首页 > 最新文献

Philosophical Issues最新文献

英文 中文
Understanding friendship 了解友谊
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-10-22 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12268
Michel Croce, Matthew Jope
This article takes issue with two prominent views in the current debate around epistemic partiality in friendship. Strong views of epistemic partiality hold that friendship may require biased beliefs in direct conflict with epistemic norms. Weak views hold that friendship may place normative expectations on belief formation but in a manner that does not violate these norms. It is argued that neither view succeeds in explaining the relationship between epistemic norms and friendship norms. Weak views inadvertently endorse a form of motivated reasoning, failing to resolve the normative clash they seek to avoid. Strong views turn out to be incoherent once we consider the question of whether the requirement to form an epistemically partial belief is independent of whether the belief in question would be true. It is then argued that an epistemology of friendship should recognise the special role that understanding plays in friendship. On this view, friendship normatively requires understanding the truth about our friends. This entails that epistemic partiality, far from being a requirement, is in fact at odds with good friendship.
本文对当前围绕友谊中认识论偏向性的辩论中的两种主要观点提出异议。关于认识偏向性的强势观点认为,友谊可能要求有偏向的信念,这与认识规范直接冲突。而弱的观点则认为,友谊可能会对信念的形成产生规范性的预期,但其方式并不违反这些规范。本文认为,这两种观点都不能成功地解释认识论规范与友谊规范之间的关系。弱观点无意中认可了一种动机推理,未能解决它们试图避免的规范冲突。一旦我们考虑形成认识论上的片面信念的要求是否与相关信念是否为真无关这一问题,强势观点就会被证明是不一致的。有学者认为,友谊认识论应该承认理解在友谊中的特殊作用。根据这一观点,友谊的规范性要求我们理解朋友的真相。这就意味着,认识论上的偏袒非但不是一种要求,事实上还与良好的友谊相悖。
{"title":"Understanding friendship","authors":"Michel Croce, Matthew Jope","doi":"10.1111/phis.12268","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12268","url":null,"abstract":"This article takes issue with two prominent views in the current debate around epistemic partiality in friendship. Strong views of epistemic partiality hold that friendship may require biased beliefs in direct conflict with epistemic norms. Weak views hold that friendship may place normative expectations on belief formation but in a manner that does not violate these norms. It is argued that neither view succeeds in explaining the relationship between epistemic norms and friendship norms. Weak views inadvertently endorse a form of motivated reasoning, failing to resolve the normative clash they seek to avoid. Strong views turn out to be incoherent once we consider the question of whether the requirement to form an epistemically partial belief is independent of whether the belief in question would be true. It is then argued that an epistemology of friendship should recognise the special role that understanding plays in friendship. On this view, friendship normatively requires understanding the truth about our friends. This entails that epistemic partiality, far from being a requirement, is in fact at odds with good friendship.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"13 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142486787","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Epistemic normativity without epistemic teleology 没有认识目的论的认识论规范性
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-30 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12274
Benjamin Kiesewetter
This article is concerned with a puzzle that arises from three initially plausible assumptions that form an inconsistent triad: (i) Epistemic reasons are normative reasons (normativism); (ii) reasons are normative only if conformity with them is good (the reasons/value‐link); (iii) conformity with epistemic reasons need not be good (the nihilist assumption). I start by defending the reasons/value‐link, arguing that normativists need to reject the nihilist assumption. I then argue that the most familiar view that denies the nihilist assumption—epistemic teleology—is untenable. Finally, I consider two alternative ways of accounting for the goodness of conformity with epistemic reasons: it may be good because it accords with the virtue of reasons‐responsiveness, and it may be good because it is good to conform with normative reasons as such. I argue that both of these conceptions avoid the problems of epistemic teleology and merit serious consideration as potential solutions to the puzzle.
本文关注的难题来自三个最初看似合理的假设,这三个假设构成了一个不一致的三元组:(i) 认识论理由是规范性理由(规范主义);(ii) 只有符合理由是好的,理由才是规范性的(理由/价值联系);(iii) 符合认识论理由不一定是好(虚无主义假设)。我首先为 "理由/价值联系 "辩护,认为规范主义者需要摒弃虚无主义假设。然后,我论证了人们最熟悉的否定虚无主义假设的观点--表义目的论--是站不住脚的。最后,我考虑了符合认识论理由之善的两种可供选择的解释方式:符合认识论理由之善可能是因为它符合理由反应性的美德,符合认识论理由之善可能是因为符合规范理由本身就是善的。我认为,这两种概念都避免了认识论目的论的问题,值得认真考虑作为解决这一难题的潜在方案。
{"title":"Epistemic normativity without epistemic teleology","authors":"Benjamin Kiesewetter","doi":"10.1111/phis.12274","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12274","url":null,"abstract":"This article is concerned with a puzzle that arises from three initially plausible assumptions that form an inconsistent triad: (i) Epistemic reasons are normative reasons (normativism); (ii) reasons are normative only if conformity with them is good (the reasons/value‐link); (iii) conformity with epistemic reasons need not be good (the nihilist assumption). I start by defending the reasons/value‐link, arguing that normativists need to reject the nihilist assumption. I then argue that the most familiar view that denies the nihilist assumption—epistemic teleology—is untenable. Finally, I consider two alternative ways of accounting for the goodness of conformity with epistemic reasons: it may be good because it accords with the virtue of reasons‐responsiveness, and it may be good because it is good to conform with normative reasons as such. I argue that both of these conceptions avoid the problems of epistemic teleology and merit serious consideration as potential solutions to the puzzle.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"10 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142330313","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reasons and belief 理由和信念
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-25 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12265
Daniel Fogal
Much recent work in epistemology has concerned the relationship between the epistemic and the practical, with a particular focus on the question of how, if at all, practical considerations affect what we ought to believe. Two main positive accounts have been proposed: reasons pragmatism and pragmatic encroachment. According to reasons pragmatism, practical (including moral) considerations can affect what we ought to believe by constituting distinctively practical (i.e., non‐epistemic) reasons for or against belief. According to pragmatic encroachment, practical considerations bear on what we ought to believe by affecting epistemic justification (e.g. how much justification is required to justifiably believe). Both debates center around intuitive judgments about cases together with various principles involving reasons (or justification) and belief, with many contributors in the pragmatism and—to a lesser extent—encroachment debates helping themselves to talk of belief without saying much about what exactly they have in mind. There has also been a tendency to overlook potentially relevant distinctions among different kinds of reasons that have been drawn elsewhere. The goal of this paper is to argue that greater clarity and care concerning both reasons and belief is called for. Increased sensitivity to various subtleties will not only minimize the chances of unwittingly engaging in merely verbal disputes but also allow us to better navigate the pragmatism and encroachment debates.
认识论近期的许多研究都涉及认识论与实践之间的关系,尤其关注实践因素如何(如果有的话)影响我们应该相信什么的问题。人们提出了两种主要的积极说法:理由实用主义和实用主义侵蚀。根据理由实用主义,实践(包括道德)因素可以通过构成支持或反对信仰的独特实践(即非表义)理由来影响我们应该信仰什么。根据实用主义侵蚀说,实用因素通过影响认识论的正当性(例如,需要多少正当性才能合理地相信)来影响我们应该相信什么。这两场争论都围绕着对案例的直觉判断以及涉及理由(或正当性)和信念的各种原则展开,实用主义和侵蚀论(程度较轻)争论中的许多贡献者都在谈论信念,而没有多谈他们心目中的信念究竟是什么。此外,还有一种倾向,即忽略了其他地方对不同类型的理由所做的潜在的相关区分。本文的目的是要论证,在理由和信念这两个问题上都需要更加清晰和谨慎。提高对各种微妙之处的敏感性,不仅可以最大限度地减少在不知不觉中陷入仅仅是口头上的争论的机会,而且还可以让我们更好地驾驭实用主义和侵占论的争论。
{"title":"Reasons and belief","authors":"Daniel Fogal","doi":"10.1111/phis.12265","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12265","url":null,"abstract":"Much recent work in epistemology has concerned the relationship between the epistemic and the practical, with a particular focus on the question of how, if at all, practical considerations affect what we ought to believe. Two main positive accounts have been proposed: reasons pragmatism and pragmatic encroachment. According to reasons pragmatism, practical (including moral) considerations can affect what we ought to believe by constituting distinctively practical (i.e., non‐epistemic) reasons for or against belief. According to pragmatic encroachment, practical considerations bear on what we ought to believe by affecting epistemic justification (e.g. how much justification is required to justifiably believe). Both debates center around intuitive judgments about cases together with various principles involving reasons (or justification) and belief, with many contributors in the pragmatism and—to a lesser extent—encroachment debates helping themselves to talk of belief without saying much about what exactly they have in mind. There has also been a tendency to overlook potentially relevant distinctions among different kinds of reasons that have been drawn elsewhere. The goal of this paper is to argue that greater clarity and care concerning both reasons and belief is called for. Increased sensitivity to various subtleties will not only minimize the chances of unwittingly engaging in merely verbal disputes but also allow us to better navigate the pragmatism and encroachment debates.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"22 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142317148","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The relational foundations of epistemic normativity 认识论规范性的关系基础
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-24 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12270
Cameron Boult
Why comply with epistemic norms? In this paper, I argue that complying with epistemic norms, engaging in epistemically responsible conduct, and being epistemically trustworthy are constitutive elements of maintaining good epistemic relations with oneself and others. Good epistemic relations are in turn both instrumentally and finally valuable: they enable the kind of coordination and knowledge acquisition underpinning much of what we tend to associate with a flourishing human life; and just as good interpersonal relations with others can be good for their own sake, standing in good epistemic relations is good for its own sake. On my account, we have reason to comply with epistemic norms because it is a way of respecting the final value of something that also tends to be an instrumentally valuable thing: good epistemic relations. Situating the account within the recent social turn in debates about epistemic instrumentalism, I argue that the dual‐value aspect of good epistemic relations can explain important anti‐instrumentalist intuitions, in a well‐motivated way, within a broadly instrumentalist framework.
为什么要遵守认识论规范?在本文中,我认为遵守认识论规范、从事认识论上负责任的行为以及在认识论上值得信赖是与自己和他人保持良好认识论关系的构成要素。良好的认识论关系反过来又具有工具价值和最终价值:它们使协调和知识获取成为可能,而这种协调和知识获取正是我们倾向于与繁荣的人类生活联系在一起的许多东西的基础;正如与他人的良好人际关系本身可能是好的一样,保持良好的认识论关系本身也是好的。根据我的观点,我们有理由遵守认识论规范,因为这是一种尊重最终价值的方式,而良好的认识论关系往往也是一种工具性价值。将这一论述置于最近关于认识论工具论的辩论的社会转向之中,我认为良好认识论关系的双重价值可以在广义的工具论框架内,以动机良好的方式解释重要的反工具论直觉。
{"title":"The relational foundations of epistemic normativity","authors":"Cameron Boult","doi":"10.1111/phis.12270","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12270","url":null,"abstract":"Why comply with epistemic norms? In this paper, I argue that complying with epistemic norms, engaging in epistemically responsible conduct, and being epistemically trustworthy are constitutive elements of maintaining <jats:italic>good epistemic relations</jats:italic> with oneself and others. Good epistemic relations are in turn both instrumentally and finally valuable: they enable the kind of coordination and knowledge acquisition underpinning much of what we tend to associate with a flourishing human life; and just as good interpersonal relations with others can be good for their own sake, standing in good epistemic relations is good for its own sake. On my account, we have reason to comply with epistemic norms because it is a way of respecting the final value of something that also tends to be an instrumentally valuable thing: good epistemic relations. Situating the account within the recent social turn in debates about epistemic instrumentalism, I argue that the dual‐value aspect of good epistemic relations can explain important anti‐instrumentalist intuitions, in a well‐motivated way, within a broadly instrumentalist framework.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"21 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142313560","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The limits of experience: Dogmatism and moral epistemology 经验的局限:教条主义与道德认识论
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-24 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12275
Uriah Kriegel
Let “phenomenal dogmatism” be the thesis that some experiences provide some beliefs with immediate prima facie justification, and do so purely in virtue of their phenomenal character. A basic question‐mark looms over phenomenal dogmatism: Why should the fact that a person is visited by some phenomenal feel suggest the likely truth of a belief? In this paper, I press this challenge, arguing that perceptually justified beliefs are justified not purely by perceptual experiences’ phenomenology, but also because we have justified second‐order background beliefs to the effect that the occurrence of certain perceptual experiences is indicative of the likely truth of certain corresponding beliefs. To bring this out, I contrast “perceptual dogmatism” with “moral dogmatism”: the thesis that some emotional experiences provide some moral beliefs with immediate prima facie justification, and do so purely in virtue of their phenomenal character. I argue that moral dogmatism is much less antecedently appealing, precisely because the counterpart second‐order beliefs here are much less plausible.
让 "现象教条主义 "成为这样一种论断,即某些经验为某些信念提供了直接的表面理由,而这样做纯粹是由于它们的现象特征。现象教条主义存在一个基本的问号:为什么一个人被某种现象感觉所拜访这一事实就能说明某种信念可能是真的呢?在本文中,我提出了这一质疑,认为知觉上合理的信念之所以合理,并不纯粹是由于知觉经验的现象学,还因为我们有合理的二阶背景信念,即某些知觉经验的发生表明了某些相应信念的可能真实性。为了揭示这一点,我将 "知觉教条主义 "与 "道德教条主义 "进行了对比:"道德教条主义 "认为某些情感体验为某些道德信念提供了直接的初步证明,而且这种证明纯粹是由于情感体验的现象学特征。我认为,道德教条主义的先验吸引力要小得多,这正是因为与之相对应的二阶信念的可信度要低得多。
{"title":"The limits of experience: Dogmatism and moral epistemology","authors":"Uriah Kriegel","doi":"10.1111/phis.12275","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12275","url":null,"abstract":"Let “phenomenal dogmatism” be the thesis that some experiences provide some beliefs with immediate prima facie justification, and do so purely in virtue of their phenomenal character. A basic question‐mark looms over phenomenal dogmatism: Why should the fact that a person is visited by some phenomenal feel suggest the likely truth of a belief? In this paper, I press this challenge, arguing that perceptually justified beliefs are justified not purely by perceptual experiences’ phenomenology, but also because we have justified second‐order background beliefs to the effect that the occurrence of certain perceptual experiences is indicative of the likely truth of certain corresponding beliefs. To bring this out, I contrast “perceptual dogmatism” with “moral dogmatism”: the thesis that some emotional experiences provide some moral beliefs with immediate prima facie justification, and do so purely in virtue of their phenomenal character. I argue that moral dogmatism is much less antecedently appealing, precisely because the counterpart second‐order beliefs here are much less plausible.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"21 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142313626","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Moral expertise as skilled practice 作为熟练实践的道德专业知识
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-22 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12282
Sarah Stroud
Contemporary discussions of moral expertise have raised a host of problems for the very idea of a “moral expert.” This article interrogates the conception of moral expertise that such discussions seem to assume and proposes instead that we understand moral expertise as a species of practical skill. On this model, a skilled moral agent is more similar to a skilled pianist than she is to a theoretical expert (for instance, an expert on the War of 1812). The article argues both that it is more natural to understand the moral “expert” as excelling in a form of skilled practice and that such a conception would render moot many of the concerns which preoccupy contemporary discussions.
当代关于道德专业知识的讨论为 "道德专家 "这一概念本身提出了一系列问题。本文对此类讨论似乎假定的道德专家概念提出质疑,并建议我们将道德专家理解为一种实践技能。在这种模式下,一个熟练的道德代理人更类似于一个熟练的钢琴家,而不是一个理论专家(例如,1812 年战争专家)。文章认为,将道德 "专家 "理解为擅长某种形式的熟练实践更为自然,而且这种概念将使当代讨论中的许多关切变得毫无意义。
{"title":"Moral expertise as skilled practice","authors":"Sarah Stroud","doi":"10.1111/phis.12282","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12282","url":null,"abstract":"Contemporary discussions of moral expertise have raised a host of problems for the very idea of a “moral expert.” This article interrogates the conception of moral expertise that such discussions seem to assume and proposes instead that we understand moral expertise as a species of practical skill. On this model, a skilled moral agent is more similar to a skilled pianist than she is to a theoretical expert (for instance, an expert on the War of 1812). The article argues both that it is more natural to understand the moral “expert” as excelling in a form of skilled practice and that such a conception would render moot many of the concerns which preoccupy contemporary discussions.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"19 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142306258","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What do we do when we suspend judgement? 当我们暂停判断时,我们该怎么做?
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-20 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12278
Anne Meylan
According to a classical view, suspension of judgement is, like belief and disbelief, a cognitive state. However, as some authors (Crawford 2022; Lord 2020; McGrath 2021a, 2021b; Sosa 2019, 2021) have pointed out, to suspend judgement is also to perform a certain mental action. The main goal of this article is to defend a precise account of the action that we take when we suspend our judgement: the Preventing Account. The Preventing Account has both the advantage of (i) accounting for familiar situations in which subjects suspend judgements and (ii) of explaining the tendency, which is widespread in the philosophical tradition (from sceptics to pragmatists), to consider suspension of judgement as something that is (at least, to some degree) difficult to achieve.
根据经典观点,暂停判断与相信和不相信一样,是一种认知状态。然而,正如一些学者(Crawford 2022;Lord 2020;McGrath 2021a、2021b;Sosa 2019、2021)所指出的,中止判断也是在执行某种心理行动。本文的主要目的是为我们在暂缓判断时所采取的行动辩护:"预防说"。预防说 "的优势在于:(i) 解释了人们所熟悉的中止判断的情形;(ii) 解释了哲学传统(从怀疑论者到实用主义者)中普遍存在的倾向,即认为中止判断是(至少在某种程度上)难以实现的。
{"title":"What do we do when we suspend judgement?","authors":"Anne Meylan","doi":"10.1111/phis.12278","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12278","url":null,"abstract":"According to a classical view, suspension of judgement is, like belief and disbelief, a cognitive state. However, as some authors (Crawford 2022; Lord 2020; McGrath 2021a, 2021b; Sosa 2019, 2021) have pointed out, to suspend judgement is also to perform a certain mental action. The main goal of this article is to defend a precise account of the action that we take when we suspend our judgement: the Preventing Account. The Preventing Account has both the advantage of (i) accounting for familiar situations in which subjects suspend judgements and (ii) of explaining the tendency, which is widespread in the philosophical tradition (from sceptics to pragmatists), to consider suspension of judgement as something that is (at least, to some degree) difficult to achieve.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"12 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142306395","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How emotions grasp value 情感如何把握价值
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-18 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12272
Antti Kauppinen
It's plausible that we only fully appreciate the value of something, say a painting or a blameworthy action, when we have a fitting emotional response to it, such as admiration or guilt. But exactly how and why do we grasp value through emotion? I propose, first, that a subject S phenomenally grasps property P only if what it is to be P is manifest in the phenomenal character of S's experience. Second, following clues from the Stoics, I argue that the phenomenal character of emotional experience is constitutively linked with its having directive content. More precisely, emotional experience directs us both to adopt a maxim for action – take certain characteristic kinds of action for an emotion‐specific end – and to treat something about the object as a presumptively decisive reason to take such action for such end. If we assent to what the experience proposes (or rational control gets bypassed), we are motivated to take the relevant action and have a corresponding evaluative belief. This picture of emotional cognition yields a natural conception of the evaluative fittingness conditions of emotions without the problematic assumption that they have a presentational phenomenology. Instead, it is precisely in virtue of the directive and valenced phenomenology of emotion that values are only fully manifest in emotional experience, since values are essentially action‐ and attitude‐guiding properties.
我们只有在对某一事物(比如一幅画或一个应受指责的行为)产生适当的情感反应(比如钦佩或内疚)时,才会充分认识到它的价值,这一点是有道理的。但是,我们究竟是如何以及为什么要通过情感来把握价值的呢?我建议,首先,只有当 "P "是什么体现在 S 的经验的现象特征中时,主体 S 才能从现象上把握属性 P。其次,根据斯多葛学派的线索,我认为情感体验的现象学特征与情感体验的指导性内容有着内在联系。更确切地说,情感体验既指导我们采取一种行动格言--为了特定的情感目的而采取某些有特征的行动--又指导我们把对象的某些东西看作是为了这种目的而采取这种行动的推定的决定性理由。如果我们同意经验的提议(或绕过理性控制),我们就会有采取相关行动的动机,并产生相应的评价信念。情感认知的这一图景为情感的评价契合性条件提供了一个自然的概念,而无需假设情感具有现时现象学这一有问题的假设。相反,正是由于情感的指导性和价值现象学,价值观才在情感体验中得到充分体现,因为价值观本质上是行动和态度的指导属性。
{"title":"How emotions grasp value","authors":"Antti Kauppinen","doi":"10.1111/phis.12272","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12272","url":null,"abstract":"It's plausible that we only fully appreciate the value of something, say a painting or a blameworthy action, when we have a fitting emotional response to it, such as admiration or guilt. But exactly how and why do we grasp value through emotion? I propose, first, that a subject S phenomenally grasps property P only if what it is to be P is manifest in the phenomenal character of S's experience. Second, following clues from the Stoics, I argue that the phenomenal character of emotional experience is constitutively linked with its having directive content. More precisely, emotional experience directs us both to adopt a maxim for action – take certain characteristic kinds of action for an emotion‐specific end – and to treat something about the object as a presumptively decisive reason to take such action for such end. If we assent to what the experience proposes (or rational control gets bypassed), we are motivated to take the relevant action and have a corresponding evaluative belief. This picture of emotional cognition yields a natural conception of the evaluative fittingness conditions of emotions without the problematic assumption that they have a presentational phenomenology. Instead, it is precisely in virtue of the directive and valenced phenomenology of emotion that values are only fully manifest in emotional experience, since values are essentially action‐ and attitude‐guiding properties.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142236726","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Unification without pragmatism 没有实用主义的统一
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-18 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12280
Keshav Singh
Both actions and beliefs are subject to normative evaluation as rational or irrational. As such, we might expect there to be some general, unified story about what makes them rational. However, orthodox approaches suggest that the rationality of action is determined by practical considerations, while the rationality of belief is determined by properly epistemic considerations. This apparent disunity leads some, like Rinard (2019), to reject orthodox theories of the rationality of belief in favor of pragmatism. In this paper, I argue we should reject pragmatist approaches to unifying the rationality of action and belief. Instead, I argue, we should embrace a correctness‐based view of rationality, on which rationality is fundamentally about getting things correct as best we can, given our epistemic limitations. On such a view, the facts about rational action and belief are a function of the facts about correct action and belief. I contend that the apparent disunity of orthodox theories is created by the fact that action and belief have different correctness conditions. Nevertheless, on the correctness‐based view, this disunity is merely apparent. This renders pragmatism's revisionary implications for the rationality of belief unnecessary to take on in order unify it with the rationality of action.
行为和信念都会受到规范性评价,被视为理性或非理性。因此,我们可能会期望有一些普遍的、统一的说法来说明是什么使它们具有合理性。然而,正统方法认为,行动的合理性由实践因素决定,而信念的合理性则由适当的认识论因素决定。这种明显的不统一导致一些人,如 Rinard(2019),拒绝接受关于信仰合理性的正统理论,转而支持实用主义。在本文中,我认为我们应该摒弃实用主义统一行动与信念合理性的方法。相反,我认为我们应该接受一种基于正确性的理性观,根据这种理性观,理性从根本上说就是在我们的认识论局限下,尽我们所能把事情做正确。根据这种观点,关于理性行动和信念的事实是关于正确行动和信念的事实的函数。我认为,正统理论表面上的不统一是由行动和信念具有不同的正确性条件这一事实造成的。然而,根据基于正确性的观点,这种不统一只是表面上的。这就使得实用主义对信念合理性的修正意义没有必要承担,以便将其与行动合理性统一起来。
{"title":"Unification without pragmatism","authors":"Keshav Singh","doi":"10.1111/phis.12280","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12280","url":null,"abstract":"Both actions and beliefs are subject to normative evaluation as rational or irrational. As such, we might expect there to be some general, unified story about what makes them rational. However, orthodox approaches suggest that the rationality of action is determined by practical considerations, while the rationality of belief is determined by properly epistemic considerations. This apparent disunity leads some, like Rinard (2019), to reject orthodox theories of the rationality of belief in favor of pragmatism. In this paper, I argue we should reject pragmatist approaches to unifying the rationality of action and belief. Instead, I argue, we should embrace a <jats:italic>correctness‐based</jats:italic> view of rationality, on which rationality is fundamentally about getting things correct as best we can, given our epistemic limitations. On such a view, the facts about rational action and belief are a function of the facts about correct action and belief. I contend that the apparent disunity of orthodox theories is created by the fact that action and belief have different correctness conditions. Nevertheless, on the correctness‐based view, this disunity is merely apparent. This renders pragmatism's revisionary implications for the rationality of belief unnecessary to take on in order unify it with the rationality of action.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"30 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142236725","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Freedom of thought 思想自由
IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-18 DOI: 10.1111/phis.12271
Matthew Chrisman
This paper develops a novel conception of freedom of thought as the right to epistemic self‐realization. The recognition of this right is characterized here as a modally robust normative status that I think one has as a potential knower in an epistemic community. It is a status that one cannot enjoy without a specific form of institutionalized intellectual respect and support. To explain and defend this conception of freedom of thought, it is contrasted here with more traditionally “negative” conceptions of freedom of thought, in terms of not being interfered with. It is also contrasted here with a “positive” conception of freedom of thought derived from a recently prominent account of doxastic agency as grounded in the rational capacity to self‐determine one's own response to reasons. In both cases, the crux of the argument in this paper is that a conception of freedom of thought as a right to epistemic self‐realization makes better sense of why we fear the counter‐liberatory forces of propaganda and regulated thinking, and also why we hold out hope for the liberating potential of education and critical engagement with expertise in the public sphere.
本文提出了一种新颖的思想自由概念,即认识论自我实现的权利。在这里,对这一权利的承认被描述为一种模态上稳健的规范性地位,我认为这是一个人作为认识论共同体中的潜在认识者所拥有的。如果没有特定形式的制度化知识尊重和支持,人们就无法享有这种地位。为了解释和捍卫这种思想自由的概念,我们在此将其与思想自由的传统 "消极 "概念(即不受干扰)进行对比。同时,它也与一种 "积极的 "思想自由概念形成对比,这种思想自由概念源于近来一种著名的论述,即 "绪论代理"(doxastic agency)是以自我决定对理由的反应的理性能力为基础的。在这两种情况下,本文论证的关键在于,作为认识论自我实现权利的思想自由概念,能够更好地解释为什么我们害怕宣传和规范思维的反解放力量,以及为什么我们对公共领域的教育和对专业知识的批判性参与的解放潜力抱有希望。
{"title":"Freedom of thought","authors":"Matthew Chrisman","doi":"10.1111/phis.12271","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12271","url":null,"abstract":"This paper develops a novel conception of freedom of thought as the right to epistemic self‐realization. The recognition of this right is characterized here as a modally robust normative status that I think one has as a potential knower in an epistemic community. It is a status that one cannot enjoy without a specific form of institutionalized intellectual respect and support. To explain and defend this conception of freedom of thought, it is contrasted here with more traditionally “negative” conceptions of freedom of thought, in terms of not being interfered with. It is also contrasted here with a “positive” conception of freedom of thought derived from a recently prominent account of doxastic agency as grounded in the rational capacity to self‐determine one's own response to reasons. In both cases, the crux of the argument in this paper is that a conception of freedom of thought as a right to epistemic self‐realization makes better sense of why we fear the counter‐liberatory forces of propaganda and regulated thinking, and also why we hold out hope for the liberating potential of education and critical engagement with expertise in the public sphere.","PeriodicalId":46360,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Issues","volume":"13 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142236723","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Philosophical Issues
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1