首页 > 最新文献

Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki最新文献

英文 中文
Gift-giving as an Epistemic Virtue 送礼作为一种认知美德
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158467
O. Popova
The article presents a study of gift-giving practices in the context of the development of modern biomedicine and shows their relationship to the realization of epistemic virtues. In biomedicine, the gain and production of knowledge (the gift of knowledge) is often grounded in bodily gift (sacrifice) and donor practices. The latter are associated with a number of mishaps in the history of biomedicine, reflecting the violation of moral norms in the process of obtaining scientific data and demonstrating the need for a clear differentiation of intellectual and moral virtues. An important factor in the formation of the epistemic norms of modern biomedicine has been the transformation of the values of scientific knowledge from practices of coercion to giving. As a result, the involuntary sacrifice of biomaterials to science was replaced by voluntary practices of somatic giving and informational exchange that determine the process of mutual recognition in science. It is shown that gift-giving in science is closely associated with intellectual virtues, with intellectual generosity characterizing the idea of openness in science and scientists’ intention for production and constant growth of knowledge, and can also be related to the idea of altruistic service to science, involving the exchange of received scientific data and access to free information in the network space. A number of examples of the modern digital gift ethos and the implementation of the principles of openness of knowledge and knowledge exchange in the context of the creation of biomedical expert digital platforms, the formation of social scientific networks – platforms with open access to scientific information, the development of the phenomenon of “garage” science and other “zones of exchange” experience are considered.
本文对现代生物医学发展背景下的送礼行为进行了研究,并阐述了送礼行为与认知美德实现的关系。在生物医学中,知识的获得和生产(知识的赠予)往往以身体的赠予(牺牲)和捐赠实践为基础。后者与生物医学史上的一些灾难有关,反映了在获取科学数据的过程中违反道德规范,并表明需要明确区分智力和道德美德。现代生物医学认知规范形成的一个重要因素是科学知识价值从强制实践向给予实践的转变。因此,为科学而非自愿地牺牲生物材料被自愿的身体捐赠和信息交换所取代,这决定了科学中相互认可的过程。研究表明,科学送礼与智力美德密切相关,智力慷慨体现了科学开放理念和科学家生产和不断增长知识的意愿,也与科学的利他服务理念有关,涉及交换收到的科学数据和在网络空间中获取免费信息。在创建生物医学专家数字平台,形成社会科学网络-开放获取科学信息的平台,发展“车库”科学现象和其他“交流区域”经验的背景下,考虑了一些现代数字礼物精神和知识开放原则的实施。
{"title":"Gift-giving as an Epistemic Virtue","authors":"O. Popova","doi":"10.5840/eps202158467","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158467","url":null,"abstract":"The article presents a study of gift-giving practices in the context of the development of modern biomedicine and shows their relationship to the realization of epistemic virtues. In biomedicine, the gain and production of knowledge (the gift of knowledge) is often grounded in bodily gift (sacrifice) and donor practices. The latter are associated with a number of mishaps in the history of biomedicine, reflecting the violation of moral norms in the process of obtaining scientific data and demonstrating the need for a clear differentiation of intellectual and moral virtues. An important factor in the formation of the epistemic norms of modern biomedicine has been the transformation of the values of scientific knowledge from practices of coercion to giving. As a result, the involuntary sacrifice of biomaterials to science was replaced by voluntary practices of somatic giving and informational exchange that determine the process of mutual recognition in science. It is shown that gift-giving in science is closely associated with intellectual virtues, with intellectual generosity characterizing the idea of openness in science and scientists’ intention for production and constant growth of knowledge, and can also be related to the idea of altruistic service to science, involving the exchange of received scientific data and access to free information in the network space. A number of examples of the modern digital gift ethos and the implementation of the principles of openness of knowledge and knowledge exchange in the context of the creation of biomedical expert digital platforms, the formation of social scientific networks – platforms with open access to scientific information, the development of the phenomenon of “garage” science and other “zones of exchange” experience are considered.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71005873","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Albert Einstein’s Epistemic Virtues and Vices 阿尔伯特·爱因斯坦的认识的美德与罪恶
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158468
V. Vizgin
The article is based on the concepts of epistemic virtues and epistemic vices and explores A. Einstein’s contribution to the creation of fundamental physical theories, namely the special theory of relativity and general theory of relativity, as well as to the development of a unified field theory on the basis of the geometric field program, which never led to success. Among the main epistemic virtues that led Einstein to success in the construction of the special theory of relativity are the following: a unique physical intuition based on the method of thought experiment and the need for an experimental justification of space-time concepts; striving for simplicity and elegance of theory; scientific courage, rebelliousness, signifying the readiness to engage in confrontation with scientific conventional dogmas and authorities. In the creation of general theory of relativity, another intellectual virtue was added to these virtues: the belief in the heuristic power of the mathematical aspect of physics. At the same time, he had to overcome his initial underestimation of the H. Minkowski’s four-dimensional concept of space and time, which has manifested in a distinctive flexibility of thinking typical for Einstein in his early years. The creative role of Einstein’s mistakes on the way to general relativity was emphasized. These mistakes were mostly related to the difficulties of harmonizing the mathematical and physical aspects of theory, less so to epistemic vices. The ambivalence of the concept of epistemic virtues, which can be transformed into epistemic vices, is noted. This transformation happened in the second half of Einstein’s life, when he for more than thirty years unsuccessfully tried to build a unified geometric field theory and to find an alternative to quantum mechanics with their probabilistic and Copenhagen interpretation In this case, we can talk about the following epistemic vices: the revaluation of mathematical aspect and underestimation of experimentally – empirical aspect of the theory; adopting the concepts general relativity is based on (continualism, classical causality, geometric nature of fundamental interactions) as fundamental; unprecedented persistence in defending the GFP (geometrical field program), despite its failures, and a certain loss of the flexibility of thinking. A cosmological history that is associated both with the application of GTR (general theory of relativity) to the structure of the Universe, and with the missed possibility of discovering the theory of the expanding Universe is intermediate in relation to Einstein’s epistemic virtues and vices. This opportunity was realized by A.A. Friedmann, who defeated Einstein in the dispute about if the Universe was stationary or nonstationary. In this dispute some of Einstein’s vices were revealed, which Friedman did not have. The connection between epistemic virtues and the methodological principles of physics and also with the “fallibilist” concept of scientific
本文从认识论的美德和认识论的罪恶两个概念出发,探讨了爱因斯坦对创立基本物理理论即狭义相对论和广义相对论的贡献,以及在几何场程序的基础上建立统一场论的贡献,但这些贡献从未取得成功。导致爱因斯坦成功建立狭义相对论的主要认识美德包括:基于思维实验方法的独特的物理直觉和对时空概念的实验证明的需要;力求理论简练典雅;科学的勇气,叛逆,意味着准备与科学的传统教条和权威对抗。在创立广义相对论的过程中,在这些美德之上又增加了另一种智力上的美德:相信物理学的数学方面具有启发式的力量。同时,他必须克服最初对闵可夫斯基的四维空间和时间概念的低估,这表现在早年爱因斯坦特有的思维灵活性上。他强调了爱因斯坦的错误在通向广义相对论的道路上所起的创造性作用。这些错误大多与协调理论的数学和物理方面的困难有关,而不是与认识上的错误有关。注意到认识美德概念的矛盾心理,它可以转化为认识的恶习。这种转变发生在爱因斯坦的后半生,当时他花了三十多年的时间试图建立一个统一的几何场论,并试图用量子力学的概率和哥本哈根解释找到一个替代方案,但都没有成功。在这种情况下,我们可以谈谈以下认识上的缺点:对理论的数学方面的重新评价和对实验经验方面的低估;采用广义相对论的概念是基于(连续性,经典因果关系,基本相互作用的几何性质)作为基本;前所未有地坚持捍卫GFP(几何场程序),尽管它失败了,并在一定程度上失去了思维的灵活性。一个宇宙学的历史,既与GTR(广义相对论)对宇宙结构的应用有关,又与发现宇宙膨胀理论的可能性有关,这与爱因斯坦的认识的优点和缺点有关。这个机会被A.A.弗里德曼发现了,他在关于宇宙是静止还是非静止的争论中击败了爱因斯坦。在这场争论中,爱因斯坦的一些恶习暴露了出来,而弗里德曼却没有。认识论的优点与物理学的方法论原则之间的联系,以及与科学知识发展的“谬误论”概念之间的联系已经被注意到。
{"title":"Albert Einstein’s Epistemic Virtues and Vices","authors":"V. Vizgin","doi":"10.5840/eps202158468","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158468","url":null,"abstract":"The article is based on the concepts of epistemic virtues and epistemic vices and explores A. Einstein’s contribution to the creation of fundamental physical theories, namely the special theory of relativity and general theory of relativity, as well as to the development of a unified field theory on the basis of the geometric field program, which never led to success. Among the main epistemic virtues that led Einstein to success in the construction of the special theory of relativity are the following: a unique physical intuition based on the method of thought experiment and the need for an experimental justification of space-time concepts; striving for simplicity and elegance of theory; scientific courage, rebelliousness, signifying the readiness to engage in confrontation with scientific conventional dogmas and authorities. In the creation of general theory of relativity, another intellectual virtue was added to these virtues: the belief in the heuristic power of the mathematical aspect of physics. At the same time, he had to overcome his initial underestimation of the H. Minkowski’s four-dimensional concept of space and time, which has manifested in a distinctive flexibility of thinking typical for Einstein in his early years. The creative role of Einstein’s mistakes on the way to general relativity was emphasized. These mistakes were mostly related to the difficulties of harmonizing the mathematical and physical aspects of theory, less so to epistemic vices. The ambivalence of the concept of epistemic virtues, which can be transformed into epistemic vices, is noted. This transformation happened in the second half of Einstein’s life, when he for more than thirty years unsuccessfully tried to build a unified geometric field theory and to find an alternative to quantum mechanics with their probabilistic and Copenhagen interpretation In this case, we can talk about the following epistemic vices: the revaluation of mathematical aspect and underestimation of experimentally – empirical aspect of the theory; adopting the concepts general relativity is based on (continualism, classical causality, geometric nature of fundamental interactions) as fundamental; unprecedented persistence in defending the GFP (geometrical field program), despite its failures, and a certain loss of the flexibility of thinking. A cosmological history that is associated both with the application of GTR (general theory of relativity) to the structure of the Universe, and with the missed possibility of discovering the theory of the expanding Universe is intermediate in relation to Einstein’s epistemic virtues and vices. This opportunity was realized by A.A. Friedmann, who defeated Einstein in the dispute about if the Universe was stationary or nonstationary. In this dispute some of Einstein’s vices were revealed, which Friedman did not have. The connection between epistemic virtues and the methodological principles of physics and also with the “fallibilist” concept of scientific","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71005935","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
“Vicious Minds” “恶性”
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158465
Asya A. Filatova
Virtue Epistemology (VE) offers a specific approach to the problem of knowledge. The condition for the possibility of knowledge is the presence of certain intellectual abilities or traits in the subject – epistemic virtues. The task of VE is to compile a list of epis - temic virtues, the development and cultivation of which should lead individuals to epistemic success with a high degree of probability. The vice epistemology arises as a branch of VE, which focuses not on virtues, but on vices that hinder achievement and deserve censure. Vices can be attributed to both individuals and communities. As a rule, those who tend to question the scientific consensus are considered to be vicious knowing communities: conspiracy theorists, denialists, religious fundamentalists, etc. The article argues that the logic of imputing blame for bad epistemic traits used in vice epistemology tends to turn from an epistemological tool into an ideological and political one. Since in the logic of the vice epistemology, "vicious minds" pose a threat not only to themselves, but also to the health of modern democratic societies, the eradication of vices is a primary political task. Using the theoretical framework of S. Fuller's social epistemology, the author shows how the rhetoric of vice epistemology is used today in the fight against anti-intellectualism and epistemic populism.
美德认识论(VE)提供了一种解决知识问题的具体方法。知识可能性的条件是在主体的认知美德中存在某种智力能力或特征。社会经济学的任务是编制一份典型美德的清单,这些美德的发展和培养应该会使个人以很高的概率获得认知上的成功。恶行认识论是VE的一个分支,它关注的不是美德,而是阻碍成就和应该受到谴责的恶行。恶习可以归咎于个人和社会。一般来说,那些倾向于质疑科学共识的人被认为是邪恶的知识团体:阴谋论者、否认论者、宗教原教旨主义者等。文章认为,“恶认识论”中使用的“恶认识论”逻辑有从认识论工具转向意识形态和政治工具的趋势。由于在邪恶认识论的逻辑中,“邪恶思想”不仅对他们自己构成威胁,而且对现代民主社会的健康构成威胁,因此根除邪恶是一项主要的政治任务。在富勒社会认识论的理论框架下,作者展示了副认识论的修辞学在当今与反智主义和认识论民粹主义的斗争中是如何被使用的。
{"title":"“Vicious Minds”","authors":"Asya A. Filatova","doi":"10.5840/eps202158465","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158465","url":null,"abstract":"Virtue Epistemology (VE) offers a specific approach to the problem of knowledge. The condition for the possibility of knowledge is the presence of certain intellectual abilities or traits in the subject – epistemic virtues. The task of VE is to compile a list of epis - temic virtues, the development and cultivation of which should lead individuals to epistemic success with a high degree of probability. The vice epistemology arises as a branch of VE, which focuses not on virtues, but on vices that hinder achievement and deserve censure. Vices can be attributed to both individuals and communities. As a rule, those who tend to question the scientific consensus are considered to be vicious knowing communities: conspiracy theorists, denialists, religious fundamentalists, etc. The article argues that the logic of imputing blame for bad epistemic traits used in vice epistemology tends to turn from an epistemological tool into an ideological and political one. Since in the logic of the vice epistemology, \"vicious minds\" pose a threat not only to themselves, but also to the health of modern democratic societies, the eradication of vices is a primary political task. Using the theoretical framework of S. Fuller's social epistemology, the author shows how the rhetoric of vice epistemology is used today in the fight against anti-intellectualism and epistemic populism.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71006071","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Wittgenstein in the Camp of Logical Positivists. Reply to Critics 逻辑实证主义阵营中的维特根斯坦。回应批评
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158110
K. Rodin
{"title":"Wittgenstein in the Camp of Logical Positivists. Reply to Critics","authors":"K. Rodin","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158110","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158110","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003609","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Cultural-Historical Epistemology and Perspectives of the Philosophy of Science 文化历史认识论与科学哲学的视角
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158223
B. Pruzhinin, T. Shchedrina
The purpose of the article is to demonstrate the methodological effectiveness of one of the directions in developing the philosophy of science – cultural and historical epistemology. Cultural-historical epistemology does not pretend at all to be any radical epistemological originality but offers a general view of science as a part of intellectual culture, where both individual historical cases and broad sociological generalizations find their methodologically significant place. The authors believe that it is the development of methodological norms capable of determining the fundamental parameters and strategies of scientific research that is now the central task of the philosophy of science. One of the characteristic forms of organization of modern advanced science is interdisciplinary research programs that involve the joint activities of large research teams. This fact raises a critical question about the mutual understanding of specialists from different disciplines and, accordingly, about the development of methodological norms that can determine the generally accepted parameters of the reproducibility of cognition results. Thus, in the center of attention of the philosophy of science, epistemological plots are put forward, one way or another connected with a specific understanding of the phenomenon of communication in science. Moreover, according to the authors, in these philosophical and methodological searches, it is essential to overcome, on the one hand, the inclination to conceptual design that leads away from the real methodological needs of science and, on the other hand, straightforward sociologization and equally direct historicization of science. These approaches are fraught with relativization of the very idea of scientific knowledge as a rational phenomenon of culture. The authors of the article believe that in modern conceptual trends in the philosophy of science, it is necessary to accentuate quite traditional epistemological principles, which in their updated edition make it possible to activate, or, as it were, to revive the methodological functions of the philosophy of science that are partially lost today. Justifying this approach, the authors turn to the epistemological trend, which for two decades has been developed based on the traditions of Russian philosophy of the first half of the 20th century.
本文的目的在于论证科学哲学发展方向之一——文化与历史认识论的方法论有效性。文化-历史认识论根本不假装是任何激进的认识论独创性,而是提供了一种将科学作为知识文化一部分的一般观点,在这种观点中,个别的历史案例和广泛的社会学概括在方法论上都有重要的地位。作者认为,能够确定科学研究的基本参数和策略的方法论规范的发展是科学哲学现在的中心任务。现代先进科学的典型组织形式之一是涉及大型研究团队联合活动的跨学科研究项目。这一事实提出了一个关键问题,即来自不同学科的专家之间的相互理解,以及相应的,关于方法规范的发展,这些规范可以确定认知结果可重复性的普遍接受的参数。因此,在科学哲学的关注中心,认识论的情节被提出,以这样或那样的方式与对科学交流现象的具体理解联系在一起。此外,根据作者的说法,在这些哲学和方法论的研究中,必须一方面克服偏离科学真正的方法论需求的概念设计倾向,另一方面克服直接的社会学和同样直接的科学历史化。这些方法充满了科学知识作为一种理性文化现象的相对化。这篇文章的作者认为,在科学哲学的现代概念趋势中,有必要强调相当传统的认识论原则,这些原则在他们的更新版本中有可能激活,或者,就像它一样,恢复科学哲学的方法论功能,这些功能在今天部分失去了。为了证明这一方法的合理性,作者转向认识论趋势,这一趋势在20世纪上半叶的俄罗斯哲学传统的基础上发展了20年。
{"title":"Cultural-Historical Epistemology and Perspectives of the Philosophy of Science","authors":"B. Pruzhinin, T. Shchedrina","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158223","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158223","url":null,"abstract":"The purpose of the article is to demonstrate the methodological effectiveness of one of the directions in developing the philosophy of science – cultural and historical epistemology. Cultural-historical epistemology does not pretend at all to be any radical epistemological originality but offers a general view of science as a part of intellectual culture, where both individual historical cases and broad sociological generalizations find their methodologically significant place. The authors believe that it is the development of methodological norms capable of determining the fundamental parameters and strategies of scientific research that is now the central task of the philosophy of science. One of the characteristic forms of organization of modern advanced science is interdisciplinary research programs that involve the joint activities of large research teams. This fact raises a critical question about the mutual understanding of specialists from different disciplines and, accordingly, about the development of methodological norms that can determine the generally accepted parameters of the reproducibility of cognition results. Thus, in the center of attention of the philosophy of science, epistemological plots are put forward, one way or another connected with a specific understanding of the phenomenon of communication in science. Moreover, according to the authors, in these philosophical and methodological searches, it is essential to overcome, on the one hand, the inclination to conceptual design that leads away from the real methodological needs of science and, on the other hand, straightforward sociologization and equally direct historicization of science. These approaches are fraught with relativization of the very idea of scientific knowledge as a rational phenomenon of culture. The authors of the article believe that in modern conceptual trends in the philosophy of science, it is necessary to accentuate quite traditional epistemological principles, which in their updated edition make it possible to activate, or, as it were, to revive the methodological functions of the philosophy of science that are partially lost today. Justifying this approach, the authors turn to the epistemological trend, which for two decades has been developed based on the traditions of Russian philosophy of the first half of the 20th century.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003954","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Lyudmila A. Markova (12.12.1932–26.12.2020) Lyudmila A.Markova(1932年12月12日至2020年12月26日)
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158121
{"title":"Lyudmila A. Markova (12.12.1932–26.12.2020)","authors":"","doi":"10.5840/eps202158121","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158121","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003993","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Owner of the Right over Nature, or Expert Mediators in the Modern Era and at Present 近现代与现当代的自然权利所有者或专家调解人
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158349
L. Shipovalova
F. Bacon in his work New Organon proposes a project of a new science, which ensures the desire of human race “to recover its right over nature”. The article examines the work on the universal owner of “the right over nature” in two historical contexts. The first context determines the emergence of modern science. Here Bacon plays the role of an expert mediator who introduces the new scientific method in its broader social meaning. His work on the universal owner of “the right over nature” combines and intersects the cognitive and political aspects of scientific endeavor. The second context covers the present situation after the Scientific-Technical Revolution, when the use of the “right over nature” becomes actual, and not only possible. The contradictions revealed in the first context in the activities of the expert mediator serve as the basis for analyzing the present situation of interaction between science and society. The author describes the expert mediator, corresponding to the modern context of uncertainty and conflict of values, through the concept of “honest broker of policy alternatives” by R. Pielke, as well as through the palette of expert knowledge types presented by the STS researchers. She shows why the presented differentiation of expert knowledge types is not enough to organize the work of an expert mediator as an “honest broker”. In conclusion, she puts forward the hypothesis about distributed expertise, which can represent contemporary work on the owner of the “right over nature” and describes some aspects of this work. The author associates the significance of the hypothesis of distributed expertise with the preservation of the openness of the project of Bacon's new science.
F.培根在他的著作《新奥加纳》中提出了一种新科学的计划,它保证了人类“恢复对自然的权利”的愿望。本文在两个历史背景下考察了“自然权利”的普遍所有者问题。第一种背景决定了现代科学的产生。在这里,培根扮演了一个专家调解人的角色,他在更广泛的社会意义上介绍了新的科学方法。他关于“对自然的权利”的普遍所有者的工作结合并交叉了科学努力的认知和政治方面。第二个背景涵盖了科学技术革命之后的现状,当时使用“对自然的权利”成为现实,而不仅仅是可能。专家调解员活动中在第一种语境中所揭示的矛盾,是分析科学与社会互动现状的基础。作者通过皮尔克(R. Pielke)的“诚实的政策选择经纪人”概念,以及STS研究人员提出的专家知识类型调色板,描述了与不确定性和价值观冲突的现代背景相对应的专家调解人。她展示了为什么提出的专家知识类型的区分不足以将专家调解人作为“诚实的经纪人”组织工作。最后,她提出了分布式专业知识的假设,这一假设可以代表当代关于“自然权利”所有者的工作,并描述了该工作的某些方面。作者将分布式专家假设的意义与保存培根新科学项目的开放性联系起来。
{"title":"The Owner of the Right over Nature, or Expert Mediators in the Modern Era and at Present","authors":"L. Shipovalova","doi":"10.5840/eps202158349","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158349","url":null,"abstract":"F. Bacon in his work New Organon proposes a project of a new science, which ensures the desire of human race “to recover its right over nature”. The article examines the work on the universal owner of “the right over nature” in two historical contexts. The first context determines the emergence of modern science. Here Bacon plays the role of an expert mediator who introduces the new scientific method in its broader social meaning. His work on the universal owner of “the right over nature” combines and intersects the cognitive and political aspects of scientific endeavor. The second context covers the present situation after the Scientific-Technical Revolution, when the use of the “right over nature” becomes actual, and not only possible. The contradictions revealed in the first context in the activities of the expert mediator serve as the basis for analyzing the present situation of interaction between science and society. The author describes the expert mediator, corresponding to the modern context of uncertainty and conflict of values, through the concept of “honest broker of policy alternatives” by R. Pielke, as well as through the palette of expert knowledge types presented by the STS researchers. She shows why the presented differentiation of expert knowledge types is not enough to organize the work of an expert mediator as an “honest broker”. In conclusion, she puts forward the hypothesis about distributed expertise, which can represent contemporary work on the owner of the “right over nature” and describes some aspects of this work. The author associates the significance of the hypothesis of distributed expertise with the preservation of the openness of the project of Bacon's new science.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71004199","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Bacon’s Inductive Method and Material Form 培根的归纳法与物质形式
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158343
O. Belkind
This paper contends that Bacon’s inductive method depends crucially on his general account of matter. I argue that Bacon develops a dynamic form of corpuscularianism, according to which aggregates of corpuscles undergo patterns of change that derive from active inclinations and appetites. The paper claims that Bacon’s corpuscularianism provides him with a theory of material form that enables him to theorize bodily change and possible material transformations. The point of natural histories and experiments is then to find the processes of corpuscular change that correlate with making present or making absent simple natures.
本文认为,培根的归纳法主要依赖于他对物质的一般描述。我认为培根发展了一种动态形式的微粒论,根据这种理论,微粒的聚集经历了源于活跃的倾向和欲望的变化模式。论文声称,培根的微粒论为他提供了一种物质形式理论,使他能够将身体变化和可能的物质转化理论化。因此,自然史和实验的重点是发现与产生存在或不存在的简单性质相关的微粒变化过程。
{"title":"Bacon’s Inductive Method and Material Form","authors":"O. Belkind","doi":"10.5840/eps202158343","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158343","url":null,"abstract":"This paper contends that Bacon’s inductive method depends crucially on his general account of matter. I argue that Bacon develops a dynamic form of corpuscularianism, according to which aggregates of corpuscles undergo patterns of change that derive from active inclinations and appetites. The paper claims that Bacon’s corpuscularianism provides him with a theory of material form that enables him to theorize bodily change and possible material transformations. The point of natural histories and experiments is then to find the processes of corpuscular change that correlate with making present or making absent simple natures.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71004573","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
On Veritism. Pritchard’s Defense Veritism。普里查德的辩护
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158457
E. Sosa
This time Pritchard is on a rescue mission. Veritism is besieged and he rises to defend it. I do agree with much in his Veritism, but I demur when he adds: “So, the goodness of all epistemic goods is understood instrumentally with regard to whether they promote truth”. If Big Brother brainwashes us to believe the full contents of The Encyclopedia Britannica, then even if we suppose those contents to be true without exception, that would not make what they do an unalloyed good thing, not even epistemically. But it does seem to promote truth. What might then diminish Big Brother’s action so much, so as to make it so deplorable epistemically after all, despite how powerfully it does instrumentally promote truth. At a minimum we need to say more about the relations between epistemic goods and truth, so as to better understand how it is that the epistemic good is made so good by what specific relation to the truth. I lay out a way to understand Veritism so that it can say more about the relations between epistemic goods and truth, thus enhancing our understanding of epistemic normativity. And in a second part I lay out a solution to Linda Zagzebski’s Swamping problem for reliabilism. I argue that it is a problem for process reliabilism, but not for a virtue epistemology that accepts a kind of reliabilism, but in an agential telic framework, and not in a process framework. So, I lay out one way to be a “veritist”, by defending explicitly its Axiological side, and by implication its Conceptual side as well. I have raised questions for Pritchard’s own defense and have offered in each case an alternative defense that I believe fits the words of his formulations, and is in their spirit as well.
这次普里查德执行的是救援任务。真理主义被围攻,他奋起捍卫。我确实同意他的真理论,但我不同意他的补充:“所以,所有认知善的善都是通过工具来理解的,看它们是否促进了真理。”如果老大哥给我们洗脑,让我们相信《大英百科全书》的全部内容,那么即使我们假设这些内容无一例外都是真实的,这也不能使他们所做的事情成为纯粹的好事,甚至在认识论上也不行。但它似乎确实促进了真相。那么,究竟是什么削弱了老大哥的行动,使其在认识论上变得如此可悲,尽管它在工具上宣扬真理是多么有力。至少我们需要更多地讨论认识善与真理之间的关系,以便更好地理解认识善是如何通过与真理的特定关系而变得如此美好的。我提出了一种理解真理论的方法,这样它就能更多地说明认知善与真理之间的关系,从而增强我们对认知规范性的理解。在第二部分中,我给出了Linda Zagzebski的可靠性淹没问题的解决方案。我认为这是过程可靠性论的问题,但不是美德认识论的问题它接受一种可靠性论,但在一个能动的目的性框架中,而不是在一个过程框架中。因此,我提出了一种成为“真实论者”的方法,即明确捍卫其价值论的一面,并暗示其概念的一面。我为普里查德自己的辩护提出了一些问题,并在每种情况下都提出了另一种辩护,我认为这种辩护符合他的表述,也符合他们的精神。
{"title":"On Veritism. Pritchard’s Defense","authors":"E. Sosa","doi":"10.5840/eps202158457","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158457","url":null,"abstract":"This time Pritchard is on a rescue mission. Veritism is besieged and he rises to defend it. I do agree with much in his Veritism, but I demur when he adds: “So, the goodness of all epistemic goods is understood instrumentally with regard to whether they promote truth”. If Big Brother brainwashes us to believe the full contents of The Encyclopedia Britannica, then even if we suppose those contents to be true without exception, that would not make what they do an unalloyed good thing, not even epistemically. But it does seem to promote truth. What might then diminish Big Brother’s action so much, so as to make it so deplorable epistemically after all, despite how powerfully it does instrumentally promote truth. At a minimum we need to say more about the relations between epistemic goods and truth, so as to better understand how it is that the epistemic good is made so good by what specific relation to the truth. I lay out a way to understand Veritism so that it can say more about the relations between epistemic goods and truth, thus enhancing our understanding of epistemic normativity. And in a second part I lay out a solution to Linda Zagzebski’s Swamping problem for reliabilism. I argue that it is a problem for process reliabilism, but not for a virtue epistemology that accepts a kind of reliabilism, but in an agential telic framework, and not in a process framework. So, I lay out one way to be a “veritist”, by defending explicitly its Axiological side, and by implication its Conceptual side as well. I have raised questions for Pritchard’s own defense and have offered in each case an alternative defense that I believe fits the words of his formulations, and is in their spirit as well.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71005211","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Epistemic Virtue of Wisdom and Evidentialism 智慧的认知美德与证据主义
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158469
K. Karpov
My primary concern in this article is the connection between virtue epistemology and evidentialism. This possible connection is analyzed upon, firstly, the example of the intellectual virtue of wisdom, and, secondly, the historical case – Thomas Aquinas’ approach to virtue of wisdom as an intellectual disposition (habitus). I argue that it is possible to offer such an interpretation of ‘intellectual virtue’ that aligns with the peripatetic tradition broadly understood (to which the epistemology of virtues ascends), and on the basis of which an evidentialist theory of justification is offered. In the first part of the paper, I briefly present the main interpretations of virtue epistemology and evidentialism in the light of externalism/internalism debate. In the second part I discuss Aquinas’ understanding of intellectual virtue as a disposition (habitus). The main concern here are virtues of theoretical habitus – wisdom and (scientific) knowledge. I show that habitus in this case is understood in two ways: as an ability, inherent to human beings, and as objective knowledge. Thus, there are two understandings of wisdom – as a virtue and knowledge (scientia). Finally, in the concluding parts of the paper, I outline possible ways of solving presented in the first part challenges to evidentialism and internalism.
我在这篇文章中主要关注的是美德认识论和证据主义之间的联系。这种可能的联系首先是基于智慧的智力美德的例子,其次是基于历史案例——托马斯·阿奎那将智慧美德视为一种智力倾向(习惯)的方法。我认为,有可能提供这样一种对“智力美德”的解释,这种解释与广泛理解的流浪传统(美德的认识论由此上升)相一致,并在此基础上提出了证据主义的证明理论。本文第一部分简要介绍了外在主义与内在主义之争对美德认识论和证据主义的主要解释。在第二部分中,我讨论了阿奎那对知性美德作为一种性情(习性)的理解。这里主要关注的是理论习惯的优点——智慧和(科学)知识。我认为习惯可以从两方面理解:一是人类固有的能力,二是客观知识。因此,对智慧有两种理解——作为美德和知识(科学)。最后,在本文的结论部分,我概述了解决第一部分中提出的对证据主义和内在主义的挑战的可能方法。
{"title":"Epistemic Virtue of Wisdom and Evidentialism","authors":"K. Karpov","doi":"10.5840/eps202158469","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158469","url":null,"abstract":"My primary concern in this article is the connection between virtue epistemology and evidentialism. This possible connection is analyzed upon, firstly, the example of the intellectual virtue of wisdom, and, secondly, the historical case – Thomas Aquinas’ approach to virtue of wisdom as an intellectual disposition (habitus). I argue that it is possible to offer such an interpretation of ‘intellectual virtue’ that aligns with the peripatetic tradition broadly understood (to which the epistemology of virtues ascends), and on the basis of which an evidentialist theory of justification is offered. In the first part of the paper, I briefly present the main interpretations of virtue epistemology and evidentialism in the light of externalism/internalism debate. In the second part I discuss Aquinas’ understanding of intellectual virtue as a disposition (habitus). The main concern here are virtues of theoretical habitus – wisdom and (scientific) knowledge. I show that habitus in this case is understood in two ways: as an ability, inherent to human beings, and as objective knowledge. Thus, there are two understandings of wisdom – as a virtue and knowledge (scientia). Finally, in the concluding parts of the paper, I outline possible ways of solving presented in the first part challenges to evidentialism and internalism.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71005976","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1