首页 > 最新文献

University of Toronto Law Journal最新文献

英文 中文
Rethinking the Division of Tax Room And Revenue in Fiscal Federalism 对财政联邦制中分税室与分税收入的再思考
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-05-03 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.4011369
R. Gillis
The division of tax room for shared tax bases, such as income taxes in Canada, the United States, Australia, and Switzerland, is a frequent cause of political conflict between national and sub-national governments. Economists and legal scholars have developed a theory that sets out an optimal division of tax room, but federal nations often substantially depart from this prescription by allocating too much or too little tax room to national governments. This article argues that the divergence between theory and actual practice can be partially explained by a ‘credit assignment problem’ that affects the political economy of government decision making. To illustrate, the article develops a model to identify the incentives governments face when dividing tax room. The model’s central observations are that (a) the optimal division of tax room requires robust intergovernmental contracting, but (b) the necessary contracts are difficult or impossible to perform due to problems in allocating political credit – electoral rewards and punishments – between the two levels of government. The result is political conflict and, frequently, a sub-optimal division of tax room and the revenue that results. This article argues that law can perform two functions in responding to the credit assignment problem: (a) it can facilitate credit assignment, so that the necessary contracts over tax room and revenue are politically feasible, and (b), failing perfect credit assignment, it can mitigate the welfare effects of a sub-optimal division of tax room. The article shows how a credit assignment perspective should lead to reconsideration of constitutional law doctrines, such as the federal spending power and various doctrines that enable or limit concurrent expenditure jurisdiction. While these doctrines are the subject of long-running debates in legal scholarship, the credit assignment perspective offers new insights and new doctrinal prescriptions.
共享税基(如加拿大、美国、澳大利亚和瑞士的所得税)的税收空间划分是国家和地方政府之间政治冲突的常见原因。经济学家和法律学者已经发展出一种理论,提出了税收空间的最佳划分,但联邦国家往往会通过向国家政府分配过多或过少的税收空间来大大偏离这一规定。本文认为,理论与实际之间的分歧可以部分解释为影响政府决策政治经济学的“信贷分配问题”。为了说明这一点,本文建立了一个模型来识别政府在划分税收空间时面临的激励。该模型的核心观察结果是:(a)税收空间的最佳划分需要强有力的政府间合同,但(b)由于两级政府之间政治信用(选举奖惩)的分配问题,必要的合同很难或不可能履行。其结果是政治冲突,而且往往是税收空间和收入的次优划分。本文认为,法律在应对信用分配问题时可以发挥两种作用:(a)它可以促进信用分配,使税收空间和收入的必要合同在政治上可行;(b)如果信用分配不完善,它可以减轻次优税收空间划分的福利效应。这篇文章展示了信贷分配的观点应该如何导致对宪法学说的重新考虑,例如联邦支出权和允许或限制并行支出管辖权的各种学说。虽然这些学说是法律学术界长期争论的主题,但学分分配视角提供了新的见解和新的学说处方。
{"title":"Rethinking the Division of Tax Room And Revenue in Fiscal Federalism","authors":"R. Gillis","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.4011369","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.4011369","url":null,"abstract":"The division of tax room for shared tax bases, such as income taxes in Canada, the United States, Australia, and Switzerland, is a frequent cause of political conflict between national and sub-national governments. Economists and legal scholars have developed a theory that sets out an optimal division of tax room, but federal nations often substantially depart from this prescription by allocating too much or too little tax room to national governments. This article argues that the divergence between theory and actual practice can be partially explained by a ‘credit assignment problem’ that affects the political economy of government decision making. To illustrate, the article develops a model to identify the incentives governments face when dividing tax room. The model’s central observations are that (a) the optimal division of tax room requires robust intergovernmental contracting, but (b) the necessary contracts are difficult or impossible to perform due to problems in allocating political credit – electoral rewards and punishments – between the two levels of government. The result is political conflict and, frequently, a sub-optimal division of tax room and the revenue that results. This article argues that law can perform two functions in responding to the credit assignment problem: (a) it can facilitate credit assignment, so that the necessary contracts over tax room and revenue are politically feasible, and (b), failing perfect credit assignment, it can mitigate the welfare effects of a sub-optimal division of tax room. The article shows how a credit assignment perspective should lead to reconsideration of constitutional law doctrines, such as the federal spending power and various doctrines that enable or limit concurrent expenditure jurisdiction. While these doctrines are the subject of long-running debates in legal scholarship, the credit assignment perspective offers new insights and new doctrinal prescriptions.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":" ","pages":"-"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-05-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48167122","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Frontiers Of Legality: Understanding The Public Policy Exception In Choice Of Law 法律的前沿:法律选择中的公共政策例外
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-04-12 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0085
Joanna Langille
The public policy exception is a notorious part of choice of law doctrine. The exception allows courts to refuse to apply foreign law selected by first-order choice of law rules that violates the forum’s fundamental principles of morality and justice. As a doctrinal matter, public policy is a well-established part of the architecture of choice of law. But scholars have struggled to understand why it should be part of choice of law doctrine, given the normative structure of the field; how to differentiate between the fundamental and non-fundamental norms that inform its use; and how to understand the leading public policy cases in a coherent way. In this Article, I offer a solution to these three problems. I argue we should reconceptualize the exception as a means by which courts can analyze the substance of foreign law to ensure that it complies with the rule of law, and thus can be applied ‘as a law’ in the forum. More specifically, public policy is how common law courts ensure that any foreign law they apply complies with the distinctive substantive requirements of the rule of law in the common law tradition – what is known as the common law constitution. Public policy thus defines the frontiers of legality in the common law tradition, and defends against threats from the rule of law that come from beyond the border. This approach justifies the inclusion of the exception in choice of law doctrine, given the field’s other normative commitments. It can also help distinguish between the fundamental and non-fundamental norms that should define the ambit of public policy. Finally, this approach may offer a coherent account of the doctrine, as numerous leading cases can be reinterpreted to track the fundamental principles of legality that inhere in the common law constitution.
公共政策例外是法律选择学说中臭名昭著的一部分。这一例外情况允许法院拒绝适用由违反法院地道德和正义基本原则的一级法律选择规则选择的外国法律。作为一个理论问题,公共政策是法律选择体系中一个公认的组成部分。但鉴于该领域的规范结构,学者们一直难以理解为什么它应该成为法律选择学说的一部分;如何区分为其使用提供信息的基本规范和非基本规范;以及如何连贯地理解主要的公共政策案例。在这篇文章中,我提出了这三个问题的解决方案。我认为,我们应该将例外重新定义为一种手段,法院可以通过这种手段分析外国法律的实质,以确保其符合法治,从而可以在法院地“作为法律”适用。更具体地说,公共政策是普通法法院如何确保其适用的任何外国法律符合普通法传统中法治的独特实质要求,即所谓的普通法宪法。因此,公共政策在普通法传统中界定了合法性的边界,并防范来自边界之外的法治威胁。考虑到该领域的其他规范性承诺,这种方法证明将例外情况纳入法律选择学说是合理的。它还可以帮助区分应该界定公共政策范围的基本规范和非基本规范。最后,这种方法可以对该学说进行连贯的解释,因为可以重新解释许多主要案例,以追踪普通法宪法中固有的合法性基本原则。
{"title":"Frontiers Of Legality: Understanding The Public Policy Exception In Choice Of Law","authors":"Joanna Langille","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0085","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0085","url":null,"abstract":"The public policy exception is a notorious part of choice of law doctrine. The exception allows courts to refuse to apply foreign law selected by first-order choice of law rules that violates the forum’s fundamental principles of morality and justice. As a doctrinal matter, public policy is a well-established part of the architecture of choice of law. But scholars have struggled to understand why it should be part of choice of law doctrine, given the normative structure of the field; how to differentiate between the fundamental and non-fundamental norms that inform its use; and how to understand the leading public policy cases in a coherent way. In this Article, I offer a solution to these three problems. I argue we should reconceptualize the exception as a means by which courts can analyze the substance of foreign law to ensure that it complies with the rule of law, and thus can be applied ‘as a law’ in the forum. More specifically, public policy is how common law courts ensure that any foreign law they apply complies with the distinctive substantive requirements of the rule of law in the common law tradition – what is known as the common law constitution. Public policy thus defines the frontiers of legality in the common law tradition, and defends against threats from the rule of law that come from beyond the border. This approach justifies the inclusion of the exception in choice of law doctrine, given the field’s other normative commitments. It can also help distinguish between the fundamental and non-fundamental norms that should define the ambit of public policy. Finally, this approach may offer a coherent account of the doctrine, as numerous leading cases can be reinterpreted to track the fundamental principles of legality that inhere in the common law constitution.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":" ","pages":"-"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-04-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46407084","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Of linchpins and bedrock: Hope, despair, and pragmatism in animal law 关键和基石:动物法中的希望、绝望和实用主义
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-03-16 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0127
Jessica Eisen
Abstract:The field of animal law is ubiquitously characterized as being split between proponents of ‘animal rights’ and ‘animal welfare.’ While rights advocates seek to end the legal classification of animals as ‘property’ (or pursue the related goal of establishing animals as legal ‘persons’), welfarists aim to improve animal lives within the property paradigm. The common wisdom that all legal approaches to animals are fundamentally split between rights and welfarism has worked to ossify categories of analysis and prevent more accurate and productive accounts of what truly divides and unites theorists within this increasingly diverse field. In place of this traditional assumption that one must be simply ‘for’ or ‘against’ the abolition of property status, I propose an alternative pair of axes around which we might more productively organize existing and future approaches to animal law. First, what do these various approaches take to be the linchpin of animals’ exploitation – the thing that, though central to the system, is changeable, such that, if changed, the whole system might change with it? Second, what do these approaches take to constitute the unchangeable bedrock of existing systems of animal exploitation – things that reform efforts must take as inevitable, for better or for worse? Changing our lens to focus on bedrock and linchpins invites more nuanced debate respecting the unique constellations of hope, despair, and pragmatism that in fact animate so much animal law scholarship. In a field characterized by transformative ambitions, the proposed analysis of linchpins and bedrock focuses our attention on differing accounts of change – what must change and what cannot.
摘要:动物法领域普遍被描述为“动物权利”和“动物福利”的支持者之间的分歧虽然权利倡导者寻求结束动物作为“财产”的法律分类(或追求将动物确立为法人的相关目标),但福利主义者的目标是在财产范式下改善动物的生活。人们普遍认为,所有对待动物的法律方法都从根本上分为权利和福利主义,这一观点使分析的类别变得僵化,并阻止了对在这个日益多样化的领域中真正分裂和团结理论家的更准确和更具成效的解释。我提出了一对替代轴心,我们可以围绕这对轴心更有效地组织现有和未来的动物法方法,以取代人们必须简单地“支持”或“反对”废除财产地位的传统假设。首先,这些不同的方法是如何成为动物剥削的关键——尽管动物剥削是系统的核心,但它是可变的,因此,如果改变,整个系统可能会随之改变?其次,这些方法是如何构成现有动物剥削制度不可改变的基石的——无论是好是坏,改革努力都必须将其视为不可避免的事情?改变我们的视角,关注基石和关键,会引发更微妙的辩论,尊重希望、绝望和实用主义的独特星座,这些星座实际上激发了如此多的动物法学术。在一个以变革雄心为特征的领域,拟议的关键和基石分析将我们的注意力集中在对变革的不同解释上——什么必须改变,什么不能改变。
{"title":"Of linchpins and bedrock: Hope, despair, and pragmatism in animal law","authors":"Jessica Eisen","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0127","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0127","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:The field of animal law is ubiquitously characterized as being split between proponents of ‘animal rights’ and ‘animal welfare.’ While rights advocates seek to end the legal classification of animals as ‘property’ (or pursue the related goal of establishing animals as legal ‘persons’), welfarists aim to improve animal lives within the property paradigm. The common wisdom that all legal approaches to animals are fundamentally split between rights and welfarism has worked to ossify categories of analysis and prevent more accurate and productive accounts of what truly divides and unites theorists within this increasingly diverse field. In place of this traditional assumption that one must be simply ‘for’ or ‘against’ the abolition of property status, I propose an alternative pair of axes around which we might more productively organize existing and future approaches to animal law. First, what do these various approaches take to be the linchpin of animals’ exploitation – the thing that, though central to the system, is changeable, such that, if changed, the whole system might change with it? Second, what do these approaches take to constitute the unchangeable bedrock of existing systems of animal exploitation – things that reform efforts must take as inevitable, for better or for worse? Changing our lens to focus on bedrock and linchpins invites more nuanced debate respecting the unique constellations of hope, despair, and pragmatism that in fact animate so much animal law scholarship. In a field characterized by transformative ambitions, the proposed analysis of linchpins and bedrock focuses our attention on differing accounts of change – what must change and what cannot.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"72 1","pages":"468 - 490"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-03-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45394238","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Flexibility, Choice, And Labour Law: The Challenge Of On-demand Platforms 灵活性、选择和劳动法:按需平台的挑战
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-03-16 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0113
Tammy Katsabian, G. Davidov
Working through platforms is a recent but fast-growing phenomenon, with obvious implications for workers’ rights. Discussions have so far focused on the status of platform-based workers, but, recently, a growing consensus is emerging by courts around the world that workers for platforms such as Uber are in fact employees. As a result, legal disputes are likely to shift, to a large extent, from status questions to working-time questions. This might seem like a very specific issue, but, in fact, it has crucial implications for the entire model of platform work, and addressing this question requires us to rethink some of the fundamental pillars of labour law, notably whether more room should be opened for flexibility and individual choice within this system. We argue that one aspect of the platform model – ‘work on demand,’ which allows workers to log into the app whenever they wish to do so – poses a difficulty. Workers should be compensated for the time they are ‘on call’ and available to work. But platforms can be expected to respond by assigning workers to pre-set shifts to avoid paying for an unknown amount of working hours, thereby dismantling the ‘on-demand’ model. Such a change would be welcomed by many employees, who will gain more security, but others can be expected to object to losing the flexibility which they value. We consider possible solutions that could allow workers to choose the ‘on-demand’ model. While rejecting the possibility of allowing employees to waive on-call compensation rights, we consider several intermediate solutions that ensure partial payments for this time or exempt employees with another full-time job. The proposed solutions are based on the understanding that more choice is preferable in labour law as long as we can protect the interests of the affected employees and eliminate the externalities that some choices might generate for other workers.
通过平台工作是最近出现的一种快速增长的现象,对工人的权利有着明显的影响。到目前为止,讨论的重点是基于平台的员工的地位,但最近,世界各地的法院越来越一致认为,优步等平台的员工实际上是员工。因此,法律纠纷可能在很大程度上从身份问题转移到工作时间问题。这似乎是一个非常具体的问题,但事实上,它对整个平台工作模式有着至关重要的影响,解决这个问题需要我们重新思考劳动法的一些基本支柱,特别是是否应该在这个体系中为灵活性和个人选择开辟更多的空间。我们认为,平台模式的一个方面——“按需工作”,允许员工随时登录应用程序——带来了困难。工人在“随叫随到”和可以工作的时间应该得到补偿。但平台可以通过将员工分配到预先设定的轮班来做出回应,以避免支付未知的工作时间,从而废除“按需”模式。这样的改变会受到许多员工的欢迎,他们将获得更多的安全感,但其他人可能会反对失去他们所珍视的灵活性。我们考虑可能的解决方案,允许员工选择“按需”模式。在拒绝允许员工放弃随叫随到的薪酬权利的可能性的同时,我们考虑了几种中间解决方案,以确保这段时间的部分付款,或免除另一份全职工作的员工。所提出的解决方案是基于这样一种理解,即只要我们能够保护受影响员工的利益,并消除某些选择可能给其他工人带来的外部性,在劳动法中,更多的选择是可取的。
{"title":"Flexibility, Choice, And Labour Law: The Challenge Of On-demand Platforms","authors":"Tammy Katsabian, G. Davidov","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0113","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0113","url":null,"abstract":"Working through platforms is a recent but fast-growing phenomenon, with obvious implications for workers’ rights. Discussions have so far focused on the status of platform-based workers, but, recently, a growing consensus is emerging by courts around the world that workers for platforms such as Uber are in fact employees. As a result, legal disputes are likely to shift, to a large extent, from status questions to working-time questions. This might seem like a very specific issue, but, in fact, it has crucial implications for the entire model of platform work, and addressing this question requires us to rethink some of the fundamental pillars of labour law, notably whether more room should be opened for flexibility and individual choice within this system. We argue that one aspect of the platform model – ‘work on demand,’ which allows workers to log into the app whenever they wish to do so – poses a difficulty. Workers should be compensated for the time they are ‘on call’ and available to work. But platforms can be expected to respond by assigning workers to pre-set shifts to avoid paying for an unknown amount of working hours, thereby dismantling the ‘on-demand’ model. Such a change would be welcomed by many employees, who will gain more security, but others can be expected to object to losing the flexibility which they value. We consider possible solutions that could allow workers to choose the ‘on-demand’ model. While rejecting the possibility of allowing employees to waive on-call compensation rights, we consider several intermediate solutions that ensure partial payments for this time or exempt employees with another full-time job. The proposed solutions are based on the understanding that more choice is preferable in labour law as long as we can protect the interests of the affected employees and eliminate the externalities that some choices might generate for other workers.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":" ","pages":"-"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-03-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48312581","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Reinvention of Canadian Tort Law, 1945–5: Jordan House as a Case Study 加拿大侵权法的再创新,1945-5:约旦之家案例研究
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-03-09 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0096
R. Kostal, E. Chamberlain
This article employs the case study method to investigate the social history of Canadian tort law and litigation after 1945. Its focus is Menow v Jordan House, the stem precedent of the Canadian common law of tavern-keeper liability for intoxicated patrons. The article examines the historical genesis, pleading, and adjudication of this litigation, probing why – in Canada in the late 1960s and early 1970s – the novel tort claim of an ejected intoxicant against a vendor of alcohol not only was imagined, discussed, and commenced but also was won by the plaintiff at three levels of court. The authors argue that the Jordan House lawsuit exemplified a pivotal moment of socio-legal discontinuity in Canada, portending a quarter century of change in three major facets of its tort law system: in the perceptions of lay persons with respect to their private legal rights and obligations; in the personal convictions, social geography, and litigation strategies of Canadian lawyers; and in the formulation of tort doctrine by Canada’s trial and appellate judges. The article is a sub-study of a larger project on the reinvention of tort law and litigation in Canada in the half-century after World War II.
本文采用案例研究的方法,对1945年以后加拿大侵权法和诉讼的社会历史进行了考察。它的焦点是Menow诉Jordan House案,这是加拿大普通法中酒馆老板对醉酒顾客承担责任的先例。这篇文章探讨了这起诉讼的历史起源、辩护和裁决,探讨了为什么在20世纪60年代末和70年代初的加拿大,一种被驱逐的麻醉剂对一名酒贩的新型侵权索赔不仅是想象、讨论和开始的,而且是原告在三级法院赢得的。提交人认为,约旦之家的诉讼体现了加拿大社会法律不连续的关键时刻,预示着其侵权法体系的三个主要方面将发生四分之一个世纪的变化:非专业人员对其私人法律权利和义务的看法;加拿大律师的个人信念、社会地理和诉讼策略;以及加拿大审判法官和上诉法官制定侵权行为学说。这篇文章是关于二战后半个世纪加拿大侵权法和诉讼重塑的一个更大项目的子研究。
{"title":"The Reinvention of Canadian Tort Law, 1945–5: Jordan House as a Case Study","authors":"R. Kostal, E. Chamberlain","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0096","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0096","url":null,"abstract":"This article employs the case study method to investigate the social history of Canadian tort law and litigation after 1945. Its focus is Menow v Jordan House, the stem precedent of the Canadian common law of tavern-keeper liability for intoxicated patrons. The article examines the historical genesis, pleading, and adjudication of this litigation, probing why – in Canada in the late 1960s and early 1970s – the novel tort claim of an ejected intoxicant against a vendor of alcohol not only was imagined, discussed, and commenced but also was won by the plaintiff at three levels of court. The authors argue that the Jordan House lawsuit exemplified a pivotal moment of socio-legal discontinuity in Canada, portending a quarter century of change in three major facets of its tort law system: in the perceptions of lay persons with respect to their private legal rights and obligations; in the personal convictions, social geography, and litigation strategies of Canadian lawyers; and in the formulation of tort doctrine by Canada’s trial and appellate judges. The article is a sub-study of a larger project on the reinvention of tort law and litigation in Canada in the half-century after World War II.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":" ","pages":"-"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-03-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43493972","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Chronotopes of Security Legal Regimes 证券法律制度的时代性
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-02-01 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0038
Irit Ballas
Legal regimes dealing with security have prominent temporal attributes: they are often intended to operate for a specified period of time in response to an imminent danger and allow governments to employ extraordinary measures enabling them to act faster when faced with time-critical scenarios. Such regimes also have prominent spatial attributes: they often protect a physical border, delineate spaces with extra-legal status, or use surveillance measures such as cameras or patrols for monitoring designated areas. Based on the analysis of one security regime that was imposed on the Palestinian minority in Israel between 1948 and 1966, I argue in this article that such spatial and temporal attributes affect each other and that different legal measures associated with security can be characterized by the specific time/space configuration – or chronotope – embedded in them. In Israel, a military regime was imposed on specific areas to foil the movement of its subjects and thereby further its territorial objectives. The procedures that the regime employed were therefore designed to monitor and control individuals’ whereabouts. Each of these seemingly spatial attributes, however, gained its particular function and meaning from a specific interaction with temporal attributes. The prism of the chronotope illuminates how security legal measures generate distinct modes of governance and produce different boundaries to the political community, in a way that a one-dimensional analysis fails to capture.
处理安全问题的法律制度具有突出的时间属性:它们通常旨在在一段特定的时间内运行,以应对迫在眉睫的危险,并允许政府采取非常措施,使它们能够在面临时间紧迫的情况时更快地采取行动。这些制度还具有突出的空间属性:它们通常保护物理边界,划定具有法外地位的空间,或使用诸如摄像机或巡逻等监视措施来监视指定区域。根据对1948年至1966年期间对以色列巴勒斯坦少数民族实行的一项安全制度的分析,我在本文中认为,这些空间和时间属性相互影响,与安全有关的不同法律措施可以根据其中嵌入的具体时间/空间配置或时间表来表征。在以色列,在特定地区实行军事政权,以阻挠其臣民的行动,从而促进其领土目标。因此,该政权所采用的程序旨在监测和控制个人的行踪。然而,每一个看似空间的属性都是通过与时间属性的特定互动而获得其特定的功能和意义。计时器的棱镜阐明了安全法律措施如何产生不同的治理模式,并以一维分析无法捕捉的方式为政治社区产生不同的边界。
{"title":"Chronotopes of Security Legal Regimes","authors":"Irit Ballas","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0038","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0038","url":null,"abstract":"Legal regimes dealing with security have prominent temporal attributes: they are often intended to operate for a specified period of time in response to an imminent danger and allow governments to employ extraordinary measures enabling them to act faster when faced with time-critical scenarios. Such regimes also have prominent spatial attributes: they often protect a physical border, delineate spaces with extra-legal status, or use surveillance measures such as cameras or patrols for monitoring designated areas. Based on the analysis of one security regime that was imposed on the Palestinian minority in Israel between 1948 and 1966, I argue in this article that such spatial and temporal attributes affect each other and that different legal measures associated with security can be characterized by the specific time/space configuration – or chronotope – embedded in them. In Israel, a military regime was imposed on specific areas to foil the movement of its subjects and thereby further its territorial objectives. The procedures that the regime employed were therefore designed to monitor and control individuals’ whereabouts. Each of these seemingly spatial attributes, however, gained its particular function and meaning from a specific interaction with temporal attributes. The prism of the chronotope illuminates how security legal measures generate distinct modes of governance and produce different boundaries to the political community, in a way that a one-dimensional analysis fails to capture.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":" ","pages":"-"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43276622","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Discrimination and the value of lived experience in Sophia Moreau’s Faces of Inequality 索菲亚·莫罗《不平等的面孔》中的歧视与生活经验的价值
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-01-19 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0086
Erin Beeghly
In Faces of Inequality: A Theory of Wrongful Discrimination, Sophia Moreau embarks on a classic philosophical journey. It is what philosophers nowadays call an explanatory project. The goal of explanatory projects is to deepen our understanding of wrongful actions and what they share in common. In this review essay, I argue that Moreau’s book embodies a valuable explanatory project that ought to be on the radar of lawyers, legal theorists, and philosophers. After sketching the book’s arguments, I explain why they are so refreshing. The remainder of the review essay proceeds in a more critical mode. First, I argue that the book’s explanatory aspirations fall short, and I sketch a framework for a more radically pluralistic theory of wrongful discrimination. This framework has the power to embrace Moreau’s compelling view that discrimination wrongs people by failing to treat them as equals while also recognizing a rich array of other discriminatory wrongs found in lived experience. Second, I argue that Faces of Inequality will disappoint readers looking for a truly inclusive account of wrongful discrimination. I end by emphasizing the book’s contribution to political philosophy and its ambition to provide a truly liberatory theory of what we owe to each other as moral and political equals.
在《面对不平等:一种错误歧视理论》一书中,索菲亚·莫罗开启了一段经典的哲学之旅。这就是当今哲学家所说的解释性工程。解释性项目的目标是加深我们对错误行为及其共同之处的理解。在这篇评论文章中,我认为莫罗的书体现了一个有价值的解释性项目,应该引起律师、法律理论家和哲学家的注意。在概述了这本书的论点之后,我解释了为什么它们如此令人耳目一新。评论文章的其余部分以更批判性的方式进行。首先,我认为这本书的解释愿望不够,我为一个更激进的多元化的错误歧视理论勾勒了一个框架。这个框架有能力接受莫罗令人信服的观点,即歧视是错误的,因为他们没有平等对待他们,同时也认识到生活经验中发现的大量其他歧视性错误。其次,我认为《不平等的面孔》会让那些希望看到关于不公平歧视的真正包容性描述的读者失望。最后,我强调了这本书对政治哲学的贡献,以及它提供了一种真正的解放理论的雄心,即我们作为道德和政治平等者对彼此的亏欠。
{"title":"Discrimination and the value of lived experience in Sophia Moreau’s Faces of Inequality","authors":"Erin Beeghly","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0086","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0086","url":null,"abstract":"In Faces of Inequality: A Theory of Wrongful Discrimination, Sophia Moreau embarks on a classic philosophical journey. It is what philosophers nowadays call an explanatory project. The goal of explanatory projects is to deepen our understanding of wrongful actions and what they share in common. In this review essay, I argue that Moreau’s book embodies a valuable explanatory project that ought to be on the radar of lawyers, legal theorists, and philosophers. After sketching the book’s arguments, I explain why they are so refreshing. The remainder of the review essay proceeds in a more critical mode. First, I argue that the book’s explanatory aspirations fall short, and I sketch a framework for a more radically pluralistic theory of wrongful discrimination. This framework has the power to embrace Moreau’s compelling view that discrimination wrongs people by failing to treat them as equals while also recognizing a rich array of other discriminatory wrongs found in lived experience. Second, I argue that Faces of Inequality will disappoint readers looking for a truly inclusive account of wrongful discrimination. I end by emphasizing the book’s contribution to political philosophy and its ambition to provide a truly liberatory theory of what we owe to each other as moral and political equals.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"5 3-4","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-01-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138519867","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Farewell to the F-Word? Fragmentation of International law in times of the Covid-19 pandemic 告别脏话?2019冠状病毒病大流行时期国际法的碎片化
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-01-07 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3932220
S. Agon
Abstract:The proliferation of international legal regimes, norms, and institutions in the post-Cold War era, known as the ‘fragmentation’ of international law, has sparked extensive debate among jurists. This debate has evolved as a dialectical process, seeing legal scholarship shifting from grave concern about fragmentation’s potentially negative impacts on the international legal order to a more optimistic view of the phenomenon, with recent literature suggesting that the tools needed to contain fragmentation’s ill-effects are today all at hand, thus arguing that the time has come ‘to bid farewell to the f-word.’ Drawing on the COVID-19 crisis as a test case and considering the unresolved problems in existing fragmentation literature that this crisis brings to the fore, this article asks whether such calls have perhaps been premature. Existing works on fragmentation, the article submits, including those bidding farewell to the f-word, have mainly focused on the problems of conflicts between international norms or international institutions, especially conflicts between international courts over competing jurisdictions and interpretations of law. But, as the COVID-19 case – and, particularly, the deficient cooperation marked between the numerous international organizations reacting to the crisis – shows, the fragmentation of the international legal order does not only give rise to the potential consequences of conflicts of norms and clashes between international courts. Fragmentation also gives rise to pressing challenges of coordination when a proactive and cohesive international response is required to address global problems like COVID-19, which cut across multiple international organizations playing critical roles in the creation, administration, and application of international law. By foregrounding cooperation between international organizations as a vital-yet-deficient form of governance under conditions of fragmentation, the article argues, the COVID-19 crisis not only denotes that the time is not yet ripe to bid farewell to the f-word. It further points to the need to expand the fragmentation debate, going beyond its conflict- and court-centred focus, while probing new tools for tackling unsettled problems that arise from the segmentation of international law along sectoral lines.
摘要:后冷战时期国际法律制度、规范和机构的扩散,被称为国际法的“碎片化”,引发了法学家们的广泛争论。这场辩论已经演变为一个辩证的过程,看到法律学者从对碎片化对国际法律秩序的潜在负面影响的严重担忧转变为对这一现象的更乐观的看法,最近的文献表明,遏制碎片化不良影响所需的工具今天都在手边,因此认为是时候告别“f”这个词了。以2019冠状病毒病危机为例,并考虑到这场危机所带来的现有碎片化文献中尚未解决的问题,本文提出这样的呼吁是否为时过早。文章认为,现有的关于碎片化的著作,包括那些告别f字的著作,主要集中在国际规范或国际机构之间的冲突问题,特别是国际法院之间在相互竞争的管辖权和法律解释方面的冲突。但是,正如2019冠状病毒病案例,特别是众多国际组织在应对危机时缺乏合作所表明的那样,国际法律秩序的碎片化不仅会导致规范冲突和国际法院之间冲突的潜在后果。在应对COVID-19等全球性问题时,需要采取积极和有凝聚力的国际应对措施,而这些问题涉及在国际法的制定、管理和适用方面发挥关键作用的多个国际组织,碎片化也带来了紧迫的协调挑战。文章认为,通过将国际组织之间的合作作为碎片化条件下至关重要但存在缺陷的治理形式,COVID-19危机不仅表明告别f-word的时机尚未成熟。它进一步指出有必要扩大分割辩论,超越以冲突和法院为中心的焦点,同时探索新的工具,以解决因国际法按部门划分而产生的未解决问题。
{"title":"Farewell to the F-Word? Fragmentation of International law in times of the Covid-19 pandemic","authors":"S. Agon","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3932220","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3932220","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:The proliferation of international legal regimes, norms, and institutions in the post-Cold War era, known as the ‘fragmentation’ of international law, has sparked extensive debate among jurists. This debate has evolved as a dialectical process, seeing legal scholarship shifting from grave concern about fragmentation’s potentially negative impacts on the international legal order to a more optimistic view of the phenomenon, with recent literature suggesting that the tools needed to contain fragmentation’s ill-effects are today all at hand, thus arguing that the time has come ‘to bid farewell to the f-word.’ Drawing on the COVID-19 crisis as a test case and considering the unresolved problems in existing fragmentation literature that this crisis brings to the fore, this article asks whether such calls have perhaps been premature. Existing works on fragmentation, the article submits, including those bidding farewell to the f-word, have mainly focused on the problems of conflicts between international norms or international institutions, especially conflicts between international courts over competing jurisdictions and interpretations of law. But, as the COVID-19 case – and, particularly, the deficient cooperation marked between the numerous international organizations reacting to the crisis – shows, the fragmentation of the international legal order does not only give rise to the potential consequences of conflicts of norms and clashes between international courts. Fragmentation also gives rise to pressing challenges of coordination when a proactive and cohesive international response is required to address global problems like COVID-19, which cut across multiple international organizations playing critical roles in the creation, administration, and application of international law. By foregrounding cooperation between international organizations as a vital-yet-deficient form of governance under conditions of fragmentation, the article argues, the COVID-19 crisis not only denotes that the time is not yet ripe to bid farewell to the f-word. It further points to the need to expand the fragmentation debate, going beyond its conflict- and court-centred focus, while probing new tools for tackling unsettled problems that arise from the segmentation of international law along sectoral lines.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"29 1","pages":"1 - 49"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-01-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83743292","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
‘Within Or Outside Canada’: The Charter’s Application To The Extraterritorial Activities Of The Canadian Security Intelligence Service “加拿大境内或境外”:《宪章》对加拿大安全情报局域外活动的适用
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2022-01-05 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0105
Leah West
Since the swift passage of the Anti-Terrorism Act in 2015, the Canadian Security Intelligence Service (CSIS) has had the unprecedented and highly controversial authority to take ‘reasonable and proportionate’ measures to reduce threats to Canadian security. While there are some limits to the types of measures CSIS can employ, the Canadian Security Intelligence Service Act permits the use of measures that would otherwise contravene the laws of Canada or limit a right protected by the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms so long as they are judicially authorized by the Federal Court. As new threats proliferate around the world, it is anticipated that CSIS will increasingly carry out this mandate overseas. Yet review bodies tasked with monitoring CSIS’s use of threat reduction measures (TRMs) report that CSIS has never sought judicial authorization to conduct a TRM. Why? One answer may be that CSIS has concluded that the Charter does not govern actions carried out abroad, and, as such, their extraterritorial conduct falls beyond the reach and oversight of the Federal Court. Whether the Charter applies to CSIS’s overseas conduct ostensibly lies in the Supreme Court of Canada’s leading case on the extraterritorial application of the Charter, R. v Hape. This article canvasses domestic and international law, as well as intelligence law theory, to explain why that presumption is wrong. Wrong, not least because the majority opinion in Hape is deeply flawed in its analysis and application of international law. But also, because intelligence operations are so distinguishable from the transnational criminal investigations at issue in Hape, the Court’s findings are inapplicable in the former context. In short, this article demonstrates that applying Hape to the actions of CSIS officers not only leaves their actions beyond the scrutiny of Canadian courts but also creates a significant human rights gap.
自2015年《反恐怖主义法》迅速通过以来,加拿大安全情报局(CSIS)拥有前所未有且极具争议的权力,可以采取“合理和相称”的措施来减少对加拿大安全的威胁。虽然加拿大安全情报局可以采取的措施类型有一些限制,但《加拿大安全情报机构法》允许使用违反加拿大法律或限制《加拿大权利与自由宪章》保护的权利的措施,只要这些措施得到联邦法院的司法授权。随着新的威胁在世界各地激增,预计CSIS将越来越多地在海外执行这一任务。然而,负责监督CSIS使用减少威胁措施的审查机构报告称,CSIS从未寻求司法授权进行减少威胁措施。为什么?一个答案可能是,CSIS得出的结论是,《宪章》不管辖在国外进行的行动,因此,他们的域外行为超出了联邦法院的管辖范围和监督范围。《宪章》是否适用于加拿大战略情报局的海外行为,表面上取决于加拿大最高法院关于《宪章》域外适用的主要案件R.v Hape。本文对国内法、国际法以及情报法理论进行了研究,以解释为什么这种推定是错误的。这是错误的,尤其是因为大多数人对Hape的意见在分析和适用国际法方面存在严重缺陷。但同时,由于情报行动与哈佩有争议的跨国刑事调查截然不同,法院的调查结果不适用于前者。简言之,这篇文章表明,将Hape应用于CSIS官员的行为不仅使他们的行为超出了加拿大法院的审查范围,而且还造成了严重的人权差距。
{"title":"‘Within Or Outside Canada’: The Charter’s Application To The Extraterritorial Activities Of The Canadian Security Intelligence Service","authors":"Leah West","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0105","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0105","url":null,"abstract":"Since the swift passage of the Anti-Terrorism Act in 2015, the Canadian Security Intelligence Service (CSIS) has had the unprecedented and highly controversial authority to take ‘reasonable and proportionate’ measures to reduce threats to Canadian security. While there are some limits to the types of measures CSIS can employ, the Canadian Security Intelligence Service Act permits the use of measures that would otherwise contravene the laws of Canada or limit a right protected by the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms so long as they are judicially authorized by the Federal Court. As new threats proliferate around the world, it is anticipated that CSIS will increasingly carry out this mandate overseas. Yet review bodies tasked with monitoring CSIS’s use of threat reduction measures (TRMs) report that CSIS has never sought judicial authorization to conduct a TRM. Why? One answer may be that CSIS has concluded that the Charter does not govern actions carried out abroad, and, as such, their extraterritorial conduct falls beyond the reach and oversight of the Federal Court. Whether the Charter applies to CSIS’s overseas conduct ostensibly lies in the Supreme Court of Canada’s leading case on the extraterritorial application of the Charter, R. v Hape. This article canvasses domestic and international law, as well as intelligence law theory, to explain why that presumption is wrong. Wrong, not least because the majority opinion in Hape is deeply flawed in its analysis and application of international law. But also, because intelligence operations are so distinguishable from the transnational criminal investigations at issue in Hape, the Court’s findings are inapplicable in the former context. In short, this article demonstrates that applying Hape to the actions of CSIS officers not only leaves their actions beyond the scrutiny of Canadian courts but also creates a significant human rights gap.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":" ","pages":"-"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2022-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44957764","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Private Liability Without Wrongdoing 没有过错的私人责任
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-12-23 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0062
R. Stone
Rights-based theories of private law tend to be wrongs based and defendant focused. But many private law wrongs do not seem like genuine wrongs, at least when the background distribution of resources is unjust. A very poor person, for example, may be held legally liable for breaching a one-sided contract with a very rich person. When such a contract reflects and reproduces existing injustice, it is hard to view the poor person’s breach of such a contract as a genuine wrong against the rich person. Conversely, some obvious moral wrongs do not generate legal liability. There is, for example, no private law duty of rescue in the absence of a prior relationship in many situations in which most would agree that there is a moral duty of rescue. Thus, private legal liability seems not to track moral wrongdoing in significant respects, raising the question what instead justifies such liability. Instead of justifying private liability in terms of the defendant’s wrongdoing, as corrective justice and civil recourse theorists do, we should seek a justification in terms of the plaintiff’s moral permission to enforce her apparent rights. Switching our gaze from the defendant’s wrongdoing to the plaintiff’s moral permission to enforce her rights will not be normatively consequential if the plaintiff’s moral permission arises when and only when the defendant has wronged her. But, I argue, background injustice can drive a wedge between genuine wrongdoing and the plaintiff’s moral permission. Thus, by reconceptualizing private liability in terms of a plaintiff’s moral permission to enforce her apparent rights, private law may be justified by the essential role it plays in constituting non-ideal political morality.
以权利为基础的私法理论往往以错误为基础,以被告为中心。但是,至少在资源分配不公的背景下,许多私法上的错误看起来并不像真正的错误。例如,一个非常穷的人可能会因违反与一个非常富有的人签订的单方面合同而被追究法律责任。当这种契约反映并再现了现有的不公正时,就很难将穷人违反这种契约视为对富人的真正错误。相反,一些明显的道德错误并不会产生法律责任。例如,在没有先前关系的情况下,没有私法上的救助义务,在许多情况下,大多数人会同意存在道德上的救助义务。因此,私人法律责任似乎没有在重大方面追踪道德不法行为,这就提出了一个问题,即是什么证明了这种责任的正当性。我们不应像纠正正义和民事追索权理论家那样,以被告的不法行为来证明私人责任的正当性,而应从原告执行其表面权利的道德许可来寻求正当性。如果原告的道德许可在且仅在被告冤枉了她时才出现,那么将我们的目光从被告的不法行为转移到原告行使其权利的道德许可上,将不具有规范的结果性。但是,我认为,背景不公正会在真正的不法行为和原告的道德许可之间造成隔阂。因此,根据原告强制执行其表面权利的道德许可来重新定义私人责任,私法在构成非理想政治道德方面所起的重要作用可能是合理的。
{"title":"Private Liability Without Wrongdoing","authors":"R. Stone","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0062","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0062","url":null,"abstract":"Rights-based theories of private law tend to be wrongs based and defendant focused. But many private law wrongs do not seem like genuine wrongs, at least when the background distribution of resources is unjust. A very poor person, for example, may be held legally liable for breaching a one-sided contract with a very rich person. When such a contract reflects and reproduces existing injustice, it is hard to view the poor person’s breach of such a contract as a genuine wrong against the rich person. Conversely, some obvious moral wrongs do not generate legal liability. There is, for example, no private law duty of rescue in the absence of a prior relationship in many situations in which most would agree that there is a moral duty of rescue. Thus, private legal liability seems not to track moral wrongdoing in significant respects, raising the question what instead justifies such liability. Instead of justifying private liability in terms of the defendant’s wrongdoing, as corrective justice and civil recourse theorists do, we should seek a justification in terms of the plaintiff’s moral permission to enforce her apparent rights. Switching our gaze from the defendant’s wrongdoing to the plaintiff’s moral permission to enforce her rights will not be normatively consequential if the plaintiff’s moral permission arises when and only when the defendant has wronged her. But, I argue, background injustice can drive a wedge between genuine wrongdoing and the plaintiff’s moral permission. Thus, by reconceptualizing private liability in terms of a plaintiff’s moral permission to enforce her apparent rights, private law may be justified by the essential role it plays in constituting non-ideal political morality.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"0 1","pages":"-"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45823167","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
University of Toronto Law Journal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1