首页 > 最新文献

Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki最新文献

英文 中文
Benacerraf and Set-Theoretic Reductionist Realism 贝纳瑟拉夫与集合论还原论实在论
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158115
L. Lamberov
The paper is devoted to analysis of P. Benacerraf’s argument against set-theoretic reductionist realism which is a fragment of a broader argument, know as the “identification problem”. The analyzed fragment of P. Benacerraf’s argument concerns the possibility of reducing of mathematical notions to set-theoretic notions. The paper presents a reconstruction of P. Benacerraf’s original argumentation, its analysis and also several possible objections proposed by P. Benacerraf himself about 30 years later after the original publication. Namely, he claimed (1) that a set-theoretic definition of natural numbers in G. Frege’s fashion can serve as a proper and unique set-theoretic definition, (2) that his argument doesn’t undermine eliminative reductionsts’ position, (3) that even if there are no argument possible in favor of some particular set-theoretic definition of natural numbers one may take set-theoretic realism for granted. An analysis of the mentioned possible objections shows their dependence on a number of additional premises. The paper demonstrates that P. Benacerraf’s objections on his own argument against set-theoretic realism either have a pragmatic character themselves or essentially rely on additional arguments that are justified pragmatically or require additional argumentation. For example, his possible objections require that set theory is considered as the only true foundational theory in mathematics, and that it has several important pragmatic virtues, like convenience of use to formalize other mathematical theories. In some cases, P. Benacerraf’s objections on their own, or the indicated additional principles may well be called into question, which demonstrates the insufficiency of P. Benacerraf’s objections against his original argument. Without the mentioned pragmatic arguments P. Benacerraf’s objections become a kind of belief in mysticism. Accordingly, his doubts about his own argument against set-theoretical realism seem insufficient to reject the problem of identification and save the position of set-theoretical realism from collapse.
本文致力于分析P. Benacerraf反对集合论还原论实在论的论点,这是一个更广泛的论点的一部分,被称为“认同问题”。P. Benacerraf论证的分析片段涉及将数学概念还原为集合论概念的可能性。本文对P. Benacerraf的原始论证进行了重构,并对其进行了分析,同时也对P. Benacerraf本人在原论文发表约30年后提出的几种可能的反对意见进行了阐述。也就是说,他声称(1)G. Frege风格的自然数的集合论定义可以作为一个适当的和唯一的集合论定义,(2)他的论证不会破坏消除约化论者的立场,(3)即使没有可能支持自然数的某些特定集合论定义的论证,人们也可以将集合论实在论视为理所当然。对上述可能的反对意见的分析表明,它们依赖于一些额外的前提。本文论证了P. Benacerraf对自己反对集合论实在论的论证的反对,要么本身具有语用性,要么本质上依赖于经语用论证或需要额外论证的附加论证。例如,他可能的反对意见要求集合论被认为是数学中唯一真正的基础理论,并且它有几个重要的实用优点,比如便于形式化其他数学理论。在某些情况下,P. Benacerraf的反对意见本身,或所指出的附加原则可能会受到质疑,这表明P. Benacerraf反对其原始论点的反对意见是不充分的。如果没有上述的实用主义论据,P. Benacerraf的反对就变成了一种对神秘主义的信仰。因此,他对自己反对集合论实在论的论点的怀疑似乎不足以拒绝认同问题,也不足以挽救集合论实在论的地位免于崩溃。
{"title":"Benacerraf and Set-Theoretic Reductionist Realism","authors":"L. Lamberov","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158115","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158115","url":null,"abstract":"The paper is devoted to analysis of P. Benacerraf’s argument against set-theoretic reductionist realism which is a fragment of a broader argument, know as the “identification problem”. The analyzed fragment of P. Benacerraf’s argument concerns the possibility of reducing of mathematical notions to set-theoretic notions. The paper presents a reconstruction of P. Benacerraf’s original argumentation, its analysis and also several possible objections proposed by P. Benacerraf himself about 30 years later after the original publication. Namely, he claimed (1) that a set-theoretic definition of natural numbers in G. Frege’s fashion can serve as a proper and unique set-theoretic definition, (2) that his argument doesn’t undermine eliminative reductionsts’ position, (3) that even if there are no argument possible in favor of some particular set-theoretic definition of natural numbers one may take set-theoretic realism for granted. An analysis of the mentioned possible objections shows their dependence on a number of additional premises. The paper demonstrates that P. Benacerraf’s objections on his own argument against set-theoretic realism either have a pragmatic character themselves or essentially rely on additional arguments that are justified pragmatically or require additional argumentation. For example, his possible objections require that set theory is considered as the only true foundational theory in mathematics, and that it has several important pragmatic virtues, like convenience of use to formalize other mathematical theories. In some cases, P. Benacerraf’s objections on their own, or the indicated additional principles may well be called into question, which demonstrates the insufficiency of P. Benacerraf’s objections against his original argument. Without the mentioned pragmatic arguments P. Benacerraf’s objections become a kind of belief in mysticism. Accordingly, his doubts about his own argument against set-theoretical realism seem insufficient to reject the problem of identification and save the position of set-theoretical realism from collapse.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003780","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ethics of Uncertainty As an Extension of Virtue Epistemology 不确定性伦理学作为美德认识论的延伸
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158116
S. Shevchenko
Uncertainty can’t be understood without taking into account both properties of the problem situation and agent’s knowledge about it. The correspondence of knowledge and situation of decision-making is crucial for understanding the onto-epistemological nature of uncertainty. At the same time, this correspondence is the key topic in virtue epistemology, especially in its ‘non-classical’, regulatory, branch, related to works of R. Roberts and W.J. Wood. In this article, genetic consultation is chosen as an example of such a problematic situation since a doctor and a patient explicitly deal with the uncertainty of genetic risks. The problems of communication and joint decision-making in the context of medical-genetic consultation are comprehensively described in bioethics. At the same time, its social dimension is limited to the direct interaction of two individual agents, that allows us to use it as a model for constructing the ethics of uncertainty. In this article, four forms of uncertainty are identified: descriptive, normative and radical uncertainties, and translation uncertainty. Referring to the approaches of virtue epistemology, the author brings each of these forms into conformity with the proposed regulatory principle. The regulations assume that generating or disseminating knowledge under conditions of uncertainty require taking into account the incompleteness of the presented model of reality in its four aspects. A modelled fragment of reality could change in a predictable (descriptive uncertainty) or unexpected (radical uncertainty) way. The goals and values of a model’s user can not be hierarchically ordered, and may also change in the future (normative uncertainty). User’s interpretations of the model may be diverse, and can never be strictly defined by the intentions of the model’s author (indeterminancy of translation, or uncertainty whether success of co-reference is achieved).
如果不同时考虑问题情境的性质和agent对它的了解,不确定性是无法被理解的。知识与决策情境的对应性对于理解不确定性的本体-认识论本质至关重要。与此同时,这种对应性是美德认识论的关键主题,尤其是在与r·罗伯茨和w·j·伍德的作品有关的“非经典”、规范分支中。在这篇文章中,遗传咨询被选为这样一个有问题的情况的一个例子,因为医生和病人明确地处理遗传风险的不确定性。在医学遗传咨询的背景下,沟通和共同决策的问题在生物伦理学全面描述。同时,它的社会维度被限制在两个个体主体的直接互动中,这使得我们可以用它作为构建不确定性伦理的模型。本文确定了四种形式的不确定性:描述性不确定性、规范性不确定性和根本性不确定性以及翻译不确定性。参考德性认识论的方法,笔者将这些形式与所提出的调节原则相一致。这些规则假定,在不确定条件下产生或传播知识需要考虑到所提出的现实模型在四个方面的不完全性。现实的建模片段可以以可预测(描述性不确定性)或不可预测(根本不确定性)的方式变化。模型用户的目标和价值不能按层次顺序排列,并且在将来也可能发生变化(规范的不确定性)。用户对模型的解释可能是多种多样的,并且永远不能由模型作者的意图严格定义(翻译的不确定性,或者共同引用是否成功的不确定性)。
{"title":"Ethics of Uncertainty As an Extension of Virtue Epistemology","authors":"S. Shevchenko","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158116","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158116","url":null,"abstract":"Uncertainty can’t be understood without taking into account both properties of the problem situation and agent’s knowledge about it. The correspondence of knowledge and situation of decision-making is crucial for understanding the onto-epistemological nature of uncertainty. At the same time, this correspondence is the key topic in virtue epistemology, especially in its ‘non-classical’, regulatory, branch, related to works of R. Roberts and W.J. Wood. In this article, genetic consultation is chosen as an example of such a problematic situation since a doctor and a patient explicitly deal with the uncertainty of genetic risks. The problems of communication and joint decision-making in the context of medical-genetic consultation are comprehensively described in bioethics. At the same time, its social dimension is limited to the direct interaction of two individual agents, that allows us to use it as a model for constructing the ethics of uncertainty. In this article, four forms of uncertainty are identified: descriptive, normative and radical uncertainties, and translation uncertainty. Referring to the approaches of virtue epistemology, the author brings each of these forms into conformity with the proposed regulatory principle. The regulations assume that generating or disseminating knowledge under conditions of uncertainty require taking into account the incompleteness of the presented model of reality in its four aspects. A modelled fragment of reality could change in a predictable (descriptive uncertainty) or unexpected (radical uncertainty) way. The goals and values of a model’s user can not be hierarchically ordered, and may also change in the future (normative uncertainty). User’s interpretations of the model may be diverse, and can never be strictly defined by the intentions of the model’s author (indeterminancy of translation, or uncertainty whether success of co-reference is achieved).","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003870","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
So, What Is Tractatus? Reply to Critics 那么,什么是Tractatus?回应批评
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS20215819
A. Nikiforov
{"title":"So, What Is Tractatus? Reply to Critics","authors":"A. Nikiforov","doi":"10.5840/EPS20215819","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS20215819","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003905","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Wisdom, not Veritism 智慧,而不是真理
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158460
Shane Ryan
In this response to Pritchard’s “In Defence of Veritism”, I defend the view that it is wisdom rather than truth that is fundamental in epistemology. Given that recent philosophical discussions of the nature of wisdom may be unfamiliar to some epistemologists, a brief overview of these discussions is provided and that which is relevant for the subsequent discussion in this piece is highlighted. I explain that scholars working on the topic tend to accept that wisdom comprises at least one familiar epistemic standing and that, unlike other epistemic goods, wisdom is thought to be tied to a narrowly specified content. I clarify the philosophical question to which veritism is the proposed answer and clarify the different senses of fundamental in play in that question. As Pritchard points out, fundamentality in epistemology concern both conceptual and axiological claims. Next, I explicate Pritchard’s veritism, his defence of the claim that truth is fundamental in epistemology, explaining the case made for it’s superiority over the considered alternatives. One alternative I consider is that there is no fundamental good in epistemology, either conceptually or axiologically. I examine whether Pritchard can reject truth equality successfully while maintaining his monism with regard to what he takes to be epistemically fundamental. Indeed, while Pritchard’s appeal to the intellectually virtuous inquirer here seems appropriate, his view that this ultimately provides support to his truth monism is less convincing for reasons that will be explored. I follow up this discussion by arguing that an appeal to the intellectually virtuous agent better lends support to wisdom as epistemically fundamental, rather than Pritchard’s veritism. I make the point that Pritchard’s claim that the intellectually virtuous agent loves the truth is plausible but I question whether it’s also plausible that the love of the intellectually virtuous agent stops at the truth. Rather, I claim that such an agent ultimately loves wisdom. In fact, wisdom seems likely to be the highest good prized by the intellectually virtuous agent – the good that they strive to attain or become better with regard to across a lifetime. In support of this claim, I point out that wisdom is the most prized of all epistemic goods.
在对普理查德的《为真理论辩护》的回应中,我为这样一种观点辩护:在认识论中,智慧而非真理才是根本。鉴于最近关于智慧本质的哲学讨论对一些认识论者来说可能是陌生的,我们将简要概述这些讨论,并强调与本文后续讨论相关的内容。我解释说,研究这一主题的学者倾向于接受智慧至少包含一种熟悉的认知立场,而且与其他认知商品不同,智慧被认为与狭隘的特定内容有关。我澄清了以真理论作为答案的哲学问题,并澄清了在这个问题中起作用的基本的不同意义。正如普里查德所指出的那样,认识论中的基要性既涉及概念主张,也涉及价值论主张。接下来,我将解释普里查德的真理论,他对真理是认识论基础的主张的辩护,解释了它优于被考虑的替代方案的理由。我考虑的另一种选择是认识论中没有根本的善,无论是概念上的还是价值论上的。我将考察普里查德是否能够成功地拒绝真理平等,同时维持他的一元论,即他所认为的认识论基础。的确,尽管普里查德在这里对智力高尚的询问者的呼吁似乎是恰当的,但他认为这最终为他的真理一元论提供了支持,这一观点并不那么令人信服,原因有待探讨。我在此讨论的基础上提出,与普里查德的真理论相比,对智力上有美德的主体的呼吁更能支持智慧作为认识论基础的观点。我想说的是,普理查德关于智力善良的行为人爱真理的说法是有道理的,但我质疑智力善良的行为人的爱止于真理是否也有道理。更确切地说,我认为这样的代理人最终是热爱智慧的。事实上,智慧似乎是智力高尚的人所珍视的最高利益——他们一生都在努力实现或变得更好的利益。为了支持这一观点,我指出智慧是所有认知商品中最珍贵的。
{"title":"Wisdom, not Veritism","authors":"Shane Ryan","doi":"10.5840/eps202158460","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158460","url":null,"abstract":"In this response to Pritchard’s “In Defence of Veritism”, I defend the view that it is wisdom rather than truth that is fundamental in epistemology. Given that recent philosophical discussions of the nature of wisdom may be unfamiliar to some epistemologists, a brief overview of these discussions is provided and that which is relevant for the subsequent discussion in this piece is highlighted. I explain that scholars working on the topic tend to accept that wisdom comprises at least one familiar epistemic standing and that, unlike other epistemic goods, wisdom is thought to be tied to a narrowly specified content. I clarify the philosophical question to which veritism is the proposed answer and clarify the different senses of fundamental in play in that question. As Pritchard points out, fundamentality in epistemology concern both conceptual and axiological claims. Next, I explicate Pritchard’s veritism, his defence of the claim that truth is fundamental in epistemology, explaining the case made for it’s superiority over the considered alternatives. One alternative I consider is that there is no fundamental good in epistemology, either conceptually or axiologically. I examine whether Pritchard can reject truth equality successfully while maintaining his monism with regard to what he takes to be epistemically fundamental. Indeed, while Pritchard’s appeal to the intellectually virtuous inquirer here seems appropriate, his view that this ultimately provides support to his truth monism is less convincing for reasons that will be explored. I follow up this discussion by arguing that an appeal to the intellectually virtuous agent better lends support to wisdom as epistemically fundamental, rather than Pritchard’s veritism. I make the point that Pritchard’s claim that the intellectually virtuous agent loves the truth is plausible but I question whether it’s also plausible that the love of the intellectually virtuous agent stops at the truth. Rather, I claim that such an agent ultimately loves wisdom. In fact, wisdom seems likely to be the highest good prized by the intellectually virtuous agent – the good that they strive to attain or become better with regard to across a lifetime. In support of this claim, I point out that wisdom is the most prized of all epistemic goods.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71005453","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Descriptive Turn in Epistemology 认识论中的描述转向
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158224
N. Kuznetsova
The article shows that cultural-historical epistemology erroneously puts forward the thesis of a global crisis in the sphere of modern epistemology and philosophy of science. The key error of such a diagnosis is rooted in the confusion of basic concepts. In the development of epistemological studies, the period of the last decades of the twentieth century, which was called the “descriptive turn”, is very important. In the philosophy of science, the task was set to reflect the real practice of scientific research. This has been successfully carried out in a number of works by Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend, Latour and others. The task of building universal norms of scientific research has faded into the background. In this regard, the subjects of "methodology of science", on the one hand, and "epistemology" and "philosophy of science", on the other hand, were distinguished. The formulation of norms and standards for scientific research has become the task of methodology. Describing scientific practice, including scientific revolutions, has become the task of the professional history of science. The philosophical understanding of the processes of historical evolution, the identification of the laws of the development of science has become the subject of the philosophy of science. Epistemology, in turn, is called upon to consider the phenomenon of knowledge not only in science, but also more broadly – in a variety of historical and cultural contexts. In modern studies in the field of epistemology and philosophy of science, case studies are important, as they provide invaluable empirical material for philosophical generalizations. As for the construction of universal standards for scientific work, such a task, as Feyerabend showed, seems to be impossible. Moreover, the universal methodological standard does not allow discovering the uniqueness of scientific research situations.
文化历史认识论在现代认识论和科学哲学领域错误地提出了全球危机的命题。这种诊断的关键错误根源于对基本概念的混淆。在认识论研究的发展中,20世纪最后几十年被称为“描述性转向”的时期是非常重要的。在科学哲学中,任务被设定为反映科学研究的真实实践。库恩、拉卡托斯、费耶阿本德、拉图尔等人的许多作品都成功地做到了这一点。建立科学研究普遍规范的任务已经退居次要地位。在这方面,一方面是“科学方法论”,另一方面是“认识论”和“科学哲学”。科学研究的规范和标准的制定已成为方法论的任务。描述科学实践,包括科学革命,已经成为科学史专业的任务。用哲学认识历史演进的过程,识别科学的发展规律,已成为科学哲学的课题。认识论,反过来,被要求考虑的知识现象不仅在科学,而且更广泛的-在各种历史和文化背景。在认识论和科学哲学领域的现代研究中,案例研究是重要的,因为它们为哲学概括提供了宝贵的经验材料。至于建立科学工作的普遍标准,正如费耶阿本德所表明的那样,这样的任务似乎是不可能的。此外,普遍的方法标准不允许发现科学研究情况的独特性。
{"title":"Descriptive Turn in Epistemology","authors":"N. Kuznetsova","doi":"10.5840/eps202158224","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158224","url":null,"abstract":"The article shows that cultural-historical epistemology erroneously puts forward the thesis of a global crisis in the sphere of modern epistemology and philosophy of science. The key error of such a diagnosis is rooted in the confusion of basic concepts. In the development of epistemological studies, the period of the last decades of the twentieth century, which was called the “descriptive turn”, is very important. In the philosophy of science, the task was set to reflect the real practice of scientific research. This has been successfully carried out in a number of works by Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend, Latour and others. The task of building universal norms of scientific research has faded into the background. In this regard, the subjects of \"methodology of science\", on the one hand, and \"epistemology\" and \"philosophy of science\", on the other hand, were distinguished. The formulation of norms and standards for scientific research has become the task of methodology. Describing scientific practice, including scientific revolutions, has become the task of the professional history of science. The philosophical understanding of the processes of historical evolution, the identification of the laws of the development of science has become the subject of the philosophy of science. Epistemology, in turn, is called upon to consider the phenomenon of knowledge not only in science, but also more broadly – in a variety of historical and cultural contexts. In modern studies in the field of epistemology and philosophy of science, case studies are important, as they provide invaluable empirical material for philosophical generalizations. As for the construction of universal standards for scientific work, such a task, as Feyerabend showed, seems to be impossible. Moreover, the universal methodological standard does not allow discovering the uniqueness of scientific research situations.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003959","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ethical Reading of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 《逻辑哲学论》的伦理解读
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS20215814
K. Rodin
The hundred-year history of interpretations of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus we examine in the article through a gradual approach (through the refusal of researchers from obviously erroneous interpretations) to an ethical (or metaphilosophical) reading of the work. The latter explains Wittgenstein’s unambiguous indication of ethical meaning as the main meaning of the Tractatus and consistently reconciles various parts of the work (ontology, figurative theory of meaning, rejection of the theory of types and logical constants, etc.) with the latest so-called ethical and mystical statements of the Tractatus and with demanding silence. An ethical (metaphilosophical) reading explains the continuing influence and relevance of the Tractatus and is presented in the article as a necessary condition for understanding the continuity between the works of early and late Wittgenstein.
维特根斯坦的《逻辑哲学论》的百年解读历史,我们在文章中通过渐进的方法(通过研究者拒绝明显错误的解读)来审视这部作品的伦理(或形而上学)解读。后者解释了维特根斯坦对伦理意义的明确指示作为《论》的主要意义,并始终将作品的各个部分(本体论、意义的比喻理论、对类型理论和逻辑常数的拒绝等)与《论》最新的所谓伦理和神秘主义陈述以及要求的沉默协调起来。伦理(形而上学)阅读解释了《论》的持续影响和相关性,并在文章中作为理解维特根斯坦早期和晚期作品之间连续性的必要条件提出。
{"title":"Ethical Reading of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus","authors":"K. Rodin","doi":"10.5840/EPS20215814","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS20215814","url":null,"abstract":"The hundred-year history of interpretations of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus we examine in the article through a gradual approach (through the refusal of researchers from obviously erroneous interpretations) to an ethical (or metaphilosophical) reading of the work. The latter explains Wittgenstein’s unambiguous indication of ethical meaning as the main meaning of the Tractatus and consistently reconciles various parts of the work (ontology, figurative theory of meaning, rejection of the theory of types and logical constants, etc.) with the latest so-called ethical and mystical statements of the Tractatus and with demanding silence. An ethical (metaphilosophical) reading explains the continuing influence and relevance of the Tractatus and is presented in the article as a necessary condition for understanding the continuity between the works of early and late Wittgenstein.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71004103","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
From “Nomos” to “Physis” and Back 从"诺莫斯"到"物理"再回来
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158235
I. Dmitriev
The article focuses on the following three issues: the characteristic features of understanding and using the term “law of nature” before F. Bacon, the novelty of F. Bacon’s approach to the interpretation of this concept, theological and legal origins of the concept. It is shown that in works related to the Middle Ages the term “law of nature” had either a purely descriptive (descriptive-stating) or mixed prescriptive-descriptive character. It is shown that in the works of medieval authors the term “law of nature” had either a purely descriptive or mixed prescriptive-descriptive character. The novelty of the approach to understanding the law of nature in the works of F. Bacon lies primarily in the fact that in his interpretation the contours of the understanding of the “law of nature” as an expression of the causal relationship between facts and phenomena are clearly visible. Moreover, Bacon points to the “Latentis Processus et Latentis Schematismi” of bodies as the deepest causes of natural phenomena, that is, he refers to the micro-level of organization of matter. The article also examines the theological (in the context of the notion “God acts in the world only through secondary causes” and the Protestant doctrine of “cessation of miracles”) and legal (in the context of norms and practices of “common law”) sources of the Baconian understanding of the concept of “law of nature”.
本文主要探讨三个问题:培根之前对“自然法”一词的理解和使用的特点;培根解释这一概念的方法的新颖性;这一概念的神学和法律渊源。在与中世纪有关的著作中,“自然法则”一词要么具有纯粹的描述性(描述性-陈述),要么具有混合的描述性-描述性特征。在中世纪作者的著作中,“自然法则”一词要么具有纯粹的描述性,要么具有混合的描述性特征。在培根的著作中,理解自然法则的方法的新颖之处主要在于,在他的解释中,理解“自然法则”作为事实和现象之间因果关系的表达的轮廓是清晰可见的。此外,培根指出,物体的“潜过程和潜图式”是自然现象的最深层原因,也就是说,他指的是物质组织的微观层面。本文还考察了培根对“自然法”概念的理解的神学来源(在“上帝在世界上的行为只是通过次要原因”和新教“奇迹停止”的教义的背景下)和法律来源(在“普通法”的规范和实践的背景下)。
{"title":"From “Nomos” to “Physis” and Back","authors":"I. Dmitriev","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158235","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158235","url":null,"abstract":"The article focuses on the following three issues: the characteristic features of understanding and using the term “law of nature” before F. Bacon, the novelty of F. Bacon’s approach to the interpretation of this concept, theological and legal origins of the concept. It is shown that in works related to the Middle Ages the term “law of nature” had either a purely descriptive (descriptive-stating) or mixed prescriptive-descriptive character. It is shown that in the works of medieval authors the term “law of nature” had either a purely descriptive or mixed prescriptive-descriptive character. The novelty of the approach to understanding the law of nature in the works of F. Bacon lies primarily in the fact that in his interpretation the contours of the understanding of the “law of nature” as an expression of the causal relationship between facts and phenomena are clearly visible. Moreover, Bacon points to the “Latentis Processus et Latentis Schematismi” of bodies as the deepest causes of natural phenomena, that is, he refers to the micro-level of organization of matter. The article also examines the theological (in the context of the notion “God acts in the world only through secondary causes” and the Protestant doctrine of “cessation of miracles”) and legal (in the context of norms and practices of “common law”) sources of the Baconian understanding of the concept of “law of nature”.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71004304","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Virtue Epistemology as Anti-luck Epistemology 美德认识论作为反运气认识论
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202158462
A. Chernyak
The idea that knowledge as an individual mental attitude with certain propositional content is not only true justified belief but a belief the truth of which does not result from any kind of luck, is widely spread in contemporary epistemology. This account is known as anti-luck epistemology. A very popular explanation of the inconsistency of that concept of knowledge with the luck-dependent nature of truth (so called veritic luck taking place when a subject’s belief could not be true if not by mere coincidence) presumes that the status of propositional knowledge crucially depends on the qualities of actions that result in the corresponding belief, or processes backing them, which reflect the socalled intellectual virtues mainly responsible for subject’s relevant competences. This account known as Virtue Epistemology presumes that if a belief is true exclusively or mainly due to its dependence on intellectual virtues, it just cannot be true by luck, hence no place for lucky knowledge. But this thesis is hard to prove given the existence of true virtuous beliefs which could nevertheless be false if not for some lucky (for the knower) accident. This led to an appearance of virtue epistemological theories aimed specifically at an assimilation of such cases. Their authors try to represent the relevant situations as such where the contribution of luck is not crucial whereas the contribution of virtues is crucial. This article provides a critical analysis of the corresponding arguments as part of a more general study of the ability of Virtue Epistemology to provide justification for the thesis of incompatibility of propositional knowledge with veritic luck. It is shown that there are good reasons to doubt that Virtue Epistemology can do this.
知识作为一种具有特定命题内容的个人心理态度,不仅是一种被证明是正确的信念,而且是一种真理并非来自任何运气的信念,这种观点在当代认识论中广泛传播。这种说法被称为反运气认识论。一个非常流行的解释是,关于知识概念与真理的运气依赖性质的不一致(所谓的真实性运气发生在一个主体的信念如果不是纯粹巧合就不可能是真的时候),假设命题知识的地位关键取决于导致相应信念的行为的质量,或者支持它们的过程,这反映了所谓的智力美德,主要负责主体的相关能力。这种被称为美德认识论的说法假定,如果一个信念完全或主要是由于它对智力美德的依赖而成立的,那么它就不可能是靠运气成立的,因此没有幸运知识的地位。但是这个命题很难证明,因为存在真正的美德信仰,如果不是因为一些幸运的(对于知者)事故,这些信仰可能是错误的。这导致了一种美德认识论理论的出现,专门针对这些案例的同化。他们的作者试图表现出相关的情况,比如运气的贡献不重要,而美德的贡献至关重要。本文对相应的论证进行了批判性分析,作为对美德认识论能力的更广泛研究的一部分,以证明命题知识与验证运气不相容的论点。我们有充分的理由怀疑美德认识论能否做到这一点。
{"title":"Virtue Epistemology as Anti-luck Epistemology","authors":"A. Chernyak","doi":"10.5840/eps202158462","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202158462","url":null,"abstract":"The idea that knowledge as an individual mental attitude with certain propositional content is not only true justified belief but a belief the truth of which does not result from any kind of luck, is widely spread in contemporary epistemology. This account is known as anti-luck epistemology. A very popular explanation of the inconsistency of that concept of knowledge with the luck-dependent nature of truth (so called veritic luck taking place when a subject’s belief could not be true if not by mere coincidence) presumes that the status of propositional knowledge crucially depends on the qualities of actions that result in the corresponding belief, or processes backing them, which reflect the socalled intellectual virtues mainly responsible for subject’s relevant competences. This account known as Virtue Epistemology presumes that if a belief is true exclusively or mainly due to its dependence on intellectual virtues, it just cannot be true by luck, hence no place for lucky knowledge. But this thesis is hard to prove given the existence of true virtuous beliefs which could nevertheless be false if not for some lucky (for the knower) accident. This led to an appearance of virtue epistemological theories aimed specifically at an assimilation of such cases. Their authors try to represent the relevant situations as such where the contribution of luck is not crucial whereas the contribution of virtues is crucial. This article provides a critical analysis of the corresponding arguments as part of a more general study of the ability of Virtue Epistemology to provide justification for the thesis of incompatibility of propositional knowledge with veritic luck. It is shown that there are good reasons to doubt that Virtue Epistemology can do this.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71005532","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Jubilee of L.A. Mikeshina 洛杉矶的朱比利
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps20215811
{"title":"Jubilee of L.A. Mikeshina","authors":"","doi":"10.5840/eps20215811","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps20215811","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003534","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Difficult Points of Chess Metaphor in the Theoretical Questions of Language and Mind 语言与心理理论问题中的象棋隐喻难点
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158231
P. Baryshnikov
This review article reveals the structural components of the chess metaphor, which represent in an unusual perspective the properties of a linguistic sign and its connection with mental processes. Strict rule-following and the conventionality of the material plane of expression turn chess into a convenient illustration of a universal linguistic structure. Particular attention is paid to the computer profile of the chess metaphor, since it reflects a whole complex of philosophical problems of computer science about mind, thinking and intelligence. In the proposed paper, the presentation of most of the material is based on the works of F. de Saussure, L. Hjelmslev, L. Wittgenstein and their interpreters, in whose texts an obvious important place is occupied by chess analogies and theoretical conclusions initiated by them. First we investigate chess metaphor in the context of language and speech structures. Next, we analyze the "chess track" in the problem of individual language and the rule-following problem. The final part is devoted to the technical elements of computer chess and the influence of this area of computer science on some of the points of cognitive theories of language and mind. The author of the article emphasizes a nontrivial transformation of the conceptual content of the chess metaphor, which indicates the evolution of computational tendencies in modern theories about language and mind. The article substantiates the thesis that the traditional chess metaphor used in the XX century in the philosophical investigation of language and mind, today it takes on a realization in the framework of computer models of the chess game. Machine deep learning can significantly expand the horizon of computability. Game interaction makes it possible to ascribe the elements of intentional content to machine functions. Nevertheless, all the argumentation in the work is aimed at proving that the rules governing language and mind are rules different from the rules of computer intelligence.
这篇综述文章揭示了象棋隐喻的结构成分,它以一种不同寻常的视角代表了语言符号的属性及其与心理过程的联系。严格的规则遵循和物质表达平面的约定俗成使象棋成为一种通用语言结构的方便例证。特别要注意的是象棋比喻的计算机轮廓,因为它反映了计算机科学中关于心灵、思维和智力的一整套哲学问题。在本文中,大部分材料的呈现都是基于索绪尔、海姆斯列夫、维特根斯坦及其诠释者的著作,在他们的文本中,象棋类比和他们提出的理论结论占据了明显的重要位置。首先,我们在语言和言语结构的背景下研究象棋隐喻。其次,我们分析了个体语言问题中的“象棋轨迹”和规则遵循问题。最后一部分致力于计算机国际象棋的技术要素,以及计算机科学的这一领域对语言和心理认知理论的一些观点的影响。作者强调了象棋隐喻概念内容的重大转变,这表明了现代语言和思维理论中计算倾向的演变。本文论证了20世纪在语言和思维的哲学研究中使用的传统象棋隐喻,今天在象棋游戏的计算机模型框架中得到了实现。机器深度学习可以显著扩展可计算性的视野。游戏交互可以将有意内容的元素归因于机器功能。然而,所有的论证都是为了证明支配语言和思维的规则不同于计算机智能的规则。
{"title":"Difficult Points of Chess Metaphor in the Theoretical Questions of Language and Mind","authors":"P. Baryshnikov","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158231","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158231","url":null,"abstract":"This review article reveals the structural components of the chess metaphor, which represent in an unusual perspective the properties of a linguistic sign and its connection with mental processes. Strict rule-following and the conventionality of the material plane of expression turn chess into a convenient illustration of a universal linguistic structure. Particular attention is paid to the computer profile of the chess metaphor, since it reflects a whole complex of philosophical problems of computer science about mind, thinking and intelligence. In the proposed paper, the presentation of most of the material is based on the works of F. de Saussure, L. Hjelmslev, L. Wittgenstein and their interpreters, in whose texts an obvious important place is occupied by chess analogies and theoretical conclusions initiated by them. First we investigate chess metaphor in the context of language and speech structures. Next, we analyze the \"chess track\" in the problem of individual language and the rule-following problem. The final part is devoted to the technical elements of computer chess and the influence of this area of computer science on some of the points of cognitive theories of language and mind. The author of the article emphasizes a nontrivial transformation of the conceptual content of the chess metaphor, which indicates the evolution of computational tendencies in modern theories about language and mind. The article substantiates the thesis that the traditional chess metaphor used in the XX century in the philosophical investigation of language and mind, today it takes on a realization in the framework of computer models of the chess game. Machine deep learning can significantly expand the horizon of computability. Game interaction makes it possible to ascribe the elements of intentional content to machine functions. Nevertheless, all the argumentation in the work is aimed at proving that the rules governing language and mind are rules different from the rules of computer intelligence.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71003758","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1