可想象的,那么建立在这种信仰之上的理论充其量只是一厢情愿。从主观主义的角度出发,我清楚地表明了一个事实,即任何求助于神圣的命令来让生活变得有意义的行为,都会在无意中呈现出一种外在的工具性,这使得这种追求成为一种没有吸引力的有意义的形式。最后,我表明,上帝目的论过于狭隘,因为它没有捕捉到其他不涉及求助于上帝的有意义的道路,而且如果上帝无所不知、无所不能,那么任何指定的目的都是不必要的(因此也没有吸引力)。
{"title":"Why the divine purpose theory fails: a conversation with Thaddeus Metz","authors":"A. D. Attoe","doi":"10.1080/21692327.2021.2002713","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2021.2002713","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Thaddeus Metz’s new book ‘God, Soul and the Meaning of Life’ presents a brief analysis of supernaturalist views about the meaning of life – my specific concern being the Divine purpose theory. While the view locates meaning in the fulfilment of some divine mandate, I show that this theory is, at best, unattractive. In this essay, I challenge the view that a belief in God is not necessary for the Divine purpose theory to be viable. I show that if we were to agree that a belief in God is inconceivable, then a theory built on such a belief is, at best, wishful thinking. Arguing from a subjectivist perspective, I make clear the fact that any recourse to a godly mandate as what makes life meaningful inadvertently assumes an extrinsic and instrumental character, which makes such a pursuit an unattractive form of meaningfulness. Finally, I show that the God purpose theory is much too narrow as it fails to capture other paths to meaningfulness that do not involve a recourse to God, and also that any assigned purpose is unnecessary (and, therefore, unattractive), if God is all-knowing, all-powerful, etc.","PeriodicalId":42052,"journal":{"name":"International Journal of Philosophy and Theology","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2021-10-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48704830","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
International Journal of Philosophy and Theology
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1