首页 > 最新文献

University of Toronto Law Journal最新文献

英文 中文
Systemic corruption and institutional multiplicity: Brazilian examples of a complex relationship 系统性腐败和制度多样性:巴西复杂关系的例子
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-10-08 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2020-0119
M. Prado, Raquel de Mattos Pimenta
Abstract:Systemic corruption is usually described as a stable self-reinforcing equilibrium that traps individuals by reducing incentives to behave honestly. This article assumes that law enforcement institutions may also be trapped in this equilibrium, leaving no alternative to individuals who want to report corruption. Would the existence of multiple institutions performing accountability functions – what we call institutional multiplicity – reduce the probability that all institutions would be trapped in a systemic corruption environment? We start by hypothesizing that even in contexts of systemic corruption there may be ‘pockets of honesty.’ If this is the case, institutional multiplicity, by increasing the number of accountability institutions available, may create avenues for individuals to report corruption. On the other hand, multiplicity may also increase the risk of ‘façade enforcement’ – that is, the mere appearance of accountability that reinforces a systemic corruption equilibrium. We illustrate these two scenarios with Brazilian examples. We end the article with a discussion of the design of accountability systems in contexts of systemic corruption, arguing that there may be advantages in preserving institutional multiplicity if its deleterious effects are addressed. While based on the Brazilian experience, this article advances theoretical hypotheses that may be useful to other countries.
摘要:系统性腐败通常被描述为一种稳定的自我强化平衡,通过减少诚实行为的动机来诱捕个人。本文假设执法机构也可能陷入这种平衡,除了想要举报腐败的个人之外别无选择。履行问责职能的多个机构的存在——我们称之为机构多样性——会降低所有机构陷入系统性腐败环境的可能性吗?我们首先假设,即使在系统性腐败的背景下,也可能存在“诚实的口袋”如果是这样的话,通过增加现有问责机构的数量,机构的多样性可能会为个人举报腐败创造途径。另一方面,多样性也可能增加“表面执法”的风险——也就是说,仅仅是问责制的出现就加强了系统性腐败的平衡。我们用巴西的例子来说明这两种情况。文章最后,我们讨论了系统性腐败背景下问责制的设计,认为如果解决了其有害影响,那么保持制度多样性可能会有好处。本文在借鉴巴西经验的基础上,提出了对其他国家有益的理论假设。
{"title":"Systemic corruption and institutional multiplicity: Brazilian examples of a complex relationship","authors":"M. Prado, Raquel de Mattos Pimenta","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2020-0119","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2020-0119","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:Systemic corruption is usually described as a stable self-reinforcing equilibrium that traps individuals by reducing incentives to behave honestly. This article assumes that law enforcement institutions may also be trapped in this equilibrium, leaving no alternative to individuals who want to report corruption. Would the existence of multiple institutions performing accountability functions – what we call institutional multiplicity – reduce the probability that all institutions would be trapped in a systemic corruption environment? We start by hypothesizing that even in contexts of systemic corruption there may be ‘pockets of honesty.’ If this is the case, institutional multiplicity, by increasing the number of accountability institutions available, may create avenues for individuals to report corruption. On the other hand, multiplicity may also increase the risk of ‘façade enforcement’ – that is, the mere appearance of accountability that reinforces a systemic corruption equilibrium. We illustrate these two scenarios with Brazilian examples. We end the article with a discussion of the design of accountability systems in contexts of systemic corruption, arguing that there may be advantages in preserving institutional multiplicity if its deleterious effects are addressed. While based on the Brazilian experience, this article advances theoretical hypotheses that may be useful to other countries.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"102 - 74"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-10-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47787651","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Corruption and the criminal law: Assurance and deterrence 腐败与刑法:保证与威慑
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-09-22 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0014
Vincent Chiao
Abstract:In this article, I consider the degree to which criminal justice interventions may be expected to ameliorate systemic corruption. I distinguish between two ideal types of corrupt actors – conditional cooperators and autonomous defectors – and argue that the prospects of reform through criminal justice are greatly affected by the relative preponderance of each type. When conditional cooperators predominate, the criminal law serves primarily to provide assurance that a perceived social norm is effective, in that the norm is both widely adhered to, and adhered to because people endorse the propriety of that norm. When autonomous defectors predominate, the criminal law serves primarily to deter would-be cheaters by attaching costs, at least in expectation, to cheating. Because patterns of compliance based upon a social norm tend to be self-reinforcing, unlike patterns of compliance motivated by fear of sanction, I argue that the prospects of sustainable reform through criminal justice interventions is likely to depend to a substantial degree upon convincing people to trust social norms rather than rely upon their private judgments of what is in their interest – that is, to become conditional cooperators.
摘要:在本文中,我考虑了刑事司法干预可能改善系统性腐败的程度。我区分了两种理想类型的腐败行为者——有条件的合作者和自主的叛逃者——并认为,通过刑事司法进行改革的前景受到每一种类型的相对优势的极大影响。当有条件的合作者占主导地位时,刑法的主要作用是保证一种被感知的社会规范是有效的,因为这种规范既被广泛遵守,又因为人们认可这种规范的适当性而被遵守。当自主叛逃者占主导地位时,刑法的主要作用是通过给作弊行为附加成本(至少在预期中)来威慑潜在的作弊者。由于基于社会规范的服从模式往往是自我强化的,而不像出于对制裁的恐惧而激发的服从模式,我认为,通过刑事司法干预实现可持续改革的前景,可能在很大程度上取决于说服人们信任社会规范,而不是依赖于他们对自己利益的个人判断——也就是说,成为有条件的合作者。
{"title":"Corruption and the criminal law: Assurance and deterrence","authors":"Vincent Chiao","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0014","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:In this article, I consider the degree to which criminal justice interventions may be expected to ameliorate systemic corruption. I distinguish between two ideal types of corrupt actors – conditional cooperators and autonomous defectors – and argue that the prospects of reform through criminal justice are greatly affected by the relative preponderance of each type. When conditional cooperators predominate, the criminal law serves primarily to provide assurance that a perceived social norm is effective, in that the norm is both widely adhered to, and adhered to because people endorse the propriety of that norm. When autonomous defectors predominate, the criminal law serves primarily to deter would-be cheaters by attaching costs, at least in expectation, to cheating. Because patterns of compliance based upon a social norm tend to be self-reinforcing, unlike patterns of compliance motivated by fear of sanction, I argue that the prospects of sustainable reform through criminal justice interventions is likely to depend to a substantial degree upon convincing people to trust social norms rather than rely upon their private judgments of what is in their interest – that is, to become conditional cooperators.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"34 - 8"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41906909","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
From birth to agony: The political life of Operation Car Wash (Operação Lava Jato) 从出生到痛苦:洗车行动的政治生活(opera<s:1> o Lava Jato)
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-09-21 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0043
F. Limongi
Abstract:This article reconstructs Operation Car Wash’s (Operação Lava Jato) political project. Three different phases of the operation are analysed: its conception, its encounter with political and administrative corruption, and its attempt to mobilize popular support to combat political and administrative corruption. The analysis characterizes the operation as a particular manifestation of judicial intervention in the system of representative politics, presenting a critical view of its effects on the balance of power between non-elected and elected officials.
摘要:本文对Operation Car Wash (opera o Lava Jato)政治项目进行了重构。本报告分析了行动的三个不同阶段:行动的构想、遇到的政治和行政腐败以及动员民众支持打击政治和行政腐败的努力。该分析将这一行动定性为代议制政治制度中司法干预的一种特殊表现,对其对非民选官员和民选官员之间权力平衡的影响提出了批判性的看法。
{"title":"From birth to agony: The political life of Operation Car Wash (Operação Lava Jato)","authors":"F. Limongi","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0043","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0043","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:This article reconstructs Operation Car Wash’s (Operação Lava Jato) political project. Three different phases of the operation are analysed: its conception, its encounter with political and administrative corruption, and its attempt to mobilize popular support to combat political and administrative corruption. The analysis characterizes the operation as a particular manifestation of judicial intervention in the system of representative politics, presenting a critical view of its effects on the balance of power between non-elected and elected officials.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"151 - 173"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-09-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41388093","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Popular sovereignty and constitutional democracy 人民主权和宪政民主
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-09-21 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2021-0048
P. Pettit
Abstract:In recent times, the idea of popular sovereignty has figured prominently in the rhetoric of neo-populist thinkers and activists who argue that legal and political authority must be concentrated in one single body or individual elected by the people to act in its name. The thesis of this article is that, while the notion of popular sovereignty may seem to offer some support to the neo-populist image of democracy, it serves more persuasively to support the idea of a polycentric, constitutional democracy. The constitutional state can be polycentric and yet feature a sovereign. And if this constitutional state is democratic in the sense of distributing power relatively equally amongst individual citizens, thus empowering the people-several, then it will establish the people-corporate in the role of sovereign.
摘要:近年来,人民主权的概念在新民粹主义思想家和活动家的言论中占有突出地位,他们认为法律和政治权威必须集中在一个由人民选举出来的单一机构或个人身上,以人民的名义行事。本文的论点是,虽然人民主权的概念似乎为新民粹主义的民主形象提供了一些支持,但它更有说服力地支持了多中心宪政民主的理念。宪政国家可以是多中心的,但又有一个主权者。如果这个宪政国家是民主的,它在公民个人之间相对平等地分配权力,从而赋予人民——几个人——权力,那么它将确立人民-法人在主权角色中的地位。
{"title":"Popular sovereignty and constitutional democracy","authors":"P. Pettit","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2021-0048","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2021-0048","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:In recent times, the idea of popular sovereignty has figured prominently in the rhetoric of neo-populist thinkers and activists who argue that legal and political authority must be concentrated in one single body or individual elected by the people to act in its name. The thesis of this article is that, while the notion of popular sovereignty may seem to offer some support to the neo-populist image of democracy, it serves more persuasively to support the idea of a polycentric, constitutional democracy. The constitutional state can be polycentric and yet feature a sovereign. And if this constitutional state is democratic in the sense of distributing power relatively equally amongst individual citizens, thus empowering the people-several, then it will establish the people-corporate in the role of sovereign.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"72 1","pages":"251 - 286"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-09-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44222235","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Giving reasons as a means to enhance compliance with legal norms 提供理由作为加强遵守法律规范的手段
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-07-25 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3892956
Daphna Lewinsohn-Zamir, E. Zamir, O. Katz
Abstract:The threat of sanctions is often insufficient to ensure compliance with legal norms. Recently, much attention has been given to nudges – choice-preserving measures that take advantage of people’s automatic System 1 thinking – as a means of influencing behaviour without sanctions, but nudges are often ineffective and controversial. This article explores the provision of information about the reasons underlying legal norms, as a means to enhance compliance, primarily through deliberative System 2 thinking. While the idea that legal norms should be accompanied by explanatory preambles – to complement the law’s threat of sanctions with persuasion – goes back to Plato, this technique is not commonly used nowadays, and scholars have failed to systematically consider this possibility. The article argues that reason giving can enhance compliance and reduce the need for costly enforcement mechanisms. The theoretical part of the article comprises three parts. It first describes the mechanisms through which reasons may influence people’s behaviour. It then distinguishes between reason giving as a means to enhance compliance and as a means to attain other goals and between reason giving and related means to enhance compliance. Finally, it discusses various policy and pragmatic considerations that bear on the use of reason giving. Following the theoretical discussion, the empirical part of the article uses vignette studies to demonstrate the feasibility and efficacy of the reason-giving technique. The results of these new studies show that providing good reasons for legal norms enhances people’s inclination to comply with them, in comparison to not providing the reasons underlying the norms. However, whereas persuasive reasons may promote compliance, questionable reasons might reduce it. We call on scholars and policy makers to pay more attention to this readily available measure of enhancing compliance with norms.
摘要:制裁威胁往往不足以确保遵守法律规范。最近,人们非常关注“助推”——利用人们的自动系统1思维来保留选择的措施——作为一种不受制裁的影响行为的手段,但“助推”往往是无效的,而且存在争议。本文主要通过审议系统2的思维,探讨了提供法律规范背后的原因信息,作为增强合规性的一种手段。虽然法律规范应该伴随着解释性序言的想法——以说服补充法律的制裁威胁——可以追溯到柏拉图,但这种技术现在并不常用,学者们也没有系统地考虑这种可能性。本文认为,给出理由可以提高遵从性,并减少对代价高昂的执行机制的需求。本文的理论部分包括三个部分。它首先描述了原因可能影响人们行为的机制。然后,它区分了作为加强服从的手段的给出理由和作为达到其他目标的手段的给出理由以及作为增强服从的相关手段的给出理由之间的区别。最后,讨论了运用推理的各种政策和实用考虑。在理论讨论之后,本文的实证部分采用小案例研究来论证推理技术的可行性和有效性。这些新研究的结果表明,与不提供法律规范背后的原因相比,为法律规范提供充分的理由会增强人们遵守法律规范的倾向。然而,虽然有说服力的理由可能会促进服从,但可疑的理由可能会减少服从。我们呼吁学者和政策制定者更多地关注这一随时可用的加强遵守规范的措施。
{"title":"Giving reasons as a means to enhance compliance with legal norms","authors":"Daphna Lewinsohn-Zamir, E. Zamir, O. Katz","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3892956","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3892956","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:The threat of sanctions is often insufficient to ensure compliance with legal norms. Recently, much attention has been given to nudges – choice-preserving measures that take advantage of people’s automatic System 1 thinking – as a means of influencing behaviour without sanctions, but nudges are often ineffective and controversial. This article explores the provision of information about the reasons underlying legal norms, as a means to enhance compliance, primarily through deliberative System 2 thinking. While the idea that legal norms should be accompanied by explanatory preambles – to complement the law’s threat of sanctions with persuasion – goes back to Plato, this technique is not commonly used nowadays, and scholars have failed to systematically consider this possibility. The article argues that reason giving can enhance compliance and reduce the need for costly enforcement mechanisms. The theoretical part of the article comprises three parts. It first describes the mechanisms through which reasons may influence people’s behaviour. It then distinguishes between reason giving as a means to enhance compliance and as a means to attain other goals and between reason giving and related means to enhance compliance. Finally, it discusses various policy and pragmatic considerations that bear on the use of reason giving. Following the theoretical discussion, the empirical part of the article uses vignette studies to demonstrate the feasibility and efficacy of the reason-giving technique. The results of these new studies show that providing good reasons for legal norms enhances people’s inclination to comply with them, in comparison to not providing the reasons underlying the norms. However, whereas persuasive reasons may promote compliance, questionable reasons might reduce it. We call on scholars and policy makers to pay more attention to this readily available measure of enhancing compliance with norms.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"72 1","pages":"316 - 355"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-07-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47220101","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Elaborate Imaginings: Rethinking Environmental Obligations in Canadian Insolvency Law 精心想象:对加拿大破产法中环境义务的再思考
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-05-15 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2020-0035
Anna J. Lund
Abstract:Environmental obligations fit uncomfortably into the framework of federal insolvency law. Canadian courts have struggled to articulate which environmental obligations should be stayed, compromised, and discharged in insolvency proceedings and which should remain fully enforceable. In its 2019 decision, Orphan Well Association v Grant Thornton Ltd, the Supreme Court of Canada drew a distinction between two types of environmental obligations: debts and public duties. Debts are subject to being stayed, compromised, and discharged, whereas public duties remain enforceable notwithstanding the obligor's insolvency proceedings. This article elaborates the distinction drawn by the Supreme Court of Canada between debts and public duties by considering who constitutes the public. It offers three answers. The public could include existing members of the human community, future generations of humanity, or non-human environmental entities. The article synthesizes the legal precedents supporting the different conceptions of the public and traces their implications for insolvency practice. Critics charge that the Supreme Court of Canada's decision in Orphan Well has improperly given environmental obligations a super-priority in insolvency proceedings and that such a reordering of insolvency priorities should have been left to Parliament. Yet careful attention to the 'public' character of environmental obligations justifies judicial interventions like the Court's decision in Orphan Well. As humanity faces the existential threat of climate change, the common law provides scope for reimagining legal concepts to better serve the needs of our communities.
摘要:环境义务不适合于联邦破产法的框架。加拿大法院一直在努力阐明哪些环境义务应在破产程序中保留、妥协和解除,哪些应保持完全可执行性。在2019年的“孤儿井协会诉均富有限公司”一案中,加拿大最高法院区分了两种类型的环境义务:债务和公共责任。债务可以暂缓、妥协和解除,而尽管债务人已进入破产程序,公共责任仍可强制执行。本文通过考虑谁构成公共责任,阐述了加拿大最高法院对债务和公共责任的区别。它提供了三个答案。公众可以包括人类社会的现有成员、人类的后代或非人类的环境实体。本文综合了支持不同公众概念的法律先例,并追溯了它们对破产实践的影响。批评人士指责加拿大最高法院在孤儿井案中的裁决不恰当地在破产程序中给予环境义务一个超级优先级,而这种对破产优先级的重新排序应该留给议会。然而,对环境义务的“公共”性质的仔细关注证明了司法干预的合理性,就像法院对孤儿井的裁决一样。当人类面临气候变化的生存威胁时,普通法为重新构想法律概念提供了空间,以更好地服务于我们社会的需要。
{"title":"Elaborate Imaginings: Rethinking Environmental Obligations in Canadian Insolvency Law","authors":"Anna J. Lund","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2020-0035","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2020-0035","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:Environmental obligations fit uncomfortably into the framework of federal insolvency law. Canadian courts have struggled to articulate which environmental obligations should be stayed, compromised, and discharged in insolvency proceedings and which should remain fully enforceable. In its 2019 decision, Orphan Well Association v Grant Thornton Ltd, the Supreme Court of Canada drew a distinction between two types of environmental obligations: debts and public duties. Debts are subject to being stayed, compromised, and discharged, whereas public duties remain enforceable notwithstanding the obligor's insolvency proceedings. This article elaborates the distinction drawn by the Supreme Court of Canada between debts and public duties by considering who constitutes the public. It offers three answers. The public could include existing members of the human community, future generations of humanity, or non-human environmental entities. The article synthesizes the legal precedents supporting the different conceptions of the public and traces their implications for insolvency practice. Critics charge that the Supreme Court of Canada's decision in Orphan Well has improperly given environmental obligations a super-priority in insolvency proceedings and that such a reordering of insolvency priorities should have been left to Parliament. Yet careful attention to the 'public' character of environmental obligations justifies judicial interventions like the Court's decision in Orphan Well. As humanity faces the existential threat of climate change, the common law provides scope for reimagining legal concepts to better serve the needs of our communities.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"301 - 337"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42931056","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Religious institutionalism: A feminist response 宗教制度主义:女权主义的回应
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-02-16 DOI: 10.3138/UTLJ-2020-0098
K. Chan
Abstract:People who are committed to religious freedom are generally also committed to protecting the conditions for the cultivation of religious life. Because of the deep linkages between religious belief and practice and religious institutions, it can seem natural and straightforward to move from championing religious freedom to championing religious freedom for religious institutions themselves. Members of the Supreme Court of Canada indicated their readiness to make this move in a 2015 case involving a Catholic secondary school in Quebec. In this article, I challenge the idea that according religious institutions section 2(a) protection in their own right is either a natural or a straightforward consequence of a commitment to collective religious freedom. I describe the intellectual history and characteristics of religious institutionalism and summarize the claims of its principal Canadian proponent. I then outline several ways in which religious institutionalism clashes with our basic constitutional commitments. Finally, I develop several prongs of a feminist response to religious institutionalism. I highlight the normative character of questions about the constitutional status of religious institutions, the gendered nature of the relationship between religious institutions and individual rights-holders, and the organic and dynamic features of religious institutions. I argue that we must approach institutional religious freedom claims cautiously and resist any interpretation of section 2(a) that would entrench and shield from internal resistance a singular, institutional religious voice.
摘要:致力于宗教自由的人通常也致力于保护培养宗教生活的条件。由于宗教信仰和实践与宗教机构之间有着深刻的联系,从支持宗教自由转向支持宗教机构本身的宗教自由似乎是自然而直接的。加拿大最高法院成员在2015年魁北克一所天主教中学的案件中表示,他们准备采取这一行动。在这篇文章中,我质疑这样一种观点,即根据宗教机构第2(a)条,对其自身权利的保护要么是对集体宗教自由的承诺的自然结果,要么是直接结果。我描述了宗教制度主义的思想历史和特点,并总结了其主要支持者加拿大的主张。然后,我概述了宗教制度主义与我们的基本宪法承诺相冲突的几种方式。最后,我提出了女权主义对宗教制度主义的几种回应。我强调了宗教机构的宪法地位问题的规范性,宗教机构与个人权利持有人之间关系的性别性质,以及宗教机构的有机和动态特征。我认为,我们必须谨慎对待制度性宗教自由主张,抵制对第2(a)条的任何解释,因为这种解释会巩固和保护一个独特的制度性宗教声音,使其免受内部阻力。
{"title":"Religious institutionalism: A feminist response","authors":"K. Chan","doi":"10.3138/UTLJ-2020-0098","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/UTLJ-2020-0098","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:People who are committed to religious freedom are generally also committed to protecting the conditions for the cultivation of religious life. Because of the deep linkages between religious belief and practice and religious institutions, it can seem natural and straightforward to move from championing religious freedom to championing religious freedom for religious institutions themselves. Members of the Supreme Court of Canada indicated their readiness to make this move in a 2015 case involving a Catholic secondary school in Quebec. In this article, I challenge the idea that according religious institutions section 2(a) protection in their own right is either a natural or a straightforward consequence of a commitment to collective religious freedom. I describe the intellectual history and characteristics of religious institutionalism and summarize the claims of its principal Canadian proponent. I then outline several ways in which religious institutionalism clashes with our basic constitutional commitments. Finally, I develop several prongs of a feminist response to religious institutionalism. I highlight the normative character of questions about the constitutional status of religious institutions, the gendered nature of the relationship between religious institutions and individual rights-holders, and the organic and dynamic features of religious institutions. I argue that we must approach institutional religious freedom claims cautiously and resist any interpretation of section 2(a) that would entrench and shield from internal resistance a singular, institutional religious voice.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"443 - 479"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-02-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46388747","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Combatting corruption and collusion in public procurement: Lessons from Operation Car Wash 打击公共采购中的腐败和勾结:洗车行动的经验教训
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2021-01-21 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3712858
Alison Jones, Caio Mário S. Pereira Neto
Abstract:This article examines the question of how a nation can combat corruption and collusion and prevent these practices from plaguing and undermining public procurement processes. This matter is especially important to Brazil where Operation Car Wash exposed widespread corruption and collusion affecting public procurement. Although focusing on Brazil, this article reflects on a broader academic and policy debate as to how a nation can escape from a ‘high-corruption’ equilibrium, especially one strengthened by its interaction with supplier collusion. In particular, whether endemic corruption can be combatted through an invigorated law enforcement push, combined with incremental reform, or whether some ‘big bang’ approach, with complete institutional overhaul, is required to establish a new equilibrium. The article notes that the Brazilian experience provides support for the hypothesis that, where corruption is endemic, better laws and law enforcement may be insufficient on their own to break a cycle and to remove the incentives and opportunities for corruption and collusion that exist. However, it also recognizes that, for many jurisdictions, wholesale big bang reform is unlikely to be feasible. It thus proposes a multi-pronged, and self-reinforcing, set of reforms to trigger change, concentrated on weaknesses diagnosed in the system. In particular, it suggests that where corruption affects public procurement, beyond specific adjustments to procurement, competition and anti-corruption laws, procurers, anti-corruption and competition enforcement agencies need to work closely together to coordinate policies, achieve synergies and to combat incentives and opportunities for corruption and collusion within procurement processes. Such reforms must be combined with measures to tackle broader factors contributing to systemic corruption. Although inspired by the Brazilian case study, the diagnosis and proposed reform strategy provides a workable model for use in other jurisdictions.
摘要:本文探讨了一个国家如何打击腐败和勾结,防止这些做法困扰和破坏公共采购过程的问题。这件事对巴西尤为重要,因为“洗车行动”揭露了影响公共采购的广泛腐败和勾结。尽管这篇文章关注的是巴西,但它反映了一场更广泛的学术和政策辩论,即一个国家如何摆脱“高度腐败”的平衡,尤其是通过与供应商勾结的互动而加强的平衡。特别是,是否可以通过强有力的执法推动,结合渐进式改革来打击地方性腐败,或者是否需要一些“大爆炸”的方法,通过彻底的制度改革来建立新的平衡。文章指出,巴西的经验支持这样一种假设,即在腐败盛行的地方,更好的法律和执法本身可能不足以打破循环,消除腐败和勾结的动机和机会。然而,它也认识到,对许多司法管辖区来说,大规模的大爆炸改革不太可能可行。因此,它提出了一套多管齐下、自我强化的改革方案,以引发变革,集中解决系统中诊断出的弱点。报告特别指出,在腐败影响公共采购的情况下,除了对采购、竞争和反腐败法进行具体调整外,采购人员、反腐败和竞争执法机构还需要密切合作,协调政策,实现协同增效,并打击采购过程中腐败和勾结的动机和机会。这些改革必须与解决导致系统性腐败的更广泛因素的措施相结合。尽管受到巴西案例研究的启发,但诊断和拟议的改革战略为其他司法管辖区提供了一个可行的模式。
{"title":"Combatting corruption and collusion in public procurement: Lessons from Operation Car Wash","authors":"Alison Jones, Caio Mário S. Pereira Neto","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3712858","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3712858","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:This article examines the question of how a nation can combat corruption and collusion and prevent these practices from plaguing and undermining public procurement processes. This matter is especially important to Brazil where Operation Car Wash exposed widespread corruption and collusion affecting public procurement. Although focusing on Brazil, this article reflects on a broader academic and policy debate as to how a nation can escape from a ‘high-corruption’ equilibrium, especially one strengthened by its interaction with supplier collusion. In particular, whether endemic corruption can be combatted through an invigorated law enforcement push, combined with incremental reform, or whether some ‘big bang’ approach, with complete institutional overhaul, is required to establish a new equilibrium. The article notes that the Brazilian experience provides support for the hypothesis that, where corruption is endemic, better laws and law enforcement may be insufficient on their own to break a cycle and to remove the incentives and opportunities for corruption and collusion that exist. However, it also recognizes that, for many jurisdictions, wholesale big bang reform is unlikely to be feasible. It thus proposes a multi-pronged, and self-reinforcing, set of reforms to trigger change, concentrated on weaknesses diagnosed in the system. In particular, it suggests that where corruption affects public procurement, beyond specific adjustments to procurement, competition and anti-corruption laws, procurers, anti-corruption and competition enforcement agencies need to work closely together to coordinate policies, achieve synergies and to combat incentives and opportunities for corruption and collusion within procurement processes. Such reforms must be combined with measures to tackle broader factors contributing to systemic corruption. Although inspired by the Brazilian case study, the diagnosis and proposed reform strategy provides a workable model for use in other jurisdictions.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"103 - 150"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2021-01-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46501006","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Taking tort seriously 认真对待侵权行为
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2020-12-04 DOI: 10.3138/utlj.2020-0110
S. Smith
Abstract:In Recognizing Wrongs, John Goldberg and Benjamin Zipursky argue that tort law is just what 'it looks to be' – and that what it looks to be is a law of wrongs and recourse. It is not necessary, in their view, to turn to economics, sociology, philosophy, or any other discipline to understand tort law: it is sufficient to take seriously judges' reasons for why they decide tort cases as they do. In advancing this argument, Goldberg and Zipursky seek to distinguish themselves from two influential camps in contemporary tort theory: (a) theories that argue that tort law's rights are 'rights' in only a nominal sense and (b) theories that accept that tort law's rights are genuine but defend those rights by invoking a comprehensive moral theory. In this review essay, I argue that Goldberg and Zipursky largely succeed in their ambitions. The qualifications that I explore are twofold. First, certain tort remedies are not recourse for wrongs, even at the level of appearances. Second, it is not easy to construct a theory of tort law while sticking as close to tort law's appearances as Goldberg and Zipursky purport to stick. The theory that Goldberg and Zipursky ultimately defend relies on certain philosophic ideas (though it does not rely on a comprehensive moral theory); it is also complex, multilayered, and skeletal in its account of tort law's primary duties and, thus, arguably less of a 'theory of tort law' than those offered by their competitors (though I argue that this feature is a virtue of their account).
摘要:在《认识错误》一书中,约翰·戈德堡(John Goldberg)和本杰明·齐珀斯基(Benjamin Zipursky)认为,侵权法只是“看起来”的样子——它看起来是一部关于错误和追索权的法律。在他们看来,没有必要求助于经济学、社会学、哲学或任何其他学科来理解侵权法:只要认真考虑法官为什么这样判决侵权案件的理由就足够了。在推进这一论点时,Goldberg和Zipursky试图将自己与当代侵权理论中的两个有影响力的阵营区分开来:(a)认为侵权法的权利只是名义上的“权利”的理论;(b)承认侵权法的权利是真实的,但通过援引全面的道德理论来捍卫这些权利的理论。在这篇评论文章中,我认为Goldberg和Zipursky在很大程度上实现了他们的野心。我探讨的条件是双重的。首先,即使在表面上,某些侵权救济也不是对错误的追索权。其次,在像Goldberg和Zipursky所主张的那样贴近侵权法的表象的情况下构建侵权法理论并不容易。Goldberg和Zipursky最终捍卫的理论依赖于某些哲学思想(尽管它并不依赖于一个全面的道德理论);在对侵权法的主要职责的描述中,它也是复杂的、多层次的和骨架的,因此,可以说,与他们的竞争对手提供的理论相比,它更不属于“侵权法理论”(尽管我认为这一特征是他们的描述的优点)。
{"title":"Taking tort seriously","authors":"S. Smith","doi":"10.3138/utlj.2020-0110","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj.2020-0110","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:In Recognizing Wrongs, John Goldberg and Benjamin Zipursky argue that tort law is just what 'it looks to be' – and that what it looks to be is a law of wrongs and recourse. It is not necessary, in their view, to turn to economics, sociology, philosophy, or any other discipline to understand tort law: it is sufficient to take seriously judges' reasons for why they decide tort cases as they do. In advancing this argument, Goldberg and Zipursky seek to distinguish themselves from two influential camps in contemporary tort theory: (a) theories that argue that tort law's rights are 'rights' in only a nominal sense and (b) theories that accept that tort law's rights are genuine but defend those rights by invoking a comprehensive moral theory. In this review essay, I argue that Goldberg and Zipursky largely succeed in their ambitions. The qualifications that I explore are twofold. First, certain tort remedies are not recourse for wrongs, even at the level of appearances. Second, it is not easy to construct a theory of tort law while sticking as close to tort law's appearances as Goldberg and Zipursky purport to stick. The theory that Goldberg and Zipursky ultimately defend relies on certain philosophic ideas (though it does not rely on a comprehensive moral theory); it is also complex, multilayered, and skeletal in its account of tort law's primary duties and, thus, arguably less of a 'theory of tort law' than those offered by their competitors (though I argue that this feature is a virtue of their account).","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"415 - 441"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2020-12-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42194234","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Private law rights as democratic participation: Kelsen on private law and (economic) democracy 作为民主参与的私法权利——凯尔森谈私法与(经济)民主
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2020-12-04 DOI: 10.3138/utlj-2020-0039
H. Dedek
Abstract:In the first edition of his famous treatise Reine Rechtslehre, Einleitung in die Rechtswissenschaftliche Problematik (translated as Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory), Hans Kelsen makes the claim that the existing liberal, property rights-based private law of his era is a 'democratic form of law' and that private law rights are 'political in the same sense as those rights that are usually characterized as political rights.' In this article, I aim to explain how Kelsen developed his theory of private law and private rights within the theoretical and methodological framework of the 'Pure Theory of Law' and its philosophical underpinnings of relativism and 'value neutrality,' culminating in the connection between private law and democracy. I wish to highlight, in particular, the still often underappreciated fact that the Pure Theory saw itself as a critical project, aimed at exposing and exorcizing 'ideology.' To Kelsen's contemporary audiences, drawing a connection between 'capitalist' private law and democracy must have appeared particularly counter-intuitive against the backdrop of one of the most important – if now almost forgotten – political debates of the Weimar era, the debate on 'economic democracy' ('Wirtschaftsdemokratie'). It was a powerful trope in the inter-war period that the capitalist economy and its institutional safeguards – private, labour, commercial, and corporate law – were 'undemocratic.' I submit that Kelsen's statement – flipping the contemporaneous revisionist-socialist rhetoric on its head – may be better understood in the larger context of the precarity of democracy in the Weimar period and especially in the context of a theoretical and political challenge that contrasted the existing 'bourgeois' parliamentary democracy with a 'true,' 'social' democracy that would realize conditions of social and economic justice. By connecting 'capitalistic' law with 'democracy' and 'socialistic' law with 'autocracy,' Kelsen once more underscores that democracy, properly understood as a formal principle, is irreducible to substantive justice.
摘要:汉斯·凯尔森(Hans Kelsen)在其著名论著《法学问题导论》(Reine Rechtslehre, Einleitung In die Rechtswissenschaftliche Problematik)的第一版中声称,他那个时代现存的自由主义的、以财产权为基础的私法是一种“民主形式的法律”,私法权利“与那些通常被定性为政治权利的权利在同一意义上是政治性的”。在这篇文章中,我的目的是解释凯尔森如何在“纯粹法律理论”的理论和方法论框架内发展他的私法和私人权利理论,以及它的相对主义和“价值中立”的哲学基础,最终在私法和民主之间建立联系。我希望特别强调一个仍然经常被低估的事实,即《纯粹理论》将自己视为一个批判性的项目,旨在揭露和驱除“意识形态”。对于凯尔森同时代的读者来说,将“资本主义”私法与民主联系起来,在魏玛时代最重要的政治辩论之一——关于“经济民主”(“wirtschaftsdemocrdemocratic”)的辩论的背景下,肯定显得特别违反直觉。在两次世界大战期间,资本主义经济及其制度保障——私法、劳动法、商法和公司法——是“不民主的”,这是一个强有力的比喻。我认为,凯尔森的声明——颠覆了当时修正主义社会主义的修辞——在魏玛时期民主不稳定的大背景下,尤其是在理论和政治挑战的背景下,可以更好地理解,这种挑战将现有的“资产阶级”议会民主与“真正的”、“社会的”民主进行了对比,后者将实现社会和经济正义的条件。通过将“资本主义”法律与“民主”、“社会主义”法律与“专制”联系起来,凯尔森再次强调,民主,如果被恰当地理解为一种形式原则,是不可简化为实质正义的。
{"title":"Private law rights as democratic participation: Kelsen on private law and (economic) democracy","authors":"H. Dedek","doi":"10.3138/utlj-2020-0039","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3138/utlj-2020-0039","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:In the first edition of his famous treatise Reine Rechtslehre, Einleitung in die Rechtswissenschaftliche Problematik (translated as Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory), Hans Kelsen makes the claim that the existing liberal, property rights-based private law of his era is a 'democratic form of law' and that private law rights are 'political in the same sense as those rights that are usually characterized as political rights.' In this article, I aim to explain how Kelsen developed his theory of private law and private rights within the theoretical and methodological framework of the 'Pure Theory of Law' and its philosophical underpinnings of relativism and 'value neutrality,' culminating in the connection between private law and democracy. I wish to highlight, in particular, the still often underappreciated fact that the Pure Theory saw itself as a critical project, aimed at exposing and exorcizing 'ideology.' To Kelsen's contemporary audiences, drawing a connection between 'capitalist' private law and democracy must have appeared particularly counter-intuitive against the backdrop of one of the most important – if now almost forgotten – political debates of the Weimar era, the debate on 'economic democracy' ('Wirtschaftsdemokratie'). It was a powerful trope in the inter-war period that the capitalist economy and its institutional safeguards – private, labour, commercial, and corporate law – were 'undemocratic.' I submit that Kelsen's statement – flipping the contemporaneous revisionist-socialist rhetoric on its head – may be better understood in the larger context of the precarity of democracy in the Weimar period and especially in the context of a theoretical and political challenge that contrasted the existing 'bourgeois' parliamentary democracy with a 'true,' 'social' democracy that would realize conditions of social and economic justice. By connecting 'capitalistic' law with 'democracy' and 'socialistic' law with 'autocracy,' Kelsen once more underscores that democracy, properly understood as a formal principle, is irreducible to substantive justice.","PeriodicalId":46289,"journal":{"name":"University of Toronto Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"376 - 414"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2020-12-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46185979","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
University of Toronto Law Journal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1