首页 > 最新文献

Hastings Law Journal最新文献

英文 中文
Corporations and the Original Meaning of 'Citizens' in Article III 公司与第三条中“公民”的原意
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2020-03-03 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3548143
M. Moller, Lawrence B. Solum
Article III grants confers the judicial power of the United States over controversies between "citizens" of different states. In Section 1332(c) of Title 28 of the United States Code, Congress has provided that for the purposes of diversity jurisdiction, corporations are citizens of the state in which they are incorporated and the state in which their principal place of business is located. This raises the question whether corporations are citizens within the original public meaning of Article III of the Constitution. This Article demonstrates that in 1787 the word "citizen" referred only to natural persons and therefore that corporations cannot be considered "citizens" within the original public meaning of Article III. As a consequence, Section 1332(c) is unconstitutional from an originalist perspective. (This is the most current version as of August 9, 2020.)
第三条授予美国对各州“公民”之间争议的司法权。在《美国法典》第28篇第1332(c)节中,国会规定,就多样性管辖而言,公司是其注册所在州及其主要营业地所在州的公民。这就提出了一个问题,即公司是否是《宪法》第三条最初公共含义范围内的公民。该条款表明,1787年,“公民”一词仅指自然人,因此,公司不能被视为第三条最初公共含义中的“公民”。因此,从原始主义的角度来看,第1332(c)条是违宪的。(这是截至2020年8月9日的最新版本。)
{"title":"Corporations and the Original Meaning of 'Citizens' in Article III","authors":"M. Moller, Lawrence B. Solum","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3548143","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3548143","url":null,"abstract":"Article III grants confers the judicial power of the United States over controversies between \"citizens\" of different states. In Section 1332(c) of Title 28 of the United States Code, Congress has provided that for the purposes of diversity jurisdiction, corporations are citizens of the state in which they are incorporated and the state in which their principal place of business is located. This raises the question whether corporations are citizens within the original public meaning of Article III of the Constitution. This Article demonstrates that in 1787 the word \"citizen\" referred only to natural persons and therefore that corporations cannot be considered \"citizens\" within the original public meaning of Article III. As a consequence, Section 1332(c) is unconstitutional from an originalist perspective. (This is the most current version as of August 9, 2020.)","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"72 1","pages":"169"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-03-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44939236","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Law of the State and Politics 国家法律与政治
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2019-12-31 DOI: 10.1525/9780520929685-019
G. Vecchio
{"title":"Law of the State and Politics","authors":"G. Vecchio","doi":"10.1525/9780520929685-019","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1525/9780520929685-019","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"17 1","pages":"669"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2019-12-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42584816","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Beyond the Double Veto: Housing Plans as Preemptive Intergovernmental Compacts 超越双重否决:住房计划作为先发制人的政府间契约
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2019-12-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3256857
Christopher S. Elmendorf
The problem of local-government barriers to housing supply is finally enjoying its moment in the sun. For decades, the states did little to remedy this problem and arguably they made it worse. But spurred by a rising Yes in My Backyard (YIMBY) movement, state legislatures are now trying to make local governments plan for more housing, allow greater density in existing residential zones, and follow their own rules when reviewing development applications. This Article describes and takes stock of the new state housing initiatives, relating them to preexisting Northeastern and West Coast approaches to the housing-supply problem; to the legal-academic literature on land use; and, going a bit further afield, to the federal government’s efforts to protect the voting rights of African Americans in the Jim Crow South. Of particular interest, we will see that in California, ground zero for the housing crisis, the general plan is evolving into something that resembles less a traditional land-use plan than a preemptive and self-executing intergovernmental compact for development permitting, one which supersedes other local law until the local government has produced its quota of housing for the planning cycle. The parties to the compact are the state, acting through its housing agency, and the local government in whose territory the housing would be built. I argue that this general approach holds real promise as a way of overcoming local barriers to housing supply, particularly in a world—our world—where there is little political consensus about the appropriate balance between local and state control over land use, or about what constitutes an illegitimate local barrier. The main weakness of the emerging California model is that the state framework does little to change the local political dynamics that caused the housing crisis in the first place. To remedy this shortcoming, I propose some modest extensions of the model, which would give relatively pro-housing factions in city politics more political leverage and policymaking discretion and also facilitate regional housing deals.
地方政府阻碍住房供应的问题终于得到了解决。几十年来,各州几乎没有采取任何措施来解决这个问题,可以说,它们使问题变得更糟了。但是,在日益高涨的“在我家后院”(YIMBY)运动的刺激下,州立法机构正试图让地方政府规划更多的住房,允许现有住宅区的密度更高,并在审查开发申请时遵循自己的规定。本文描述并评估了新的国家住房倡议,将它们与先前存在的东北和西海岸解决住房供应问题的方法联系起来;关于土地利用的法律学术文献;再往远一点说,就是联邦政府为保护南方种族隔离地区非裔美国人的投票权所做的努力。特别有趣的是,我们将看到,在加州,住房危机的原点,总体规划正在演变成一种类似于传统土地使用计划的东西,而不是一种先发制人的、自动执行的政府间开发许可契约,它取代了其他地方法律,直到当地政府为规划周期生产出住房配额。契约的双方是通过其住房机构行事的国家,以及将在其领土上建造住房的地方政府。我认为,这种普遍的方法作为克服地方住房供应障碍的一种方式,具有真正的希望,特别是在一个世界——我们的世界——在这个世界上,关于地方和国家对土地使用的控制之间的适当平衡,或者关于什么构成了非法的地方障碍,几乎没有政治共识。新兴的加州模式的主要弱点是,州框架对改变导致住房危机的地方政治动态几乎没有作用。为了弥补这一缺陷,我提出了对该模型的一些适度扩展,这将赋予城市政治中相对支持住房的派系更多的政治杠杆和决策自由裁量权,并促进区域住房交易。
{"title":"Beyond the Double Veto: Housing Plans as Preemptive Intergovernmental Compacts","authors":"Christopher S. Elmendorf","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3256857","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3256857","url":null,"abstract":"The problem of local-government barriers to housing supply is finally enjoying its moment in the sun. For decades, the states did little to remedy this problem and arguably they made it worse. But spurred by a rising Yes in My Backyard (YIMBY) movement, state legislatures are now trying to make local governments plan for more housing, allow greater density in existing residential zones, and follow their own rules when reviewing development applications. This Article describes and takes stock of the new state housing initiatives, relating them to preexisting Northeastern and West Coast approaches to the housing-supply problem; to the legal-academic literature on land use; and, going a bit further afield, to the federal government’s efforts to protect the voting rights of African Americans in the Jim Crow South. Of particular interest, we will see that in California, ground zero for the housing crisis, the general plan is evolving into something that resembles less a traditional land-use plan than a preemptive and self-executing intergovernmental compact for development permitting, one which supersedes other local law until the local government has produced its quota of housing for the planning cycle. The parties to the compact are the state, acting through its housing agency, and the local government in whose territory the housing would be built. I argue that this general approach holds real promise as a way of overcoming local barriers to housing supply, particularly in a world—our world—where there is little political consensus about the appropriate balance between local and state control over land use, or about what constitutes an illegitimate local barrier. The main weakness of the emerging California model is that the state framework does little to change the local political dynamics that caused the housing crisis in the first place. To remedy this shortcoming, I propose some modest extensions of the model, which would give relatively pro-housing factions in city politics more political leverage and policymaking discretion and also facilitate regional housing deals.","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"79"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2019-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46577047","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
Unmasking the Right of Publicity 公开权的揭秘
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2019-04-10 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3300959
Dustin Marlan
In the landmark 1953 case of Haelan Laboratories v. Topps Chewing Gum, Judge Jerome Frank first articulated the modern right of publicity—a transferable intellectual property right. The right has since been seen to protect the commercial value of one’s “persona”—the Latin-derived word meaning the mask of an actor. Among other frequent criticisms, the right of publicity is accused of lacking a coherent justification, permitting only economic redress against public harms to the persona, and stripping away individual identity by allowing for a proprietary right in one’s personality. Why might Judge Frank have been motivated to fashion a transferable right in the monetary value of one’s public persona distinct from the psychic harm to feelings, emotions, and dignity rooted in the individual and protected under the rubric of privacy? Judge Frank was a leading figure in the American legal realist movement known for his unique and controversial “psychoanalysis of certain legal positions” through influential books including Law and the Modern Mind and Courts on Trial. His work drew heavily on the ideas of psychoanalytic thinkers, like Sigmund Freud and Carl Jung, to describe the distorting effects of unconscious wishes and fantasies on the decision-making process of legal actors and judges. For Judge Frank, the psychoanalytic interplay between public and private aspects of the personality supported his realist interpretation of lawmaking as a subjective and indeterminate activity. Indeed, though Frank provided little rationale for articulating a personality right separate from privacy in Haelan, he had given a tremendous amount of attention to the personality in his scholarly works. This Article suggests that the modern right of publicity’s aim, as perhaps intended by Judge Frank in considering his psychoanalytic jurisprudence, may be usefully understood through the psychoanalytic conception of the personality—one divided into public and private subparts. In the psychoanalytic sense, the term persona, or “false self,” is used to indicate the public face of an individual, i.e., the image one presents to others for social or economic advantage, as contrasted with their feelings, emotions and subjective interpretations of reality anchored in their private shadow, or “true self.” Yet, the law’s continued reliance on this dualistic metaphor of the personality appears misguided, particularly as technology, internet, and new media increasingly blur the traditional distinctions between public and private. The Article thus concludes by examining intersubjective personality theory. Intersubjectivity could provide publicity law with a useful conceptual update given its view of the self and personality as a relational, contextual, and social construct, rather than a public-private dichotomy.
在1953年具有里程碑意义的Haelan Laboratories诉Topps Chewing Gum一案中,法官Jerome Frank首先阐述了现代宣传权——一种可转让的知识产权。自那以后,这项权利被视为保护个人“人格”的商业价值——这个拉丁语衍生的词,意思是演员的面具。在其他经常出现的批评中,公开权被指责缺乏连贯的理由,只允许对公众对人格的伤害进行经济补偿,并通过允许个人人格中的所有权来剥夺个人身份。为什么弗兰克法官会有动机在公众形象的货币价值上创造一种可转让的权利,而不是对植根于个人并受到隐私保护的情感、情感和尊严的精神伤害?弗兰克法官是美国法律现实主义运动的领军人物,以其独特而有争议的“对某些法律立场的精神分析”而闻名,其著作颇具影响力,包括《法律与现代思想》和《审判中的法院》。他的作品大量借鉴了西格蒙德·弗洛伊德和卡尔·荣格等精神分析思想家的思想,描述了无意识的愿望和幻想对法律行为者和法官决策过程的扭曲影响。对弗兰克法官来说,人格的公共和私人方面之间的精神分析相互作用支持了他对立法作为一种主观和不确定活动的现实主义解释。事实上,尽管弗兰克在《海兰》中几乎没有为阐明独立于隐私的人格权提供任何理由,但他在学术著作中对人格给予了极大的关注。这篇文章表明,正如弗兰克法官在考虑其精神分析法学时所意图的那样,现代公示权的目的可以通过精神分析的人格概念来理解——人格概念分为公共和私人两部分。在精神分析意义上,人格或“虚假自我”一词用于表示个人的公众形象,即一个人为了社会或经济利益而向他人呈现的形象,与他们的感受、情绪和对现实的主观解释形成鲜明对比,而现实的主观解释植根于他们的私人阴影或“真实自我”。然而,法律对这种二元人格隐喻的持续依赖似乎被误导了,尤其是随着技术、互联网和新媒体越来越模糊了公共和私人之间的传统区别。文章最后对主体间性人格理论进行了考察。主体间性可以为公共法提供一个有用的概念更新,因为它将自我和人格视为一种关系、语境和社会结构,而不是公私二分法。
{"title":"Unmasking the Right of Publicity","authors":"Dustin Marlan","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3300959","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3300959","url":null,"abstract":"In the landmark 1953 case of Haelan Laboratories v. Topps Chewing Gum, Judge Jerome Frank first articulated the modern right of publicity—a transferable intellectual property right. The right has since been seen to protect the commercial value of one’s “persona”—the Latin-derived word meaning the mask of an actor. Among other frequent criticisms, the right of publicity is accused of lacking a coherent justification, permitting only economic redress against public harms to the persona, and stripping away individual identity by allowing for a proprietary right in one’s personality. Why might Judge Frank have been motivated to fashion a transferable right in the monetary value of one’s public persona distinct from the psychic harm to feelings, emotions, and dignity rooted in the individual and protected under the rubric of privacy? \u0000 \u0000Judge Frank was a leading figure in the American legal realist movement known for his unique and controversial “psychoanalysis of certain legal positions” through influential books including Law and the Modern Mind and Courts on Trial. His work drew heavily on the ideas of psychoanalytic thinkers, like Sigmund Freud and Carl Jung, to describe the distorting effects of unconscious wishes and fantasies on the decision-making process of legal actors and judges. For Judge Frank, the psychoanalytic interplay between public and private aspects of the personality supported his realist interpretation of lawmaking as a subjective and indeterminate activity. Indeed, though Frank provided little rationale for articulating a personality right separate from privacy in Haelan, he had given a tremendous amount of attention to the personality in his scholarly works. \u0000 \u0000This Article suggests that the modern right of publicity’s aim, as perhaps intended by Judge Frank in considering his psychoanalytic jurisprudence, may be usefully understood through the psychoanalytic conception of the personality—one divided into public and private subparts. In the psychoanalytic sense, the term persona, or “false self,” is used to indicate the public face of an individual, i.e., the image one presents to others for social or economic advantage, as contrasted with their feelings, emotions and subjective interpretations of reality anchored in their private shadow, or “true self.” Yet, the law’s continued reliance on this dualistic metaphor of the personality appears misguided, particularly as technology, internet, and new media increasingly blur the traditional distinctions between public and private. The Article thus concludes by examining intersubjective personality theory. Intersubjectivity could provide publicity law with a useful conceptual update given its view of the self and personality as a relational, contextual, and social construct, rather than a public-private dichotomy.","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"71 1","pages":"419"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2019-04-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.3300959","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43039717","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
History, Tradition, the Supreme Court, and the First Amendment 历史,传统,最高法院和第一修正案
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2018-12-07 DOI: 10.4324/9781315053615-2
Erwin Chemerinsky *
{"title":"History, Tradition, the Supreme Court, and the First Amendment","authors":"Erwin Chemerinsky *","doi":"10.4324/9781315053615-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315053615-2","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2018-12-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70625342","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Explaining Choice-of-Entity Decisions by Silicon Valley Start-Ups 硅谷初创企业实体决策选择的解释
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2018-02-14 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3123793
Gregg D. Polsky
Perhaps the most fundamental role of a business tax advisor is to recommend the optimal entity choice for nascent business enterprises. Nevertheless, even in 2018, the choice-of-entity analysis remains highly muddled. Most tax practitioners across the United States consistently recommend flow-through entities, such as LLCs and S corporations, to their clients. In contrast, a discrete group of highly sophisticated tax professionals, those who advise start-ups in Silicon Valley and other hotbeds of start-up activity, prefer C corporations. Prior commentary has described and tried to explain this paradox without finding an adequate explanation. These commentators have noted a host of superficially plausible explanations, all of which they ultimately conclude are not wholly persuasive. The puzzle therefore remains. This article attempts to finally solve the puzzle by examining two factors that have been either vastly underappreciated or completely ignored in the existing literature. First, while previous commentators have briefly noted that flow-through structures are more complex and administratively burdensome, they did not fully appreciate the source, nature, and extent of these problems. In the unique start-up context, the complications of flow-through structures are exponentially more problematic, to the point where widespread adoption of flow-throughs is practically infeasible. Second, the literature has not appreciated the effect of perplexing, yet pervasive, tax asset valuation problems in the public company context. The conventional wisdom is that tax assets are ignored or severely undervalued in public company stock valuations. In theory, the most significant theoretical benefit of flow-through status for start-ups is that it can result in the creation of valuable tax assets upon exit. However, the conventional wisdom makes this moot when the exit is through an initial public offering or sale to a public company, which are the desired types of exits for Silicon Valley start-ups. Thus, the most significant benefit of using a flow-through (at least in theory) is eliminated because of the tax asset pricing problem. Accordingly, while the costs of flow-through structures are far larger than have been appreciated, the benefits of these structures are much smaller than they appear.
也许商业税务顾问最基本的角色是为新生商业企业推荐最佳实体选择。尽管如此,即使在2018年,实体分析的选择仍然非常混乱。美国各地的大多数税务从业者一直向客户推荐流通实体,如有限责任公司和S公司。相比之下,一群高度复杂的税务专业人士,那些为硅谷和其他创业活动温床的初创企业提供建议的人,更喜欢C公司。先前的评论描述并试图解释这一悖论,但没有找到充分的解释。这些评论家注意到了许多表面上看似合理的解释,他们最终得出的结论都不完全有说服力。因此,难题依然存在。本文试图通过考察现有文献中被严重低估或完全忽视的两个因素来最终解决这个难题。首先,尽管之前的评论员曾简要指出,流通结构更复杂,行政负担更重,但他们并没有充分认识到这些问题的来源、性质和程度。在独特的启动环境中,流通结构的复杂性问题成倍增加,以至于广泛采用流通实际上是不可行的。其次,文献没有意识到上市公司背景下令人困惑但普遍存在的税务资产评估问题的影响。传统观点认为,在上市公司股票估值中,税收资产被忽视或严重低估。理论上,流通状态对初创企业最重要的理论好处是,它可以在退出时创造有价值的税收资产。然而,传统观点认为,当退出是通过首次公开募股或出售给上市公司时,这是硅谷初创企业想要的退出类型。因此,由于税收资产定价问题,使用流通(至少在理论上)最显著的好处被消除了。因此,尽管流通结构的成本远大于人们所认识到的成本,但这些结构的益处远小于它们所表现出的益处。
{"title":"Explaining Choice-of-Entity Decisions by Silicon Valley Start-Ups","authors":"Gregg D. Polsky","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3123793","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3123793","url":null,"abstract":"Perhaps the most fundamental role of a business tax advisor is to recommend the optimal entity choice for nascent business enterprises. Nevertheless, even in 2018, the choice-of-entity analysis remains highly muddled. Most tax practitioners across the United States consistently recommend flow-through entities, such as LLCs and S corporations, to their clients. In contrast, a discrete group of highly sophisticated tax professionals, those who advise start-ups in Silicon Valley and other hotbeds of start-up activity, prefer C corporations. \u0000 \u0000Prior commentary has described and tried to explain this paradox without finding an adequate explanation. These commentators have noted a host of superficially plausible explanations, all of which they ultimately conclude are not wholly persuasive. The puzzle therefore remains. \u0000 \u0000This article attempts to finally solve the puzzle by examining two factors that have been either vastly underappreciated or completely ignored in the existing literature. First, while previous commentators have briefly noted that flow-through structures are more complex and administratively burdensome, they did not fully appreciate the source, nature, and extent of these problems. In the unique start-up context, the complications of flow-through structures are exponentially more problematic, to the point where widespread adoption of flow-throughs is practically infeasible. Second, the literature has not appreciated the effect of perplexing, yet pervasive, tax asset valuation problems in the public company context. The conventional wisdom is that tax assets are ignored or severely undervalued in public company stock valuations. In theory, the most significant theoretical benefit of flow-through status for start-ups is that it can result in the creation of valuable tax assets upon exit. However, the conventional wisdom makes this moot when the exit is through an initial public offering or sale to a public company, which are the desired types of exits for Silicon Valley start-ups. Thus, the most significant benefit of using a flow-through (at least in theory) is eliminated because of the tax asset pricing problem. Accordingly, while the costs of flow-through structures are far larger than have been appreciated, the benefits of these structures are much smaller than they appear.","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"70 1","pages":"409"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2018-02-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47126263","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Are U.S. Public Lands Unconstitutional 美国公共土地是否违宪
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2018-02-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3123176
John D. Leshy
Arguments are sometimes made most recently in a paper commissioned by the State of Utah, and by a lawyer for a defendant facing charges for the armed takeover of a National Wildlife Refuge in Oregon in 2016 that U.S. public lands are unconstitutional. This article disputes that position. It digs deeply into the history of the public lands, going back to the very founding of the nation. It seeks to show that the arguments for unconstitutionality reflect an incomplete, defective understanding of U.S. legal and political history; an extremely selective, skewed reading of numerous Supreme Court decisions and federal statutes; a misleading assertion that states have very limited governing authority over activities taking place on U.S. public lands; and even a misuse of the dictionary. At bottom, the arguments rest on the premise that the U.S. Supreme Court should use the U.S. Constitution to determine how much if any land the U.S. may own in any state. For the Court to assume that responsibility would be a breathtaking departure from more than 225 years of practice during which Congress has made that determination through the political process, and from a century and a half of Supreme Court precedent deferring to Congress. It would also be contrary to the Court’s often expressed reluctance to revisit settled public land law, upon which so many property transactions depend.
最近,犹他州委托的一篇论文,以及因2016年武装接管俄勒冈州国家野生动物保护区而面临指控的被告的律师,有时会提出美国公共土地违宪的论点。这篇文章对这一立场提出异议。它深入挖掘了公共土地的历史,可以追溯到建国之初。它试图表明,违宪的论点反映了对美国法律和政治历史的不完整、有缺陷的理解;对许多最高法院裁决和联邦法规的解读极为选择性和歪曲;一种误导性的断言,即各州对在美国公共土地上进行的活动的管理权限非常有限;甚至是对字典的误用。归根结底,争论的前提是,美国最高法院应该利用美国宪法来确定美国在任何州可以拥有多少土地。最高法院承担这一责任,将与225多年来国会通过政治程序做出这一决定的做法,以及一个半世纪以来最高法院服从国会的先例,大相径庭。这也违背了法院经常表示不愿重新审视已确定的公共土地法,因为许多财产交易都依赖于该法。
{"title":"Are U.S. Public Lands Unconstitutional","authors":"John D. Leshy","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3123176","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3123176","url":null,"abstract":"Arguments are sometimes made most recently in a paper commissioned by the State of Utah, and by a lawyer for a defendant facing charges for the armed takeover of a National Wildlife Refuge in Oregon in 2016 that U.S. public lands are unconstitutional. This article disputes that position. It digs deeply into the history of the public lands, going back to the very founding of the nation. It seeks to show that the arguments for unconstitutionality reflect an incomplete, defective understanding of U.S. legal and political history; an extremely selective, skewed reading of numerous Supreme Court decisions and federal statutes; a misleading assertion that states have very limited governing authority over activities taking place on U.S. public lands; and even a misuse of the dictionary. At bottom, the arguments rest on the premise that the U.S. Supreme Court should use the U.S. Constitution to determine how much if any land the U.S. may own in any state. For the Court to assume that responsibility would be a breathtaking departure from more than 225 years of practice during which Congress has made that determination through the political process, and from a century and a half of Supreme Court precedent deferring to Congress. It would also be contrary to the Court’s often expressed reluctance to revisit settled public land law, upon which so many property transactions depend.","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"69 1","pages":"499"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2018-02-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45787287","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Gerrymandering and Conceit: The Supreme Court's Conflict With Itself 选区划分不公与自负:最高法院与自身的冲突
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2018-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2989985
McKay Cunningham
In November 2016, a federal court struck as unconstitutional Wisconsin’s redistricting map under both the First Amendment and the Equal Protection Clause. The court’s decision in Whitford v. Gill marks the first time a federal court invalidated a redistricting map as unconstitutional for partisan gerrymandering in over thirty years. Wisconsin has appealed the decision to the United States Supreme Court, which recently granted review. The Supreme Court has long held that extreme partisan gerrymandering violates equal protection but has simultaneously refused to determine the merits of gerrymandering disputes, instead labeling them as non-justiciable political questions. In particular, the Court has maintained that no manageable standard yet exists by which the Court could implement the promise of equal protection to partisan redistricting. This Article analyzes the manageable standard requirement, revealing the Court’s failure to define the term and that the Court has applied the manageability requirement haphazardly. Scores of court-made standards either over- or under-enforce the constitutional norm they purport to implement. Why is “fairness” a workable standard in one context but not another? How are standards that measure one’s shocked conscious, or weigh the totality of the circumstances judicially manageable? Importantly, a common thread connects the Court’s use of the manageability requirement to its insecurity in exercising judicial review, indicating that the Court often applies the manageability requirement when particularly insecure in exercising the judicial function. Recast in this light, the question of Court engagement in gerrymandering disputes turns on the propriety of Court intervention to address artificial obstacles that disrupt democratic functionality. The Court should no longer hide behind the manageability barrier because court intervention to ensure democracy’s proper functioning was (1) anticipated by the Framers, (2) memorialized in the Constitution’s form and structure, and (3) exercised by the Court without loss of judicial legitimacy in analogous contexts. This Article posits that judicial intervention to unblock the avenues of political change is one of the Court’s central responsibilities, that in similar contexts the Court has recognized as much, and that it should do so again in Whitford.
2016年11月,一家联邦法院根据《第一修正案》和平等保护条款,裁定威斯康星州的选区重划地图违宪。法院在惠特福德诉吉尔案中的裁决标志着30多年来,联邦法院首次以党派不公正划分选区为由,宣布选区重划地图违宪。威斯康星州已向美国最高法院提起上诉,最高法院最近批准了复审。最高法院长期以来一直认为,极端的党派不公正划分选区违反了平等保护,但同时拒绝确定不公正划分选区争议的是非对错,而是将其标记为不可审理的政治问题。法院特别认为,目前还没有可管理的标准,法院可以据此执行对党派重新划分提供平等保护的承诺。本文通过对可管理标准要求的分析,揭示了法院对可管理标准要求的定义缺失,以及法院对可管理标准要求的随意适用。许多法院制定的标准对其声称要执行的宪法规范要么执行过度,要么执行不足。为什么“公平”在一种情况下是可行的标准,而在另一种情况下却不是?衡量一个人的震惊意识的标准,或者衡量整个情况的标准,在司法上是如何管理的?重要的是,一条共同的线索将法院使用可管理性要求与其行使司法审查时的不安全感联系起来,这表明法院在行使司法职能时特别不安全时往往适用可管理性要求。从这个角度重新考虑,法院参与不公正划分选区争议的问题就变成了法院干预的适当性,以解决破坏民主功能的人为障碍。法院不应再躲在可管理性障碍后面,因为法院为确保民主的正常运作而进行的干预是(1)制宪者所期望的,(2)在宪法的形式和结构中得到了纪念,(3)在类似的情况下由法院行使而不会失去司法合法性。这条规定,司法干预以畅通政治变革的道路是法院的中心责任之一,在类似的情况下,法院已经认识到这一点,它应该在惠特福德案中再次这样做。
{"title":"Gerrymandering and Conceit: The Supreme Court's Conflict With Itself","authors":"McKay Cunningham","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2989985","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2989985","url":null,"abstract":"In November 2016, a federal court struck as unconstitutional Wisconsin’s redistricting map under both the First Amendment and the Equal Protection Clause. The court’s decision in Whitford v. Gill marks the first time a federal court invalidated a redistricting map as unconstitutional for partisan gerrymandering in over thirty years. Wisconsin has appealed the decision to the United States Supreme Court, which recently granted review. The Supreme Court has long held that extreme partisan gerrymandering violates equal protection but has simultaneously refused to determine the merits of gerrymandering disputes, instead labeling them as non-justiciable political questions. In particular, the Court has maintained that no manageable standard yet exists by which the Court could implement the promise of equal protection to partisan redistricting. This Article analyzes the manageable standard requirement, revealing the Court’s failure to define the term and that the Court has applied the manageability requirement haphazardly. Scores of court-made standards either over- or under-enforce the constitutional norm they purport to implement. Why is “fairness” a workable standard in one context but not another? How are standards that measure one’s shocked conscious, or weigh the totality of the circumstances judicially manageable? Importantly, a common thread connects the Court’s use of the manageability requirement to its insecurity in exercising judicial review, indicating that the Court often applies the manageability requirement when particularly insecure in exercising the judicial function. Recast in this light, the question of Court engagement in gerrymandering disputes turns on the propriety of Court intervention to address artificial obstacles that disrupt democratic functionality. The Court should no longer hide behind the manageability barrier because court intervention to ensure democracy’s proper functioning was (1) anticipated by the Framers, (2) memorialized in the Constitution’s form and structure, and (3) exercised by the Court without loss of judicial legitimacy in analogous contexts. This Article posits that judicial intervention to unblock the avenues of political change is one of the Court’s central responsibilities, that in similar contexts the Court has recognized as much, and that it should do so again in Whitford.","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"69 1","pages":"1509"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2018-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68462160","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
'Innocence' and the Guilty Mind “纯真”与罪恶心理
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2017-08-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3019450
Stephen F. Smith
For decades, the “guilty mind” requirement in federal criminal law has been understood as precluding punishment for “morally blameless” (or “innocent”) conduct, thereby ensuring that only offenders with adequate notice of the wrongfulness of their conduct face conviction. The Supreme Court’s recent decision in Elonis v. United States portends a significant, and novel, shift in mens rea doctrine by treating the potential for disproportionately severe punishment as an independent justification for heightened mens rea requirements. This long-overdue doctrinal move makes perfect sense because punishment without culpability and excessive punishment involve the same objectionable feature: the imposition of morally undeserved punishment. This Article uses Elonis as a vehicle for reexamining the effectiveness of current mens rea doctrine. Even after Elonis, mens rea doctrine remains hobbled by several methodological flaws which prevent it from making moral culpability a necessary precondition for punishment. These flaws, I argue, are traceable to the doctrine’s simultaneous embrace of two irreconcilable views of the separation of powers in criminal law. The project of reading implied mens rea requirements into statutes and fleshing out incomplete legislative crime definitions necessarily assumes that courts have a lawmaking role on par with Congress. The mens rea selection methodology, however, reflects standard faithful-agent textualism. This turns out to be the doctrine’s Achilles heel because the risk of morally undeserved punishment stems primarily from poor legislative crime definition. To be truly effective, mens rea doctrine must operate outside the statutory definition of the offense. All mens rea options not clearly foreclosed by Congress -- even knowledge of criminality -- must be available wherever needed to prevent morally undeserved punishment. Until this occurs, mens rea doctrine will continue to default on its promise of preventing conviction for morally blameless conduct, not to mention the broader promise, suggested both by Elonis and criminal law tradition and theory, of precluding disproportionately severe punishment.
几十年来,联邦刑法中的“有罪”要求一直被理解为排除对“道德上无可指责”(或“无辜”)行为的惩罚,从而确保只有充分了解其行为不法性的罪犯才会面临定罪。最高法院最近在Elonis诉United States一案中的裁决预示着犯罪意图学说的重大而新颖的转变,它将过度严厉惩罚的可能性视为提高犯罪意图要求的独立理由。这一早就应该采取的理论行动是完全合理的,因为没有罪责的惩罚和过度惩罚都涉及同样令人反感的特征:施加道德上不应有的惩罚。这篇文章使用埃隆尼斯作为一个工具,重新审视现行犯罪意图学说的有效性。即使在埃洛尼斯之后,犯罪意图学说仍然受到几个方法论缺陷的阻碍,这些缺陷阻碍了它将道德罪责作为惩罚的必要前提。我认为,这些缺陷可以追溯到该学说同时接受了刑法中两种不可调和的分权观点。将隐含的犯罪意图要求解读为法规并充实不完整的立法犯罪定义的项目必然假设法院具有与国会同等的立法作用。然而,犯罪意图选择方法论反映了标准的忠实代理人文本主义。事实证明,这是该学说的致命弱点,因为道德上不应有惩罚的风险主要源于糟糕的立法犯罪定义。为了真正有效,犯罪意图学说必须在犯罪的法定定义之外运作。所有未被国会明确排除的犯罪意图选择——甚至是犯罪知识——都必须在任何需要的地方提供,以防止道德上不应有的惩罚。在这种情况发生之前,犯罪意图学说将继续违背其防止对道德上无可指责的行为定罪的承诺,更不用说埃隆尼斯和刑法传统和理论提出的更广泛的承诺,即排除不成比例的严厉惩罚。
{"title":"'Innocence' and the Guilty Mind","authors":"Stephen F. Smith","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3019450","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3019450","url":null,"abstract":"For decades, the “guilty mind” requirement in federal criminal law has been understood as precluding punishment for “morally blameless” (or “innocent”) conduct, thereby ensuring that only offenders with adequate notice of the wrongfulness of their conduct face conviction. The Supreme Court’s recent decision in Elonis v. United States portends a significant, and novel, shift in mens rea doctrine by treating the potential for disproportionately severe punishment as an independent justification for heightened mens rea requirements. This long-overdue doctrinal move makes perfect sense because punishment without culpability and excessive punishment involve the same objectionable feature: the imposition of morally undeserved punishment. This Article uses Elonis as a vehicle for reexamining the effectiveness of current mens rea doctrine. Even after Elonis, mens rea doctrine remains hobbled by several methodological flaws which prevent it from making moral culpability a necessary precondition for punishment. These flaws, I argue, are traceable to the doctrine’s simultaneous embrace of two irreconcilable views of the separation of powers in criminal law. The project of reading implied mens rea requirements into statutes and fleshing out incomplete legislative crime definitions necessarily assumes that courts have a lawmaking role on par with Congress. The mens rea selection methodology, however, reflects standard faithful-agent textualism. This turns out to be the doctrine’s Achilles heel because the risk of morally undeserved punishment stems primarily from poor legislative crime definition. To be truly effective, mens rea doctrine must operate outside the statutory definition of the offense. All mens rea options not clearly foreclosed by Congress -- even knowledge of criminality -- must be available wherever needed to prevent morally undeserved punishment. Until this occurs, mens rea doctrine will continue to default on its promise of preventing conviction for morally blameless conduct, not to mention the broader promise, suggested both by Elonis and criminal law tradition and theory, of precluding disproportionately severe punishment.","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"69 1","pages":"1609"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2017-08-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.3019450","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49614376","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Sexual Autonomy and the Constitutional Right to Privacy: A Case Study in Human Rights and the Unwritten Constitution 性自主与宪法隐私权——以人权与未成文宪法为例
IF 0.5 4区 社会学 Q2 LAW Pub Date : 2017-05-15 DOI: 10.4324/9781315243375-2
D. A. Richards
{"title":"Sexual Autonomy and the Constitutional Right to Privacy: A Case Study in Human Rights and the Unwritten Constitution","authors":"D. A. Richards","doi":"10.4324/9781315243375-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315243375-2","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46736,"journal":{"name":"Hastings Law Journal","volume":"30 1","pages":"71-132"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2017-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46098912","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 14
期刊
Hastings Law Journal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1