首页 > 最新文献

Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki最新文献

英文 中文
Rhetoric of Science 科学修辞学
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-06-19 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158233
I. Griftsova, N. Y. Kozlova
This contribution examines the status of the rhetoric of science in two contexts. The first one is the effect that the changing interpretation of logic (the changing 'image of logic') has had on the status of the rhetoric of science. The second is the role that imagery has in scientific discourse. It is argued that the very possibility of a rhetorical interpretation of science depends on how the logic of science is understood. Informal logic, which acts here as a variant of argumentation theory or a logic of argumentation, is proposed as such a logic. This leads to a revision of the nature of justification in science in general, the substitution of apodictic logic for a logic of argumentation as a principal tool, and the consideration of strict formal ways of material implication-based justification as mere individual cases of a logic of argumentation. The role of imagery in scientific discourse is analysed. It is demonstrated that the situation of rhetoric and perception of imagery is paradoxical: although using rhetorical mechanisms in scientific communication is unavoidable, rhetoric has been criticised for many centuries. It is shown that the negative attitude to using rhetorical elements in scientific texts has long historical roots going back to ancient philosophical thought, namely, Socrates's criticism of eloquence and sophistic rhetoric. Analysis of the functions of imagery in scientific discourse suggests that imagery is an inalienable mechanism of both professional communication and the creation of theoretical models of knowledge.
这篇文章从两个方面考察了科学修辞学的地位。第一个是逻辑解释的变化(逻辑意象的变化)对科学修辞学地位的影响。二是意象在科学话语中的作用。有人认为,对科学进行修辞解释的可能性取决于如何理解科学的逻辑。非正式逻辑,在这里作为论证理论的变体或论证逻辑,被认为是这样一种逻辑。这导致了对一般科学中正当性的本质的修正,用指称逻辑取代了作为主要工具的论证逻辑,并将基于物质暗示的正当性的严格形式化方式视为论证逻辑的个别案例。分析了意象在科学话语中的作用。研究表明,修辞和意象感知的状况是矛盾的:尽管在科学传播中使用修辞机制是不可避免的,但修辞已经受到了几个世纪的批评。研究表明,在科学文本中使用修辞元素的消极态度有着悠久的历史渊源,可以追溯到古代哲学思想,即苏格拉底对雄辩和诡辩修辞的批评。对意象在科学话语中的作用的分析表明,意象是专业交流和创造知识理论模型的不可分割的机制。
{"title":"Rhetoric of Science","authors":"I. Griftsova, N. Y. Kozlova","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158233","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158233","url":null,"abstract":"This contribution examines the status of the rhetoric of science in two contexts. The first one is the effect that the changing interpretation of logic (the changing 'image of logic') has had on the status of the rhetoric of science. The second is the role that imagery has in scientific discourse. It is argued that the very possibility of a rhetorical interpretation of science depends on how the logic of science is understood. Informal logic, which acts here as a variant of argumentation theory or a logic of argumentation, is proposed as such a logic. This leads to a revision of the nature of justification in science in general, the substitution of apodictic logic for a logic of argumentation as a principal tool, and the consideration of strict formal ways of material implication-based justification as mere individual cases of a logic of argumentation. The role of imagery in scientific discourse is analysed. It is demonstrated that the situation of rhetoric and perception of imagery is paradoxical: although using rhetorical mechanisms in scientific communication is unavoidable, rhetoric has been criticised for many centuries. It is shown that the negative attitude to using rhetorical elements in scientific texts has long historical roots going back to ancient philosophical thought, namely, Socrates's criticism of eloquence and sophistic rhetoric. Analysis of the functions of imagery in scientific discourse suggests that imagery is an inalienable mechanism of both professional communication and the creation of theoretical models of knowledge.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44493762","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Social Position of an Expert as a New Element of Science 作为科学新元素的专家的社会地位
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158232
Evgeny V. Maslanov
The article focuses on analyzing the changes that have occurred in the procedures for assessing scientific knowledge during the period of their massive introduction into the economy, politics and everyday life, as well as the formation of a new social position of the expert. Up to this point, the assessment of scientific knowledge often took place within the scientific community. In that case, a special role was played by “authority” able to evaluate projects basing on criteria intrinsic to the scientific ethos. The active introduction of scientific knowledge into the social life encouraged the emergence of a new expert’s social position differing from an intrascientific “authority”. In their work, they have to evaluate projects that involve large financial resources and contribute to changes in social and economic life, and therefore, in addition to scientific criteria, such experts consider any possible economic, political and social consequences of the project implementation. Along with it, the formation of the new expert’s social position and its active use by scientists leads to several problems. First, the expertise and expert practices are beginning to be used by scientists to legitimize their own position in science and fight rival groups. Second, these processes can provoke a decrease in diversity both within science itself and in the number of cognitive practices; also they can limit the emergence of new approaches to the analysis of technological, economic, political and social innovations.
本文着重分析科学知识在经济、政治和日常生活中大量引入的过程中,评估科学知识的程序发生了变化,以及专家新的社会地位的形成。到目前为止,对科学知识的评估通常在科学界内部进行。在这种情况下,能够根据科学精神固有的标准评估项目的“权威”发挥了特殊作用。科学知识在社会生活中的积极引入鼓励了一种新的专家的社会地位的出现,这种地位不同于科学内部的“权威”。在他们的工作中,他们必须评估涉及大量财政资源并有助于社会和经济生活变化的项目,因此,除了科学标准外,这些专家还必须考虑项目实施可能产生的任何经济、政治和社会后果。与此同时,新专家社会地位的形成及其在科学家中的积极运用也带来了一些问题。首先,科学家们开始利用专业知识和专家实践来使自己在科学中的地位合法化,并与敌对团体作斗争。其次,这些过程可能会导致科学本身和认知实践数量的多样性下降;它们还可以限制分析技术、经济、政治和社会创新的新方法的出现。
{"title":"Social Position of an Expert as a New Element of Science","authors":"Evgeny V. Maslanov","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158232","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158232","url":null,"abstract":"The article focuses on analyzing the changes that have occurred in the procedures for assessing scientific knowledge during the period of their massive introduction into the economy, politics and everyday life, as well as the formation of a new social position of the expert. Up to this point, the assessment of scientific knowledge often took place within the scientific community. In that case, a special role was played by “authority” able to evaluate projects basing on criteria intrinsic to the scientific ethos. The active introduction of scientific knowledge into the social life encouraged the emergence of a new expert’s social position differing from an intrascientific “authority”. In their work, they have to evaluate projects that involve large financial resources and contribute to changes in social and economic life, and therefore, in addition to scientific criteria, such experts consider any possible economic, political and social consequences of the project implementation. Along with it, the formation of the new expert’s social position and its active use by scientists leads to several problems. First, the expertise and expert practices are beginning to be used by scientists to legitimize their own position in science and fight rival groups. Second, these processes can provoke a decrease in diversity both within science itself and in the number of cognitive practices; also they can limit the emergence of new approaches to the analysis of technological, economic, political and social innovations.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48720591","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Metaphysics and Realism 形而上学与现实主义
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158237
V. Kosykhin, S. Malkina
The article deals with the problem of the return of metaphysics within the framework of the ontological turn of philosophy and the situation of post-metaphysical thinking. The conditions for the possibility of modern metaphysical discourse in the projects of empirical metaphysics and historical ontology are revealed. Historical ontology as a meta-reflexion of philosophy over its own historical foundations is able to bridge the gap between the epistemological static nature of transcendental subjectivity and the ontological dynamism of the growth of scientific knowledge about reality by comprehending the conditions of interaction between science and metaphysics in conditions of post-metaphysical thinking and realistic reversal of ontology. Philosophical knowledge in the context of the ontological turn and the associated return of metaphysics becomes focused not so much on the sharp demarcation of science and metaphysics and postulating the incommensurability of their ontologies, but on identifying mutually enriching areas of research that could give a new impetus to their development.
本文在哲学本体论转向和后形而上学思维形势的框架下,探讨了形而上学的回归问题。揭示了现代形而上学话语在经验形而上学和历史本体论方案中的可能性条件。历史本体论作为哲学对其自身历史基础的元反思,能够通过理解科学与形而上学在后形而上学思维和本体论的现实逆转条件下相互作用的条件,弥合先验主体性的认识论静态性质与关于现实的科学知识增长的本体论动态之间的差距。在本体论转向和形而上学相关回归的背景下,哲学知识不再那么关注科学和形而上学的尖锐界限,也不再假设它们的本体论不可通约性,而是关注识别相互丰富的研究领域,这些研究领域可以为它们的发展提供新的动力。
{"title":"Metaphysics and Realism","authors":"V. Kosykhin, S. Malkina","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158237","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158237","url":null,"abstract":"The article deals with the problem of the return of metaphysics within the framework of the ontological turn of philosophy and the situation of post-metaphysical thinking. The conditions for the possibility of modern metaphysical discourse in the projects of empirical metaphysics and historical ontology are revealed. Historical ontology as a meta-reflexion of philosophy over its own historical foundations is able to bridge the gap between the epistemological static nature of transcendental subjectivity and the ontological dynamism of the growth of scientific knowledge about reality by comprehending the conditions of interaction between science and metaphysics in conditions of post-metaphysical thinking and realistic reversal of ontology. Philosophical knowledge in the context of the ontological turn and the associated return of metaphysics becomes focused not so much on the sharp demarcation of science and metaphysics and postulating the incommensurability of their ontologies, but on identifying mutually enriching areas of research that could give a new impetus to their development.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47436013","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On Wittgenstein’s Influence on the Logical Positivists 论维特根斯坦对逻辑实证主义者的影响
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-03-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS20215815
V. Vasilyev
In this article, I consider the influence of the ideas of Ludwig Wittgenstein, and above all the ideas of his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus on the philosophy of logical positivism. Agreeing that the question of such an influence is not a self-evident one, I clarify at first the concept of logical positivism and then turn to the evidence of the leading logical positivists about the influence of Wittgenstein upon them. An analysis of recollections of Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, Otto Neurath, Friedrich Waismann, and Alfred Ayer suggests that at least these thinkers themselves considered such an influence as very significant.
在本文中,我将考虑路德维希·维特根斯坦思想的影响,尤其是他的《逻辑哲学论》思想对逻辑实证主义哲学的影响。我同意这种影响的问题不是一个自明的问题,我首先澄清了逻辑实证主义的概念,然后转向主要的逻辑实证主义者关于维特根斯坦对他们的影响的证据。对莫里茨·施里克、鲁道夫·卡尔纳普、奥托·纽赖特、弗里德里希·魏斯曼和阿尔弗雷德·艾尔的回忆的分析表明,至少这些思想家自己认为这种影响是非常重要的。
{"title":"On Wittgenstein’s Influence on the Logical Positivists","authors":"V. Vasilyev","doi":"10.5840/EPS20215815","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS20215815","url":null,"abstract":"In this article, I consider the influence of the ideas of Ludwig Wittgenstein, and above all the ideas of his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus on the philosophy of logical positivism. Agreeing that the question of such an influence is not a self-evident one, I clarify at first the concept of logical positivism and then turn to the evidence of the leading logical positivists about the influence of Wittgenstein upon them. An analysis of recollections of Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, Otto Neurath, Friedrich Waismann, and Alfred Ayer suggests that at least these thinkers themselves considered such an influence as very significant.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44028408","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Alexius Meinong's Extraontology Alexius Meinong的《外存论
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-03-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158119
V. Seliverstov
The notion of Ausersein/outbeing, proposed by Alexius Meinong, was for a long time in the shadow of the principle of the Ausersein of a pure object, which made it possible to make non-existent objects part of a judgment. This principle was adopted by many followers of Meinong within the framework of analytical philosophy, but the very concept of Ausersein was almost totally ignored. When it’s become an object of research, there appeared several interpretations of it. It was interpreted either as a way of describing the ontological status of non-existent objects, or as a basic property of all objects without exception. Dale Jacquette suggests interpreting Ausersein as extraontology, i.e. a metasemantic category that includes all items. In this article, we will analyse the arguments of modern interpreters of this notion and try to find out which interpretation is most correct.
亚历克修斯·梅农提出的客体存在/外在存在的概念,在很长一段时间内都处于纯粹客体的客体存在原则的阴影之下,这使得不存在的客体成为判断的一部分成为可能。这一原则在分析哲学的框架内被美农的许多追随者所采用,但“用户”这个概念却几乎完全被忽视了。当它成为研究对象时,出现了几种解释。它要么被解释为描述不存在对象的本体论状态的一种方式,要么被解释为所有对象毫无例外的基本属性。Dale Jacquette建议将用户定义为外存论(extraontology),即包含所有项目的元语义范畴。在本文中,我们将分析这一概念的现代诠释者的论点,并试图找出哪种解释是最正确的。
{"title":"Alexius Meinong's Extraontology","authors":"V. Seliverstov","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158119","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158119","url":null,"abstract":"The notion of Ausersein/outbeing, proposed by Alexius Meinong, was for a long time in the shadow of the principle of the Ausersein of a pure object, which made it possible to make non-existent objects part of a judgment. This principle was adopted by many followers of Meinong within the framework of analytical philosophy, but the very concept of Ausersein was almost totally ignored. When it’s become an object of research, there appeared several interpretations of it. It was interpreted either as a way of describing the ontological status of non-existent objects, or as a basic property of all objects without exception. Dale Jacquette suggests interpreting Ausersein as extraontology, i.e. a metasemantic category that includes all items. In this article, we will analyse the arguments of modern interpreters of this notion and try to find out which interpretation is most correct.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46255313","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Inherent Logic in the Idea of the Multiverse 多元宇宙思想的内在逻辑
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-03-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158118
Nick Overduin
The idea of the multiverse, likely difficult to prove in traditional scientific ways, may be bolstered by two arguments from the field of logic. This article, contextualized by the metaphorical, non-logical approaches to the multiverse and situating itself within the history of astronomy, explicates these two arguments from logic. The first argument relates to the implicit illogical vanity in the assumption that our presently-known universe is special. In other words, it may be somewhat logical to embrace the history of deanthropomorphism more fully in the light of the Big Bang and the theory of cosmic inflation. The second argument suggests resolution to the long-standing philosophical and logical mysteries associated with the anthropic principle, as well as the attendant use of Ockham’s razor as a logical tool. The problem of evidence and falsifiability is briefly implicated, as well as some consequences for apologetics.
多元宇宙的概念可能很难用传统的科学方法来证明,可能会得到逻辑领域的两个论点的支持。本文以多元宇宙的隐喻性、非逻辑性方法为背景,将其置于天文学史中,从逻辑上解释了这两个论点。第一个论点与我们目前已知的宇宙是特殊的假设中隐含的不合逻辑的虚荣有关。换言之,根据宇宙大爆炸和宇宙膨胀理论,更充分地接受去人类形态的历史可能是合乎逻辑的。第二个论点建议解决与人类原理相关的长期哲学和逻辑谜团,以及随之而来的将奥卡姆剃刀作为逻辑工具的使用。证据和可证伪性的问题被简要地牵涉在内,以及对辩护学的一些后果。
{"title":"The Inherent Logic in the Idea of the Multiverse","authors":"Nick Overduin","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158118","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158118","url":null,"abstract":"The idea of the multiverse, likely difficult to prove in traditional scientific ways, may be bolstered by two arguments from the field of logic. This article, contextualized by the metaphorical, non-logical approaches to the multiverse and situating itself within the history of astronomy, explicates these two arguments from logic. The first argument relates to the implicit illogical vanity in the assumption that our presently-known universe is special. In other words, it may be somewhat logical to embrace the history of deanthropomorphism more fully in the light of the Big Bang and the theory of cosmic inflation. The second argument suggests resolution to the long-standing philosophical and logical mysteries associated with the anthropic principle, as well as the attendant use of Ockham’s razor as a logical tool. The problem of evidence and falsifiability is briefly implicated, as well as some consequences for apologetics.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44909888","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Body As an Object of Experimentation and the Emergence of Biomedicine Ethos 人体实验与生物医学伦理学的产生
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-03-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158114
O. Popova
The purpose of the article is to study the influence of Nazi experiments on the formation of ideas about the ethos of science in the field of biomedicine. It is shown that the idea of discrediting a value-neutral science was often confronted with the resistance of the scientists themselves, who, in different contexts of condemning Nazi crimes, appealed to the fact that they acted for the good of science, and even of all mankind. The article discusses the strategy of American lawyers adopted at the Nuremberg Trials aimed at demonstrating the perversity of Nazi crimes in the field of biomedicine both ethically and scientifically. In addition, an analysis of individual materials of the Nuremberg process was carried out, which made it possible to give an idea of the scientific and linguistic design of the human body (name correction strategy) as a “correct” scientific object with desired properties. The article considers the influence of the data obtained on Nazi crimes on the formation of the content of the Nuremberg Code and the design of the principle of informed consent in biomedicine. Ethical aspects related to the further use of Nazi scientific data are also considered. In conclusion, the problem of the formation of scientific knowledge in non-violence mode is articulated.
本文的目的是研究纳粹实验对生物医学领域科学精神观念形成的影响。研究表明,诋毁一门价值中立的科学的想法经常遭到科学家们自己的抵制,他们在谴责纳粹罪行的不同背景下,呼吁他们的行为是为了科学的利益,甚至是全人类的利益。本文论述了美国律师在纽伦堡审判中所采取的策略,旨在从伦理和科学上论证纳粹在生物医学领域的罪恶。此外,对纽伦堡工艺的单个材料进行了分析,这使得有可能将人体的科学和语言设计(名称纠正策略)作为具有所需属性的“正确”科学对象。本文考虑了所获得的关于纳粹罪行的数据对《纽伦堡法典》内容的形成和生物医学中知情同意原则的设计的影响。还审议了与进一步使用纳粹科学数据有关的伦理问题。最后,阐述了以非暴力方式形成科学知识的问题。
{"title":"Body As an Object of Experimentation and the Emergence of Biomedicine Ethos","authors":"O. Popova","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158114","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158114","url":null,"abstract":"The purpose of the article is to study the influence of Nazi experiments on the formation of ideas about the ethos of science in the field of biomedicine. It is shown that the idea of discrediting a value-neutral science was often confronted with the resistance of the scientists themselves, who, in different contexts of condemning Nazi crimes, appealed to the fact that they acted for the good of science, and even of all mankind. The article discusses the strategy of American lawyers adopted at the Nuremberg Trials aimed at demonstrating the perversity of Nazi crimes in the field of biomedicine both ethically and scientifically. In addition, an analysis of individual materials of the Nuremberg process was carried out, which made it possible to give an idea of the scientific and linguistic design of the human body (name correction strategy) as a “correct” scientific object with desired properties. The article considers the influence of the data obtained on Nazi crimes on the formation of the content of the Nuremberg Code and the design of the principle of informed consent in biomedicine. Ethical aspects related to the further use of Nazi scientific data are also considered. In conclusion, the problem of the formation of scientific knowledge in non-violence mode is articulated.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41778477","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What Is Formal Philosophy? 什么是形式哲学?
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-03-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158120
Vitaly V. Dolgorukov, Vera Shumilina
The paper focuses on the review of current literature on formal philosophy. Special attention is paid to the review of the book «Introduction to Formal Philosophy» [Hansson, Hendricks, 2018]. The book is a consistent introduction to the problems of formal philosophy, a research tradition that relies on the precise mathematical tools in order to study traditional philosophical problems. The methods of formal philosophy are successfully applied not only to the problems of ontology, epistemology and philosophy of language but also relevant for the problems of ethics, axiology and social philosophy. The book demonstrates that it is not correct to identify formal philosophy with another area of study – philosophical logic, since formal philosophy uses not only logical methods of analysis, but also uses the tools of game theory, decision theory, probability theory, Bayesian statistics, and other theories. Although the book has a propaedeutic character, it also contains some open problems. These problems include the aggregation of the opinions of the group under the condition of a conflicting base of premises in the theory of public choice, there are still open problems in the interpretation of Arrow’s impossibility theorem and others. Certainly, formalization in itself is not a general solution to the particular philosophical problem, but only a tool that allows to formulate a problem in a more rigorous and precise way, which sometimes allows to reveal some unexpected consequences, some implicit contradictions and new solutions. Despite the importance of the concept of coherence in ethics, decision theory, philosophy of law, Bayesian epistemology, philosophy of science, the existing formalizations of the concept of coherence are highly specialized for epistemology, researchers recognize the lack of the relevant explanatory models. Overall, the book is an excellent introduction in to the field of formal philosophy, which provides a general overview of different aspects of formal philosophy and the opportunity to study particular research topics by means of an extensive bibliography accompanying each of the chapters.
本文着重对形式哲学的现有文献进行了综述。特别关注《形式哲学导论》一书的评论[Hansson, Hendricks, 2018]。这本书是对形式哲学问题的一致介绍,这是一种依赖于精确的数学工具来研究传统哲学问题的研究传统。形式哲学的方法不仅成功地应用于本体论、认识论和语言哲学问题,而且也适用于伦理学、价值论和社会哲学问题。这本书表明,它是不正确的,以确定形式哲学与另一个领域的研究-哲学逻辑,因为形式哲学不仅使用分析的逻辑方法,而且还使用博弈论,决策理论,概率论,贝叶斯统计等理论的工具。这本书虽然有先见之明的特点,但也存在一些开放性的问题。这些问题包括公共选择理论中在前提基础冲突的情况下群体意见的聚集,阿罗不可能性定理的解释等仍存在的开放性问题。当然,形式化本身并不是特定哲学问题的一般解决方案,而只是一种工具,它允许以更严格和精确的方式制定问题,有时允许揭示一些意想不到的结果,一些隐含的矛盾和新的解决方案。尽管一致性概念在伦理学、决策理论、法律哲学、贝叶斯认识论、科学哲学中具有重要意义,但现有的一致性概念的形式化是高度专门化的认识论,研究人员认识到缺乏相关的解释模型。总的来说,这本书是对形式哲学领域的一个很好的介绍,它提供了形式哲学不同方面的总体概述,并通过每个章节附带的广泛参考书目来研究特定的研究课题。
{"title":"What Is Formal Philosophy?","authors":"Vitaly V. Dolgorukov, Vera Shumilina","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158120","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158120","url":null,"abstract":"The paper focuses on the review of current literature on formal philosophy. Special attention is paid to the review of the book «Introduction to Formal Philosophy» [Hansson, Hendricks, 2018]. The book is a consistent introduction to the problems of formal philosophy, a research tradition that relies on the precise mathematical tools in order to study traditional philosophical problems. The methods of formal philosophy are successfully applied not only to the problems of ontology, epistemology and philosophy of language but also relevant for the problems of ethics, axiology and social philosophy. The book demonstrates that it is not correct to identify formal philosophy with another area of study – philosophical logic, since formal philosophy uses not only logical methods of analysis, but also uses the tools of game theory, decision theory, probability theory, Bayesian statistics, and other theories. Although the book has a propaedeutic character, it also contains some open problems. These problems include the aggregation of the opinions of the group under the condition of a conflicting base of premises in the theory of public choice, there are still open problems in the interpretation of Arrow’s impossibility theorem and others. Certainly, formalization in itself is not a general solution to the particular philosophical problem, but only a tool that allows to formulate a problem in a more rigorous and precise way, which sometimes allows to reveal some unexpected consequences, some implicit contradictions and new solutions. Despite the importance of the concept of coherence in ethics, decision theory, philosophy of law, Bayesian epistemology, philosophy of science, the existing formalizations of the concept of coherence are highly specialized for epistemology, researchers recognize the lack of the relevant explanatory models. Overall, the book is an excellent introduction in to the field of formal philosophy, which provides a general overview of different aspects of formal philosophy and the opportunity to study particular research topics by means of an extensive bibliography accompanying each of the chapters.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45315073","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 49
Logical Positivism, Values, and Norms 逻辑实证主义、价值观与规范
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-03-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS20215816
V. Ogleznev
During its hundred-year history, Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus has undergone a variety of interpretations and explanations. But the significance of this work cannot be limited to an assessment of whether it had an impact on the development of logical positivism or not. Similarly, the reading of Tractatus cannot be reduced to just an ethical or some other readings. This article proposes to study a possible reading of “Tractatus” in terms of legal philosophy, which is based on the relation between facts, values and norms, as well as on how interesting it could be (or would be) for legal philosophy.
维特根斯坦的《逻辑哲学论》在其百年的历史中,经历了各种各样的诠释和解释。但这项工作的意义不能仅限于评估它是否对逻辑实证主义的发展产生了影响。同样,《论论》的解读也不能被简化为伦理解读或其他解读。本文拟从法哲学的角度研究《哲学论》的一种可能解读,这种解读是基于事实、价值和规范之间的关系,以及它对法哲学可能(或将会)有多大的吸引力。
{"title":"Logical Positivism, Values, and Norms","authors":"V. Ogleznev","doi":"10.5840/EPS20215816","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS20215816","url":null,"abstract":"During its hundred-year history, Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus has undergone a variety of interpretations and explanations. But the significance of this work cannot be limited to an assessment of whether it had an impact on the development of logical positivism or not. Similarly, the reading of Tractatus cannot be reduced to just an ethical or some other readings. This article proposes to study a possible reading of “Tractatus” in terms of legal philosophy, which is based on the relation between facts, values and norms, as well as on how interesting it could be (or would be) for legal philosophy.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41464186","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Group Belief 团体信念
IF 0.4 Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-03-01 DOI: 10.5840/EPS202158111
Domingos Faria
Beliefs are commonly attributed to groups or collective entities. But what is the nature of group belief? Summativism and nonsummativism are two main rival views regarding the nature of group belief. On the one hand, summativism holds that, necessarily, a group g has a belief B only if at least one individual i is both a member of g and has B. On the other hand, non-summativism holds that it is possible for a group g to have a belief B even if no member of g has B. My aim in this paper is to consider whether divergence arguments for non-summativism and against summativism about group belief are sound. Such divergence arguments aim to show that there can be a divergence between belief at the group level and the corresponding belief at the individual level. I will argue that these divergence arguments do not decisively defeat a minimal version of summativism. In order to accomplish this goal, I have the following plan: In section 2, I will analyze the structure of two important counterexamples against the summativist view, which are based on divergence arguments. Such counterexamples are based on the idea that a group decides to adopt a particular group belief, even if none of its members holds the belief in question. However, in section 3, I will show that these counterexamples fail, because they can be explained without the need to posit group beliefs. More specifically, I argue that in these apparent counterexamples, we have only a ‘group acceptance’ phenomenon and not a ‘group belief’ phenomenon. For this conclusion, I advance two arguments: in subsection 3.1, I formulate an argument from doxastic involuntarism, and in subsection 3.2, I develop an argument from truth connection. Thus, summativism is not defeated by divergence arguments. Lastly, in section 4, I will conclude with some advantages of summativism.
信仰通常归因于群体或集体实体。但是群体信仰的本质是什么呢?总结主义和非总结主义是关于群体信仰本质的两种主要对立观点。summativism认为,一方面,一群g的信念只有如果至少有一个人我是一个成员的g和B .另一方面,non-summativism认为,有可能一个g组信念B g B我即使没有成员本文目的是考虑是否分歧参数对non-summativism和summativism群体信仰的声音。这种分歧论点旨在表明,在群体层面的信念和相应的个人层面的信念之间可能存在分歧。我将论证,这些分歧论证并不能决定性地击败最小版本的总结主义。为了实现这一目标,我有以下计划:在第2节中,我将分析两个重要的反例的结构,反对总结主义的观点,这是基于分歧的论点。这些反例是基于这样一种观点,即一个群体决定采用一种特定的群体信仰,即使它的成员中没有人持有这种信仰。然而,在第3节中,我将说明这些反例是失败的,因为它们可以在不需要假定群体信念的情况下进行解释。更具体地说,我认为在这些明显的反例中,我们只有“群体接受”现象,而不是“群体信仰”现象。对于这个结论,我提出了两个论点:在第3.1节中,我从悖论不自主主义中提出了一个论点,在第3.2节中,我从真理联系中提出了一个论点。因此,总结论并没有被分歧论证打败。最后,在第4节中,我将总结总结主义的一些优点。
{"title":"Group Belief","authors":"Domingos Faria","doi":"10.5840/EPS202158111","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/EPS202158111","url":null,"abstract":"Beliefs are commonly attributed to groups or collective entities. But what is the nature of group belief? Summativism and nonsummativism are two main rival views regarding the nature of group belief. On the one hand, summativism holds that, necessarily, a group g has a belief B only if at least one individual i is both a member of g and has B. On the other hand, non-summativism holds that it is possible for a group g to have a belief B even if no member of g has B. My aim in this paper is to consider whether divergence arguments for non-summativism and against summativism about group belief are sound. Such divergence arguments aim to show that there can be a divergence between belief at the group level and the corresponding belief at the individual level. I will argue that these divergence arguments do not decisively defeat a minimal version of summativism. In order to accomplish this goal, I have the following plan: In section 2, I will analyze the structure of two important counterexamples against the summativist view, which are based on divergence arguments. Such counterexamples are based on the idea that a group decides to adopt a particular group belief, even if none of its members holds the belief in question. However, in section 3, I will show that these counterexamples fail, because they can be explained without the need to posit group beliefs. More specifically, I argue that in these apparent counterexamples, we have only a ‘group acceptance’ phenomenon and not a ‘group belief’ phenomenon. For this conclusion, I advance two arguments: in subsection 3.1, I formulate an argument from doxastic involuntarism, and in subsection 3.2, I develop an argument from truth connection. Thus, summativism is not defeated by divergence arguments. Lastly, in section 4, I will conclude with some advantages of summativism.","PeriodicalId":44031,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43071247","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
Epistemology & Philosophy of Science-Epistemologiya i Filosofiya Nauki
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1